Draft for the book Philosophical Semantics, to be published
by CSP in 2017.
Appendix to Chapter 2
MODAL ILUSIONS:
AGAINST TRANSEPISTEMIC METAPHYSICAL IDENTITIES
Die Probleme, die durch ein Mißdeuten unserer Sprachformen entstehen,
haben den Charakter der Tiefe. Es sind tiefe Beunruhigungen; sie wurzeln so
tief in uns wie die Formen unserer Sprache, und ihre Bedeutung ist so groß wie
die Wichtigkeit unserer Sprache.
[The problems arising through a
misinterpretation of our forms of language have the character of depth. They
are deep disquietudes; their roots are as deep in us as the forms of our
language and their significance is as great as the importance of our language.]
Wittgenstein
Although
exceedingly original and challenging, Saul Kripke’s philosophical application
of modal logic to the problems of reference seems to me to be burdened by a
disturbing web of confusion. Since many disagree, I will try to justify myself
through a critical discussion of his article ‘Identity and Necessity’ (Kripke
1971), which precedes the more developed views defended in his book Naming
and Necessity (Kripke 1980),
since that short article takes some fundamental ideas direct from the oven.
Paragraphs summarising Kripke’s article are printed in italics in order to be
distinguished from paragraphs containing my own comments. To my comments on
this article, in the addendum I will make some short criticisms to central
ideas not only from Kripke, but also from Hilary Putnam, Gareth Evans, David
Kaplan, Tyler Burge and John Perry, as part of my project of debunking the
metaphysics of meaning.
Kripke begins
by considering the modal argument for the necessity of statements of identity.
Where □ is the
operator of necessity, which here will be seen as de re
(regardless of the mode of linguistic designation), we can consider that, given
the principle of indiscernibility of identicals, according to which ‘(x) (y)
((x = y) → (Fx → Fy))’, and given the principle of identity, according to which
‘(x) □(x = x)’, we
can conclude that if the property F is to be necessarily applied to x, then y
must also have this property, i.e. it is necessary that y equals x; in symbolic
notation, ‘(x) (y) (x = y) → (□(x = x) → □(x
= y))’, namely: ‘(x) (y) (x = y) → □(x = y)’.
This apparently inconsequential formal
result leads Kripke to the bold conclusion that, as long as there are
theoretical (essential) identities, identities between names are necessary. We
know that by universal instantiation ‘□(x = y) → □ (a
= b)’. That is, if a
and b are real names and a = b
is a true identity, then this identity is necessarily true. This would concern
identities like ‘Hesperus is (the same as) Phosphorus’ and ‘Cicero is (the same
as) Tulius’: they must be necessary. Further, if F and G are theoretical
predicates, defined as essential designators of properties, if they form
a true theoretical identity of the form (x) (Fx = Gx), then this identity is
also necessarily true. That is why identities like ‘Heat is molecular motion’
and ‘A state of mind is a physical state’, if true, are necessary.
Kripke
recognises that identities between names and between theoretical identities
have generally been considered contingent; but he presents the reasons for it.
Consider the statement ‘Hesperus is Phosphorus’. Since Hesperus is Venus seen
at dusk (evening star), and Phosphorus is Venus seen at dawn (morning star), it
was an important astronomical discovery that they are actually the same planet,
as Frege has noted. Therefore, this seems not to be a necessary, but
rather a contingent empirical truth. The same applies to theoretical
identities such as ‘Heat is molecular motion’. This identity was a discovery of
science and could be false, because if caloric theory (the theory that heat
consists of a self-repellent fluid called caloric) were correct, heat would not be molecular
motion. This seems to be a clearly contingent statement, since it could be
otherwise.
Kripke’s thesis, however, is that contrary
to the appearances, all these identities, despite having been learned a
posteriori, are necessary, even if they do not seem to be. To reinforce his thesis
he introduces an important distinction between the rigid designator, here defined as a
term that refers to the same object in all possible worlds in which this object
exists or would exist, and the non-rigid or accidental designator, which can refer to different objects in
distinct possible worlds. Proper names and terms of natural species, at
least, are rigid designators, while definite descriptions are accidental
designators. Hence, if we have an identity in which the identity symbol is
flanked by proper names, this identity is necessarily true if true at all,
considering that proper names cannot change their reference in different
possible worlds.
It seems clear
that a mathematical term can be seen as a rigid designator, insofar as it does
not depend on how the world is; but is really impossible for all our empirical
proper names not be rigid designators? In the attempt to show that sometimes they
could be accidental designators, we can imagine the following. Suppose that it
were discovered that after the early childhood of G. W. Bush an
extra-terrestrial creature possessed his body, and since then has lived in it
and maintained his identity, becoming in this way the president of the United
States and performing all actions attributed to him. Would not in this case the
proper name ‘G. W. Bush’ be used to refer to this extra-terrestrial creature
instead of the son of Barbara and George Bush, being in this way an accidental
designator?
The truth is that the idea that the proper
name is a rigid designator would resist to this objection. According to
Kripke’s views, the reference of a proper name is determined by an act of
baptism, so that the true W. G. Bush, as the holder of the rigid designator ‘W.
G. Bush’, would have since long disappeared. On the other hand, a homonymous
being, the embodied extraterrestrial being, whose true name is Gkw9, would have
had in some remote day a baptism and the name W. G. Bush, as a nickname of
Gkw9, would apply to this same extraterrestrial being in each possible world
where it would exist, being therefore also a rigid designator.
Applying my own theory of proper names
summarized in the appendix of chapter 1, the results would be the similar.
According to this theory, the referent of a proper name is the object that
satisfies the identifying rule for the application of the proper name. What
this identifying rule requires is a sufficient and better than any other
satisfaction of the inclusive disjunction of the fundamental description-rules,
which are the localizing and the characterizing rules. For the adult W. G. Bush
(as Gkw9), for instance, the localizing description includes his
spatio-temporal career in the planet Omega before his embodiment and on the
Earth and after its Bush-embodiment in Washington… On the other hand the
characterizing description would include his main deeds, as his election as the
43tr president from USA, the wars in Iraq and Afghanistan, and the person who
earlier in the planet Omega has make the main deeds of Gkw9... In every possible
world were the identifying rule is satisfied, W. G. Bush (as Gkw9) would exist.
Hence, the identifying rule for the name is a rigid designator for us too.
Something of the kind could be easily established for the child named W. G.
Bush – the true Bush – making this name also a rigid designator.
Something different, however, is the idea
that the concept of rigid designator has the consequences that Kripke expected
as a way to ensure existence of de re metaphysical necessities of
identities between our usual proper names and between terms of natural species.
Kripke believes to have warranted the
necessity of this identity by having discovered some radical difference of
nature between proper names, on the one hand, and definite descriptions, on the
other. What his words suggest is that a proper name would reach its reference
without intermediaries by means of a direct (in my view purely magic) relation
instituted in the act of baptism. For him this does not really depend on any
property of the object, allowing then the production of external causal chains
that in the end would reach each speaker of the name who really refers to its
bearer.[1]
A definite description, on the other hand, is only an accidental designator: it
would refer to different objects in different possible worlds, probably because
it has what Stuart Mill called ‘connotation’, which is the description’s
implication of an attribute that the object may have (1881, I, Ch. 2). Using
Kripke’s example, this would be the case of the definite description ‘the
inventor of the bifocals’, which refers to Benjamin Franklin in our world, but
that could refer to any other person and even to no person in a different
possible world.
I think that this strange dichotomy,
suggesting a mysterious difference in the nature of reference is completely
dispensable if we apply my own neo-descriptivist theory of proper names, since
this theory gives a sufficiently reasonable explanation for the rigidity of
proper names versus the accidental character of definite descriptions (see appendix
of chapter 1, sec. 7, 8). Partially because of this I agree with the idea that
the necessity of the rigid designator is always de dicto, supporting John Searle’s view according to which the so-called
de re beliefs are only a sub-class
of the de dicto beliefs and there is
no irreducible de re belief. [2]
Clearly, this rejection of irreducible de
re beliefs leads to the rejection of the kind of metaphysical de re necessity proposed by Kripke.
The neo-descriptivism I propose makes a
proper name a rigid designator because any combination of descriptions that
allows its reference in accordance with its identifying rule must be satisfied
in any world in which the proper name has a bearer, simply because the
identifying rule defines what its bearer
can be. However, two different proper names of the same object can have
different identifying rules, identifying their bearer under different guises,
under different ways of presentation, simply because they emphasize different
perspectives in which different descriptions or groups of descriptions are
satisfied. In this case, even being rigid designators, we cannot without
further information know that they are referring to the same object, and it may
be an empirical matter to decide if two different rigid designators are
referring to the same object or to two different objects. We still do not know
whether the identifying rules of two names are part of a common identifying
rule, being the identity sentence at this first stage contingent a posteriori. This state of affairs endures until after
empirical experience we establish by convention
according to which the different ways of presentation, the different
identifying rules, are constituents of the same rigid designator, building in
this way a more complex identifying rule that includes both, each of them
emphazising a different perspective. In this case, the identity will be indeed necessary a priori! In no moment of this
process, however, we need to resort to a Kripkian necessary a posteriori identity.
Only to illustrate the point: there is a way
to express Frege’s insight according to which ‘Afla = Ateb’, in which Afla is
the same mountain as Ateb, though explored from a different complementary
perspective, what gives to these names different but complementary senses or
modes of presentation. Since for Frege references are dependent on senses, the
proper names ‘Afla’ and ‘Ateb’ are from the beginning de dicto rigid
designators and not metaphysically de
re rigid designators. However, some
day the explorers can ask themselves whether Afla is Ateb. At first, they see
this identification as a contingent matter. After they discover that they are
indeed referring to the same mountain, the more complete identity sentence
turns to be seem as having the implicit form ‘Afla [-Ateb] = Ateb [-Afla]’,
that is: Afla and Ateb express rules identifying numerically the same object
simply because they were blended in the formation of one and the same
identifying rule, applicable to both sides of the same mountain under different
guises.
Kripke also
considers the problem of apriority. A priori truths are those that we can know
without appealing to experience. Many consider the necessary and the a priori to be equivalent. However, the
concept of necessity is for him metaphysical – about
how the world must be – while
the concept of a priori is epistemic – about how we know
the world. Kripke thinks that the two classes are not equivalent. Consider, he
writes, Goldbach’s conjecture, which states that any natural number above two
is the sum of two primes. It may be a necessary truth without the possibility
of our knowing it a priori. In this
case it would have metaphysical necessity.
The suggestion
that necessity is metaphysical while apriority is epistemological is highly
questionable. This distinction would be justified only if there were
metaphysical de re necessities, as Kripke intends, since a de dicto necessity would follow from a more
trivial epistemologically established apriority, even if well grounded. Moreover,
the existence of metaphysical de re necessities
in the supposed sense seems to be something that escapes our cognitive
faculties, since our empirical knowledge is inherently fallible, something that has been insistently repeated by
philosophers of science from C. S. Peirce (1991, Ch. 7) to Karl Popper (1959).
All that we can do is to postulate
empirical necessities by accepting the
most well-entrenched[3] and strongly inductively grounded
regularities as natural laws (Tugendhat 1983; Mackie 1974). To really know
if there is a necessity of a natural law beyond this well-grounded postulation
(pace Armstrong), a metaphysical
necessity, would require absolute knowledge – something that our epistemic fallibility
makes impossible. Therefore, the necessities of natural laws are nothing but a
result of a well-grounded decision to treat
them as necessities. They are necessities in a weaker sense of the word.
However, once we postulate them as natural laws, we have the right to treat
them as basic rules of our conceptual system. We view them as necessary as long
as we accept the system.
Thus, if our analysis of necessity is
correct, there seems to be at least two kinds of necessity, both of them with
epistemic import:
(i)
the logical and
conventional necessities that we find in formal sciences (like ‘~(A &
~A)) and in definitional sentences (like ‘brothers are persons with the same
parents’), or that can be translated to the last ones;
(ii)
the empirical
necessity, which is reached a posteriori, but afterwards can be simply postulated as necessary, as far as it is
useful to work with them in this way.
Wittgenstein
would classify empirical necessities as ‘grammatical rules’ – rules grounding a
useful linguistic practice (Wittgenstein 1984a). Here is his suggestion, in
which we read the word ‘rule’ involving a priori propositions:
Every
empirical proposition can serve as a rule
if it is fixed as the unmovable part of a mechanism, in such a way that the
entire representation revolves around it, making it part of a system of
coordinates independent of the facts. (Wittgenstein 1984e, part VII: 437)[4]
As for
Goldbach’s conjecture, the fact that it may be a necessary truth without our
being aware of it does not mean that its necessity is not a priori or has some
indefinite status. It is not
impossible that someone finds a proof of this conjecture, giving to it finally
the status of a theorem with a
priori necessity.
Moreover, it is because the mathematicians hold as a heuristic rule that it is
possible to reach such an a priory knowledge that they insist in searching for
a proof; otherwise they would not sustain the conjecture.
Maybe the
most stricking example of a necessary a posteriori statement introduced by
Kripke is that of the wooden table in front of him. It starts with the
question: could it have consisted since the beginning of its existence of ice
from the Thames? Certainly not: It would be a different object. Thus, the
statement ‘This table, if it exists, cannot be made of ice,’ is a necessary
truth known a posteriori. Tables, he says, are usually not made of ice. This
table seems to be made of wood, and it is not cold. Hence, it is probably not
made of ice. Of course, this could be a delusion. It could actually be made of
ice. But that’s not the point, writes Kripke. The point is that given the fact that the table is not made
of ice, but of wood, one cannot imagine that it could be made of ice. Given
the fact that it is not made of ice, he concludes, it is necessary
that it is not made of ice. In other words: being P = ‘This table is not made of ice’ we know a priori the
truth of ‘If P then □P’.
Moreover, he says, we know from empirical research that P is true... Combining
these two statements, he constructs the following argument applying a modus ponens:
(A)
1
P → □P
2
P
3
□P
It is
therefore necessary that the table is not made of ice, although this is only
known a posteriori, by empirical research. The statement, ‘This table is not made of ice’ is necessary
a posteriori!
Clearly, the
covert mistake in Kripke’s argument concerns the epistemological status of P in the second premise. In
this premise, the truth of P is affirmed in disregard to the fact (earlier
confusionist way referred to by Kripke) that P, as any empirical statement, can
only be known as true by inevitably fallible epistemic subjects. However, if
it is so P can in principle be false. In order to show this clearly, we first
understand a statement as practically
certain when it is extremely likely
to be true, that is, when we can assign to its truth a probability very near to
1. Considering this, we can rather say that the statement P of the second
premise should be more precisely written as (2’): ‘It is practically certain
that P (that this table isn’t made of ice)’. Indeed, (2’) must be correct
because only God – the infallible and omniscient epistemic subject – could know
with absolute certainty the
truth of the statement P (that is, would be able to assign it the probability
1). God could know for sure the factual existence of P, giving in this way to
the affirmation of P a truly metaphysically de re necessity.
Unfortunately, we cannot appeal to God in this matter. Consequently, all that
we can know is that P is practically certain in the already pointed
sense of being, under the assumption of all our present body of information,
extremely likely to be true. This must be so, since our
empirical knowledge is never absolute[5]
(it is always possible, for instance, that for some reason I believe I am
standing before a hard wooden table, as much as all the beholders, although it
is actually made of ice[6]).
Assuming this, consider now the first
premise. The same cannot be said of it, since it is a conditional. It is fully
acceptable that given the fact that P
– or, more precisely, if the fact that P
is really given – then P follows by
necessity. Thus, what P → □P
says is (1) ‘If it is really the case
that P, then it is necessary that P,’ and this, I concede, is a logical truth. However,
what the antecedent requires is that P implies □P only under the assumption that the truth of P is
absolutely certain, for instance, knowable by God’s omniscience. Hence, the
most complete analysis of premise (1) would be (1’): ‘If it is absolutely
certain that P is the case (if P has the probability 1), then it is necessary
that P’. Surely, premise (1) could not be analysed as (1’’) ‘If it is
practically certain that P is the case (that is, if P has a probability near to
1), then P is necessary’, since the mere probability of P, no matter how high,
if less than 1, would not warrant the necessity of P. Once we admit the changes
of premise (1) to (1’) and (2) to (2’), Kripke’s argument can be made completely
explicit as saying:
B
1’. If it is absolutely certain that P, then it is
necessary that P.
2’. It is practically certain that P.
3’. It is necessary that P.
Obviously, the
argument (B) is non-valid, since the modus
ponens cannot be applied to (1’) and (2’) in order to give us (3’). The
reason is that the antecedent of (1’) does not say precisely the same thing as
(2’), what makes the argument equivocal, hence fallacious. We conclude that
under a better scrutiny Kripke’s argument does nothing to convince us that we
can know that the utterance ‘This table is not made of ice’ is a metaphysically
necessary a posteriori truth.
Now, the reason for Kripke’s misleading view
that the conclusion of his own argument must be necessary a posteriori becomes clear. He
ignores the fine semantic differences made explicit by means of the argument
(B), and by doing this he jumps to a conclusion that unduly joins the necessity
of the first premise of his argument with the aposteriority of its second
premise, building what he calls a necessary a posteriori truth in the
conclusion 3.
Kripke comes
then to the analysis of identities between proper names such as ‘Hesperus is Phosphorus’
and ‘Cicero is Tulio.’ These are empirical identities, generally considered
contingent. For Kripke they are identities between rigid designators, which
make them necessary, since in the most diverse possible worlds these names will
refer to the same object, a situation not possible where Hesperus isn’t
Phosphorus or Cicero isn’t Tulio. We could, he says, have identified Hesperus
and Phosphorus with two different celestial bodies, but in this case the
sentence ‘Hesperus is Phosphorus’ would have a different meaning. This would be
the case, for example, if Martians had once populated the Earth and had
identified Hesperus with Venus and Phosphorus with Mars... The same is true
with the identity ‘Cicero is Tulio.’ According to him it seems that this statement
is contingent because sometimes we learn these names with the help of definite
descriptions, like ‘the greatest Roman orator,’ which are accidental
designators, thinking that we identify the object through properties, when in
fact such names are not synonymous with descriptions, but rather with rigid
designators.
One could
produce here an argument parallel to the argument applied by Kripke to the
indexical case of the table made of wood in the attempt to demonstrate the
metaphysical necessity that Hesperus is the same as Phosphorus, since these
names are rigid designators that must pick out necessarily the same object in
any possible world. Calling Hesperus h
and Phosphorus p we can build up the
following Kripkian argument:
(h = p) → □ (h = p)
h = p
□ (h = p)
However, here
too the modus ponens does not apply because although the first
premise is true, the second premise would only conjoin with the first one
assuring us the conclusion ‘□ (h
= p)’ if it were able to give
us an absolute assurance of the truth of ‘h = p’. But this is not the case. In
order to get the absolute assurance that ‘h = p’ that enables us to reach the
conclusion this truth must be discovered, not by inevitably fallible human epistemic
subjects, but again only by God, the omniscient and infallible epistemic
subject. Because of this, ‘h = p’ can here only be seen as an empirically
achieved fallible conclusion, saying that it is practicaly certain (extremely
probable) that ‘h = p’, which is still not the same as its absolute certainty.
The following formulation demonstrates again the hidden failure of the
argument:
If it is absolutely certain (with
probability 1) that h = p,
then □ (h = p).
It is practically certain (with probability near to 1) that h = p.
□ (h = p)
Since the
absolute certainty required by the identity of the second premise with the
antecedent of the first is not available, the equivocity of the argument is
clear. We cannot use the modus ponens to derive the a posteriori
necessity of h = p. The statement ‘Hesperus is Phosphorus’ is in
this interpretation contingent a posteriori. It cannot be metaphysically
necessary because being this identity only highly probable it remains always
possible that Hesperus is not Phosphorus: it does not belong to these two
identifying rules that they become necessarily unified into a same convention.
For instance: although extremely unlikely, it is logically possible that the
gods have produced a great illusion of knowledge in the human minds, and that
the planets are nothing more than a swarm of fireflies that every night
assemble to decorate the celestial Vault. In this case, Hesperus would have a
different location than Phosphorus when seen by the naked eye, but it would
look identical to Phosphorus when viewed through a telescope – not because it
is the same planet or a planet at all, but as a result of an unknown kind of
witchery.
The second example given by Kripke is very
different and it would be misleading to confuse it with the example above. It
concerns the utterance ‘Cicero is Tulio.’ Assuming my neo-descriptivist theory
of proper names, the localizing description for his identification is (shortly)
‘Born in Greece in 3.1.106 BC and died in Rom 7.12.43 BC’, while the
characterizing description is (shortly) ‘the greatest Roman orator, a
politician, jurist and philosopher.’ His whole name was ‘Marcus Tullius
Cicero.’ Since the proper name does not belong to the fundamental descriptions,
but to the auxiliary ones (he could receive another name in a different
possible world), Kripke is only relying on the fact that not all speakers know
that Cicero and Tulio are parts of a same proper name as a point of convention
in our actual world, assuming that they know who is the bearer of the
fundamental descriptions implied by each part of the whole name.
As a consequence the question is a trivial
one, namely, whether the speaker knows an auxiliary convention. Hence, the
right answer is that ‘Tulio is Cicero’ is necessary
a priori as a linguistic definition, since the convention that the whole
name is ‘Marcus Tullius Cicero’ is something a priori, as much as the
convention that a triangle is a trilateral figure. Moreover, to say that the
statement ‘Cicero is Tulio’ is a posteriori would be to confuse its belonging
to a definition in our actual world – which is a question of being informed
about conventions – with the possible names that the same reference could have
received in different counterfactual situations. Indeed, it is possible that
Cicero would not have been also called Tullius, but Tittus, making ‘Cicero is
Tulio’ false. However, this is as trivial as to say that in a different
possible world one could give a different name for the word ‘triangle’.
The next of
Kripke’s examples concerns the identity between kinds of things, as in the already discussed statement ‘Heat
is molecular movement.’ Many think that this expresses an a posteriori
truth, because it is the result of empirical scientific research. But for
Kripke this is a necessary a posteriori identity because the heat (in
gases) cannot be anything other than molecular kinetic energy. It may
be, he says, that the Earth could at some time be inhabited by beings who feel
cold where we feel heat and vice versa, so that for them heat would not be
identical with molecular motion. However, this would not be the case, since
heat is understood as molecular motion as we feel it. For Kripke the
terms ‘heat’ and ‘molecular motion’ are rigid
designators, which make the identity between them unavoidable. For him the fact
that molecular motion produces the sensation of heat is used to fix the
reference, making the identity necessary. The illusion of contingency arises
from the fact that we confuse this fixing the reference with the fact that our
identification of molecular motion with the sensation of heat is contingent.
As it was
already noted in the appendix to chapter 1, since we have ways to translate
rigidity in descriptive terms regarding proper names, we have reasons to guess
that the same can be done with general terms. That is, we could link the two
ascription rules of heat in gases and kinetic molecular energy, building a
unified ascription rule that has two different guises: two different but
interchangeable criteria of identification. I do not intend to provide an
analysis of this rule here, but only show how to employ to concepts a reasoning
similar to those applied above to the identity of proper names.[7]
Thus, considering heat in gases and molecular movement as rigid designators
that necessarily designate the same essence, we could build the following
Kripkian argument calling heat in gazes H and molecular motion M:
(x)
((Hx = Mx) → □ (Hx = Mx))
(x) (Hx
= Mx)
(x)
□ (Hx = Mx)
Clearly, the
same kind of difficulty returns. The first premise says only that if it the identity (x) (Hx = Mx) is really the case, then it is necessarily
the case that all heat is molecular motion, or, from an epistemic perspective,
if it is absolutely certain that all heat in gases are molecular motion, then
it is necessary that all heat in gases are molecular motion. However, as
those who conclude the identity expressed in the second premise are always
fallible epistemic subjects, even if they have the best reasons to believe it
to be true, the following paraphrase of the above argument would be inescapable:
(x) If it is absolutely certain (with
probability 1) that (Hx = Mx),
then □(Hx = Mx).
(x) It is
practically certain (with probability near to 1) that (Hx = Mx).
(x) □(Hx = Mx)
Here again the more
explicit formulation shows an equivocal and consequently fallacious argument.
Because the antecedent of the first premise is different from the second
premise, we cannot apply the modus ponens
and the conclusion does not follows. The result is that we cannot by this way
conclude that the statement ‘Heath (in gazes) is the same as molecular kinetic
energy’ is a necessary a posteriori truth. However, if Kripke were right, this
conclusion should follow.
The last of
Kripke’s examples should be the most important one. It is intended as a
refutation of the type-type identity theory of the mind-body relation,
according to which ‘Pain is (the same as) such and such a brain state’ would be
a contingent a posteriori scientific discovery, yet to be made. But, writes
Kripke, ‘pain’ and ‘such and such a brain state’ are here rigid designators,
because they refer to essential properties. However, if that’s the case, the
identity theorist is in trouble, because the identity needs to be necessary, which clashes frontally with
the fact that whenever you feel pain you do have a pain, while no one is
denying that it is possible to conceive that we have pain without having the
corresponding brain states. For a devout philosopher like Kripke this makes
identity theory improbable.
I find this argument
puzzling. First, one can feel pain without being in pain as a matter of fact –
this can be done, for instance, with hypnotized people. However, even if we
correct this, saying that we cannot feel pain without having the qualitative
state of feeling pain, why this forces us to think that a future neuroscience
cannot show us that speaking of such and such a brain state we make a rigid
reference to pain in Kripke’s own terms?
In my view in most cases Kripke confuses the
a posteriori element of a contingent
a posteriori discovery with the necessary
element of an identity of the reference with itself implied by each flank of
the identity sign, what leads him to believe in a mystical, metaphysically de re grounded necessity a posteriori. In doing so, he
assigns to an ontologically unknowable identity the same status of an
epistemologically alleged identity. He thinks as if we could assert ontological
(metaphysical) truths without regarding our epistemic capacities and their
limits. He refuses to accept that we cannot ever separate completely the
epistemic from the ontic. In doing so, he denies a point that modern
philosophers after Descartes were already aware, namely, that we lack access to
transepistemic truths.
Addendum
There is a considerable variety of
arguments from Kripke and other externalist philosophers deserving close examination.
In what follows I will be short, as a more careful analyses would exceed the
scope of this book.
1. There is a variety of supposed examples of necessary a posteriory
truths later suggested by Kripke and others. Consider, for instance, the
statement (i) ‘Cats are animals’ (Kripke 1980: 181-2). For Kripke this is a
necessary statement, since we cannot conceive a cat that isn’t an animal; but
this is something discovered a posteriori. My answer is that statement (i) can
be interpreted in two ways. As a mere result of an inductive inference it
should be clearly read as a contingent a posteriori statement. However, (i) can
also be read as a necessary a priori statement under the assumption of the
truth of our contemporary taxonomy, according to which the cat is classified as
an organism belonging to the kingdom animalia.[8]
In this case, we are dealing with an analytic statement since (i) should be
interpreted as (ii) ‘Animals called cats are animals’.
2. Another kind of necessary a posteriori later suggested by Kripke concerns the origin. For him, rigidity
makes true parenthood necessary. Consider the statement ‘Ismael Lowenstein is
the son of Abel and Berta Lowenstein.’ According to a Kripkian philosopher this
statement should be necessary a
posteriori because even if this is known a posteriori, a person with
different parents coming from a different ovulo and a different spermatozoid,
would not be Ismael Lowenstein.
(See Kripke 1980: 112 f.).[9]
However, suppose that the adult Ismael makes
the shocking discovery that his parents are not his parents; there was a
mistaken change of babies in the hospital where he was born and the DNA
analysis has proved that he is instead the actual son of Amanda and Mario
Belinzoni. Of course, this is no reason to think that Ismael ceases to be
called Ismael. It is even written in his personal identity card. If asked, he
could insist in answering that his name is Ismael Lowenstein, probably with the
agreement of others.
Anyway, concerning the main point, namely,
the whole statement ‘Ismael is the son of Abel and Berta Lowenstein’, with
concerns the question of parenthood, the conclusion may be more ambiguous.[10] One could
use as criterion of parenthood those who have taken care of the child and
nurtured him with love until the adulthood, and in this case the statement
‘Ismael is the son of Abel and Berta Lowenstein’ will be seen as true, even if
he is originated from one spermatozoid of Mario and one ovulo of Amanda. Under
this understanding the statement ‘Ismael is the son of Abel and Berta
Lowenstein’ is contingent a posteriori.
Contingent because it could be false that they have taken care and nurtured him.
A posteriori because it depends on experience to be learned.
However, it is easy to imagine a situation in
which Kripke’s view would apply. Suppose that we were in the Nazi Germany and
that Abel Lowenstein were Jewish. Suppose that the Nazis have catch him. It is
clear that for them the criterion of parenthood was genetic. In this case,
Ismael Lowenstein would be considered son of Mario and Amanda Belinzoni, while
Carlos would be considered the son of Abel and Berta Lowenstein and sent to a
concentration camp. Finally, it is even possible that the Nazis have
established that the true name of a person must be related to her genetic
origins, concluding that the person called Ismael Lowenstein is in fact Mario
Belinzoni and that Mario Belinzoni is in fact the true Ismael Lowenstein.
Anyway, even in this case the statement ‘Carlos Belinzoni is the son of Mario
and Amanda Belinzoni’ would not be necessary a posteriori, even if in this case
the parenthood turns to be part of the localizing description-rule, since the
whole identifying rule involves much more than this. It would be rather seen by
the Nazis as contingent a posteriori discover, as far as they still have
achieved only an inductive certainty of its truth, even if they consider it a
practical certainty.
2. Worst than
the necessary a posteriori is a later invention of Kripke called contingent a priori. It is the case
involving the platinum rode in Paris, which once defined the meter as the unity
of length. According to him, analysis of meaning is something different from a
definition; the first is necessary, the second not. The definition of ‘one meter’ as ‘the length of S at to’ was a priori but contingent.
Moreover, ‘one meter’ is a rigid designator while ‘the length of S at to,’ being a definite description, is
an accidental designator, allowing the length to be possibly longer or shorter
than one metter, for instance, by earlier heating or cooling. Therefore, the
statement ‘Paris platinum rode is one meter long’, though established a priori,
is contingent, for it could be different. (Kripke 1980: 56)
A difficult it that Kripke gives no
satisfactory reason for this conclusion. The definition of one meter as ‘the
length of S at to’ is a stipulative definition establishing a new meaning. Beside this, why cannot ‘one
meter’ be an abbreviation of ‘the length of S in ∆t[11], whoever
this length is,’ as it seems? Assuming this, our intuitive reasoning would be
to think that if the length changes the meter itself isn’t different, since the
standard meter is defined as whatever
length S has when used as a pattern. Being so it is recommendable to have the
most unchangeable possible standard meter. For suppose that the standard meter
were something elastic, always changing. It would remain the same standard
meter, for sure, but it would be very unpractical. Using this standard
according to the given definition, we could be forced to say of a woman who was
1:67 m high two hours ago that she is 2:24 m high right now, or that two object
with very different sizes would have the same size only because they were
measured in different times… Anyway, if you consider that the statement ‘One
meter is the length of S in ∆t’ presents the definition of a standard meter –
and it really does – this definition is necessary,
since it is conventional and cannot be falsified in any possible world in which
it holds. Moreover, this definition is a
priori, for we don’t need to have any
experience to know its truth (it exemplifies the law of identity). Consequently,
the definition:
Paris platinum rode is one
meter long in ∆t as a standard to be met in any circumstance.
is a
necessary a priori truth, not a contingent a priori one.
Now, if you decide to treat it differently, comparing different possible standard meters
in different times or different counterfactual situations, then you are
reading the statement ‘Paris platinum rode is one meter long’ as something like
‘The standard meter in w1 has the
same length as the standard meter in w2
(or in a counterfactual situation)’. In this case it means more precisely:
Paris platinum rode is one
meter long during ∆t only if compared with others standard meters that could be
used as standards in different times or in any counterfactual circumstances.
This, of
course, is impossible. Now, because Kripke sees that the standard meter cannot
perform this function he comes to the conclusion that it must be contingent. But this function was never
required. Consequently, the standard meter isn’t contingent: it is, as Wittgenstein
correctly saw, a necessary a priori stipulation.
3. Another
attempt to exemplify the contingent a
priori could come from Gareth Evans’ example with the name ‘Julius’, which
is artificially stipulated as ‘the inventor of the zip’ (Evans 1982: 31).
According to some, the statement (i) ‘Julius was the inventor of the zip’ is
contingent a priori. It is a priori because we don’t need the experience to
know this. But it is also contingent since it is possible that he dropped on
his head when little, growing up too stupid to invent the zip (Papineau 2012:
61).
Here we have in fact a contingent a
posteriori statement. It is a posteriori because its truth depends on
experience to be learned. It is contingent because in a counterfactual situation
the zip wasn’t invented or was invented by several persons. Of course, assuming
to be true that someone invented the zip, we could paraphrase ‘Julius invented
the zip’ as (ii) ‘If someone invented the zip we decide that we will call this
person Julius’. However, this paraphrase of (i) is not contingent a priori, but
necessary a priori. It is necessary because it is a stipulation and it is a
priori because it is independent of experience.
4. A related
funny example is the following utterance: ‘I am here now.’ According to David
Kaplan, this is also a kind of contingent
a priori truth. It is a priori because since each one of its terms refers
directly respectively to the agent,
the place and the time of a given context of utterance,
the possibility of its falsity is excluded. But since we can imagine
counterfactual circumstances in which I would not be here, its utterance is
only contingently true (Kaplan 1989: 509).
This example is also delusive. For ‘I am
here now’ can be false in the actual world too. I remember a case related by
Dr. Oliver Sacks of a patient who had a seriously deranged perception of the
continuity of time. Because of this, her daily life was made of time lapses:
she could think ‘I am here now’ as if she were still in the sleeping room, when
in fact she had already moved to the kitchen. So, in this case ‘I am here now’ is
empirically false. The statement is
contingent and also a posteriori, since dependent on the context of the
experience.
5. I also do
not agree with Hilary Putnam’s view that the meaning of the word ‘water’ must
be (essentially) external to our heads. This is perhaps the most influential
argument for semantic externalism. According to Putnam’s thought-experiment, in
1750 Oscar-1 in the Earth and Oscar-2 in the Twin-Earth – both nearly identical
planets with the same history – seeing that it rains, could have only the same
idea of a watery liquid (an under normal temperatures transparent, inodorous,
tasteless… liquid) within their heads. However, without their knowledge, they
were referring to very different composites, the first H2O and the second XYZ,
since the water in the Twin-Earth has a very different chemical composition,
summarized by Putnam as XYZ, though with the same appearance and effects. For
Putnam this proves that the meaning
of water – which for him concerns essentially amounts of atoms with the same
microstructure H2O – wasn’t in the heads of the Oscars, since in their heads
they had the same state, namely, the
idea of a watery liquid. Consequently, the meaning isn’t in the head. As he in
a central passage wrote:
Oscar-1 and
Oscar-2 understood the term ‘water’
differently in 1750, although they had the same psychological state, and
though, given the state of development of Science in their epoch, the
scientific community would need to take circa 50 years to Discovery that they
understood the term ‘water’ differently. Hence, the extension of the term ‘water’ (and, in fact, its meaning in the pre-analytic intuitive
use of the term isn’t function of the psychological state of the speaker. (My
italics)[12]
This shocking
conclusion was later radicalized by John McDowell, who concluded that even the
mind is external to the heads because it is the locus of our manipulation of
meanings (1992: 36).
My neodescriptivist answer is that Putnan’s
result comes from the overseen of the fact that the word ‘water’ has in fact
two descriptive nuclei of meaning: a popular and a scientific one.[13] First there is an old popular nucleus of meaning of the word ‘water’, which is phenomenal or
dispositional and can be summarized in the expression ‘watery liquid’ (the
under normal temperatures transparent, inodorous liquid, that quenches the
thirst, serves to wash, extinguish fire, falls as rain, fulfils rivers, lakes
and oceans, when made cold turns into ice, when warmed into steam, has high
superficial tension, etc.). This was the only meaning in the market until the end
of the XVIII century. Then a new meaning was increasingly added: the scientific nucleus of meaning, which can be summarized as ‘quantities of H2O’ (which
results from 2H2 + O2 = 2H2O, can be subjected to electrolysis, forms
intermolecular hydrogen bounds responsible for its high superficial tension,
etc.). Both nuclei of meaning are obviously descriptive
(since the domain of what can be described is much wider then a merely
phenomenal domain) and can be found today in any good dictionary.[14] Furthermore,
it is easy to see that in consonance with the variability of the context, one
of these meanings comes often to the fore.
This summary already allows a convincing
internalist explanation to the Twin-Earth fantasy. In 1750 the two Oscars had
only the meaning ‘watery liquid’ in their heads, so that the extension of the
word water were the same for them. But when Putnam considers what is going on,
he is unconsciously projecting the scientific
meanings of the word water in the utterances
of the two Oscars. What he does is to treat them as indexical devices for the projection of the new nucleus of meaning,
whose true locus is in fact our own heads (i.e., those of Putnam and his
readers), since we know that Oscar-1 is pointing to H2O while Oscar-2 is
pointing to XYZ. Consequently, the different scientific meanings of the word
‘water’ are not in the world and out of our heads, as Putnam believes, but in
Putnam’s head when he thinks his thought-experiment and in our heads when we
read him, since we all today know the scientific core of meaning. And since
Putnam and his readers have different
scientific meaning-descriptions in their heads when unconsciously projecting
them to Oscar-1 and Oscar-2 by using them as indexical devices, these different
meanings remain, as they should, internal properties of minds.
This idea is reinforced within the neodescriptivist
view that I suggest by the consideration that the meaning of ‘water’ varies
with the context of interest in which
the word is used. In a scientific context of interest (e.g., in a laboratory of
chemistry) the scientific nucleus of meaning is emphasized. Here ‘Water is H2O’
means (a) ‘Hydroxide of oxygen = H2O’: a tautological analytic statement. In this context even if water were not a watery
liquid, but something like coal, it could still be called water, as far as it
preserves the right microstructure.
Now, in a popular context of interest (e.g.,
of fishermen wishing to use water for drinking and washing) ‘Water is H2O’ the
sense of water that is emphasized is that of a watery liquid. In this case
`Water is H20` means (b) `Watery liquid = liquid composed of H2O`. This is an a posteriori contingent statement, not
only because it isn`t known without experience but because at least in
principle (though very improbably) it could be false.
Conclusion: Putnam’s and Kripke’s
classification of the statement ‘Water is H2O’ as a necessary a posteriori statement is only a confusion between the
necessity of the statement (a) and the a posteriori nature of the similar
statement (b). A confusion resulting from lack of attention to the pragmatic of
natural language. We already spoke about these kinds of confusion as we
examined Wittgenstein’s account of the transgressions of the internal limits of
language.
The point can be easily generalized.
Consider the statement (i) ‘Hydrogen is a gas containing atoms with one proton
and one electron.’ One could say: though necessary, it was discovered a
posteriori. But in fact it has at least two contextualized senses: First, if
you think of the transparent inflammable gas discovered by Cavendish in 1766,
called by him ‘inflammable air’, which was later analysed as constituted by
atoms with one electron and one proton. In this case statement (i) is read as contingent a posteriori; this gas could have a different atomic structure
and one could spell the same statement as (i-a) ‘Inflammable air is constituted
by atoms containing one proton and one electron.’ On the other hand, after we
conventionally established the meaning of hydrogen as a gas containing atoms
with one electron and one proton (as we do definitionally in science today),
(i) can be read as (i-b) ‘Hydrogen (Df)
= the gas constituted by atoms containing one proton and one electron’, as far
as we emphasize the sense that the word ‘hydrogen’ has gained in the modern
chemistry. In this case (i) will be read as a tautological, necessary a priori
statement. (We will come back to this point in the chapter 4, sec. 25).
6. There are
two others examples of Putnam aiming to show that the meaning is not only in
the external physical world, but also in the society. In the first one, Putnam assumes that aluminium and
molybdenum are only distinguishable by metalworkers and that the Twin-Earth is
full of molybdenum used to build pots and pans. In addition, he imagines that
the inhabitants of the Twin-Earth call molybdenum ‘aluminium’. In this case, he
writes, the word ‘aluminium’ said by Oscar-1 will have an extension different
than the word ‘aluminium’ said by Oscar-2, so that they mean different things
with the word. However, as they are not Steelworkers, they have the same psychological states. Hence, the
real meaning of these words is external to what happens in their heads,
depending on the society.
Our answer is as follows. If we consider the words
‘aluminium’ and ‘molybdenum’ in the way they were used by Oscar-1 and Oscar-2,
the Oscars are unable to really decide if what they have is aluminium or
molybdenum. They are not experts and what they have in their minds is indeed
the same, as much as the extension that they can give to their concept of
aluminium. For the metalworkers of Earth and Twin-Earth, on the other hand, the
aluminium and molybdenum have very different constitutive properties, what
means that they would have something different in their heads. The Oscar’s, on
their hand, may confuse both things, but only because they do not know really
what these things are: they are using the words in a subsidiary sense. However,
we can consider the aluminium and the molybdenum observed by Oscar-1 and
Oscar-2 and take both persons as referential devices, so that we would say that
Oscar-2 is pointing at what his linguistic community calls aluminium, but which
is what we in our linguistic community call molybdenum. That people should use the
words in accordance with the conventions of their own linguistic community does
not make the meaning external, only dependent of the explicit or implicit agreements
under the members of their communities.
In the second example, Putnam considers the
difference between elms and beeches. Most of us do not know how to distinguish
elms from beeches in a forest. However, we are able to assume that these words
have different extensions. Thus, what we mean with these words are different,
though we do not have different concepts and the difference is not in our
heads... Consequently, their meanings are external: the physical world and the
society with its specialists are those who have the ability to fix the
referential meaning of these words.
The important point to be noticed here is
that we in fact do have an insufficient
knowledge of the meaning of the words ‘elm’ and ‘beech’. But we already know
something very generic about them: we surely know that they are trees and we
guess as very probable that these two names refer to distinct kinds of trees.
With help of these convergent descriptions (see appendix of chapter 1, sec 4)
we are able to insert these words into the discourse, often waiting for the
distinguishing information given by specialists, privileged speakers who have
the sufficient knowledge of the meaning of these words, which enables them to
identify the different kinds. But the meaning – sufficient or not – is always in
the heads of the speakers.[15]
In these two cases, Putnam appeals to a division of linguistic labour in order
to explain different dimensions of meaning that may be considered by different
speakers. This is an important suggestion. However, this is not a suggestion
that confirms an externalist conception of meaning. It is rather neutral, for
the idea of a division of labour of the language was already suggested by
internalist philosophers, from John Locke to C. S. Peirce (Smith 2005: 70-73).
In effect, this idea is perfectly compatible with the difference in the fact
that, even if being socially shared, the meaning remains in the heads of the
speakers, specialists or not, in different dimensions and degrees. In none of
the cases above the meaning needs to be outside the heads.
Finally, to be fair, Putnam expresses
himself much more carefully in a later writing (Putnam, 1988, Ch. 2), e.g., by
saying that the meaning is determined
by the external world. However, either we understand this in the sense that it
is the external world that ultimately produces referential meanings in our
minds, what is an obvious truism that as a weak internalist I have no desire to
deny, or what he means with the word ‘determination’ remains a too subtle
metaphor to find any intelligible rescue.
7. Now I wish to
reinforce my anti-externalist arguments discussing Tyler Burge’s social
externalism of thought concerning the concept of arthritis, which is
complementary to Putnam’s argument. What Burge intended was, apart from Putnam,
to show that not only the meaning is outside the head, but the beliefs’ extension,
i.e., the proper content of thought
(Burge 1979).
I will first summarize the argument of Burge
and then show that it is easy to find a much more plausible weak internalist
explanation for what happens, simply by developing an objection already made by
John Searle (2004: 284-6). In order to make it clearer, instead of following
Burge’s counterfactual mental experiment, I will first suppose that a person
with the name Oscar feels pain in the thigh and see a doctor saying:
(i)
I think I have arthritis in the thigh.
Since arthritis
is characterized as a painful inflammation of the joints, the doctor sees that
his belief is false, for one cannot
have arthritis in the thigh. Imagine now Oscar-2 in the Twin-Earth visits a
doctor for the same reason. But although in the Twin-Earth all things occur
nearly as in the Earth, the people use the word ‘arthritis’ in a much broader
sense, referring to any kind of inflammation. Suppose that in this second
linguistic community Oscar-2 says to the doctor (i) ‘I think I have arthritis
in the thigh’, having in mind exactly the same as in his first utterance. In
this place, as one would expect, the doctor will confirm the suspicion,
agreeing that this is an unquestionably true
belief.
Based on this example, Burge’s reasoning
goes as follows. Without doubt, the psychological States of Oscar-1 and
Oscar-2, when they said to have arthritis in the thigh are exactly the same, as
well as their behaviour. But the contents
of thought expressed in the two
utterances must be different, since the thought expressed by the first
utterance is false, while the thought expressed by the second is true, and the
same thought cannot be false and true. We can even mark the second meaning of
the word ‘arthritis’ on the utterance of Oscar-2 with a new word:
‘tharthritis’. Burge’s conclusion is that the contents of thoughts cannot be
merely psychological.[16]
These contents must belong also to the outside world, to the social communities
involving the speakers.
Against this conclusion it isn’t difficult
to find a commonsensical internalist-descriptivist explanation for what
happens. For this healthy internalism (which admits that our mental
subjectivity unavoidably depends on external inputs), in the Twin-Earth the
concept-word ‘arthritis’ is the expression of an ascription rule constitutive
of its meaning, which is more general, designating any kind of inflammation.
According to this rule, ‘an inflammation that occurs in the thigh’ serves as a
criterial condition and belongs to the sense of the word in the linguistic
community of the twin-Earth, though not in the linguistic community of our
Earth. Thus, although the thought expressed in the sentence ‘I think I have
arthritis in the thigh’ said by the Oscars in the two linguistic communities are
exactly the same, there is a fundamental difference that was rightly recalled
by John Searle in the following words:
Our use of
language is presumed to conform to the other members of our community,
otherwise we could not intend to communicate with them by using a common
language. (Searle 2004, 184-5)
That is, when
Oscar-1 says to the doctor of the Earth ‘I believe I have arthritis in the thigh,’
he must be dispositional assuming that his generalised ascription rule for the
predicate ‘arthritis’ belongs to the language that the other competent speakers
of the language conventionally apply. The whole of what Oscar-1 has in mind
(not only actually but also dispositional) in his utterance in the Earth’s
linguistic community is:
(a) I
have arthritis in the thigh… [and I am assuming that the generalised criterial
condition for the ascription of the predicate ‘arthritis’ is accepted as
correct by the linguistic community speakers to which belongs my present
interlocutor D1].
This is false because the second sentence of the
conjunction is false. Let’s now see what is (actually and dispositional) meant
when Oscar says he has arthritis in the thigh to the second doctor:
(b) I
have arthritis in the thigh… [and I am assuming that the generalised criterial
condition for the ascription of the predicate ‘arthritis’ is accepted as
correct by the community of speakers to which belongs my present interlocutor
D2].
Now the
statement (b) is true. Although the
statement ‘I have arthritis in the tight’ says the same, it has a hidden
indexical meaning that differs from (a) to (b). And this hidden indexical
content is in the minds of the Oscars. So, it may be true that if we confine
ourselves to the content expressed in the thoughts of the Oscars in making the
same utterance in both places we see them as identical. But the whole of what they have mind (that is,
in their heads) with each utterance are different because in the first Oscar-1
knows that he is speaking with doctor D1 belonging to the linguistic community
of the Earth, while in the second he is aware that he is speaking with doctor
D2 at a linguistic community of the Twin-Earth.
This assumption that the verifiability rules
constituting the content of thought should be in accordance with the conventions
of the community of language in which it is expressed in order to achieve truth
is infringed by Oscar when he speaks with the doctor the community belonging to
the earth, but it isn’t infringed when Oscar speaks with the doctor of the
community belonging to the Twin-Earth.
Nonetheless, Burge has called us attention
to one important thing: that the truth or falsehood of utterances depends on
the linguistic conventions adopted by the community involving the speaker. This
is an already relevant point, though it does not reach the claim that anything
of a thought-content or belief is outside the internal psychological realm, in
some way dispersed in the external social-physical environment.
Finally, the given explanation allows us to
make a healthy internalist paraphrase of the well-known distinction between narrow content and wide content. For the unmasked externalist
point of view, the narrow content is one that is in the mind of the speaker,
while the wide content is external: it is out there in the world or in the
society. The healthy internalist analysis of Burge’s example allows us to
propose that the narrow content of thought is the semantic-cognitive
verifiability rule that constitutes it (expressed by the statement ‘I think
that I have arthritis in the thigh’), while the wide content of thought is what
is assumed in the speaker’s mind as a provision whose expected existence will
be arguably accepted.
8. Finally, one
word about John Perry’s argument for the essential
indexical (1979). I will be extremely
short, since I am repeating an argument presented in details in another place
(Costa 2014c). His view is that senses of indexicals are inevitably tied with
the external circumstances of utterance, what can be proved by the fact that
one cannot translate them into eternal sentences without loss. Consequently,
externalism is correct.
In Perry’s main example he is in a
supermarket and discovers that there is a trail of sugar on the floor. He
begins to search for the author of the trail only to discover that the person
who is spilling sugar out of the car is he himself, what leads him to say: (i)
‘I am making a mess’, what immediately changes his behaviour. Suppose, says
Perry, that he translate this statement in the non-indexical statement (ii)
‘Perry is making a mess’. It is not the same, since he could, for instance, be
suffering from Alzheimer, having forgotten that his name is Perry…
However, I think that there is indeed a way
to preserve the sense of the indexical detaching it from the context. It is a
technique that I call transplantation:
if you need to change the place of a plant, you usually don’t take the plant
alone, but the plant with the earth in which it is rooted, often together with a
cover. Applying a analogue technique, here is how Perry’s example appears after
transplantation:
(iii) At 10:20
a.m. on March 26, 1968 in the confectionary supplies of the Fleuty Supermarket
in the city of Berkeley, CA, after noticing a sugar trail stretching away from
his shopping cart, Perry says to himself that he is making a mess.
Here what counts
is the truth of the eternal sentence into which the indexical sentence is
included. Although containing an indexical (he, himself), the statement (iii)
is not referring to the real context, but referring
indirectly to the Fregean thought expressed within the subordinate
sentence after the that-clause. Thus, protected by its surrounding description
(the covering of the eternal sentence) the sense of ‘I am making a mess’ is
here integrally transplanted without loss into the non-indexical context that
would be called by Frege indirect reference.[17]
What this argument shows is that essential indexicals are not essential, once
the external components can be internalized.
[1] Rejecting the view of a particular as a
bundle of abstract properties, he concludes: ‘What I do deny is that a
particular is nothing but a ‘bundle of qualities’, whatever that may mean’.
(1980: 52).
[2] According to Searle, although
there is a class of beliefs whose explanation depends on contextual
characteristics, one should not equivocally conclude that such characteristics
cannot be entirely represented as part of the intentional (mental) content. The
difference between beliefs called de dicto and de re is a difference
between reports. In a de re belief like ‘About the man with the
brown hat, Ralf believes he is a spy’, we
commit ourselves with the existence of the man with brown hat. In a de dicto
belief like ‘Ralf believes that the man in the brown hat is a spy’, we commit
ourselves only with the report of Ralf’s belief. (Searle 1983: 208-220).
[3] It seems that the real reason
why we distinguish the regularities that are natural laws from those that are
merely coincidental is that the first are well-entrenched, that is, are strongly
inferentially bounded with our scientific system of beliefs. This is what gives
them the impression of logical necessity. It is true that we have in the
present discussion several alternative approaches to this classic Humean
regularity view. But first, the regularity view seems to be the most plausible
approach, regarding the assumption of fallibility; second, the fact that
something is presently very much on the stage is within the intrinsically
changeable landscape of philosophy no value judgment.
[4] See also Wittgenstein 1984a sec. 96.
[5] Some say ‘almost never’, a
point that is open to scrutiny, also because the extension of our empirical
knowledge is still an open question.
[6] See my evaluation of the
‘brain in a vat’ argument in Costa 2014: 135-6.
[7] Anyway, see the section 5 of
the Addendum to this Appendix, where the rules of application for the
concept-word ‘water’ are analysed.
[8] According to Kant there is
priori knowledge that isn’t pure, taking long exercise to be separated from the
knowledge adquired by means of sensory experience (Kant 1787: Introduction, I).
[9] Kripke speaks of Elisabeth
II, the Queen of England. But this is a biased example, since in the case of a
queen the ovulo origin acquires maximal importance, contaminating the
characterizing description of its identifying rule.
[10] There are today several
competing theories of parenthood (genetic, labour-based, intentional, causal
and pluralistic accounts) and there is no consensus on the right cluster of
criteria (see Brake & Millum 2016, sec. 4).
[11] The symbol ‘∆t’ is more
correct because the road served a standard not only in to but during all the time in which it was
conventionally designed to this function.
[12] Hilary Putnam: “The Meaning
of ‘Meaning’” (1995: 224).
[13] I am strongly summarizing
here. For the full argument, which is preceded by a more careful
neodescriptivist analysis of the meanings of the word ‘water’, see Costa 2014b.
[14] For instance, the main
definition in the Merrian Webster
dictionary contains elements of both,
popular and scientific nuclei of meaning: ‘water = the liquid that descends
from the clouds as rain, form streams, lakes, and seas, and is a major
constituent of all living matter and that when pure is an odourless, tasteless,
very slightlty compressible liquid oxide of hydrogen H2O which appears bluish
in thic layers, freezes at 0°C freezes and boils at 100°C, has a maximum density at 4°C and a high
specific heat, is feebly ionized to hydrogen and hydroxy ions, and is a poor
cinductor of electricity and a good solvent.’ (See also Stroll 1996, Ch. 2)
[15] For interesting answers to
some others externalist arguments see Searle 2004.
[16] As he wrote: ‘The upshot of these reflections is that
the patient’s mental contents differ while his entire
physical and non-intentional mental histories, considered in isolation from
their social context, remain the same.’ (Burge 1976: 106, my italics)
[17] See appendix of chapter 4, sec. 5 (iv).