This is an advanced draft of a text published in the 42th International Ludwig Wittgenstein Symposium, 2019.
COMPREHENSIVE
PHILOSOPHY IN THE AGE OF SCIENCE
Susan
Haack criticizes current philosophy as falling prey to a
scientistic-reductionist trap characterized by fragmentation, hermeticism,
and ahistoricism, which she sees as an intellectual disaster (2016,
1.1). Her main complaint concerns the loss of breadth in
contemporary philosophy. From Plato to Peirce, at least, the interconnectedness
of different areas was an integral part of philosophical work. However, it has
almost disappeared in current academic philosophy. One could then ask: why
interconnection? Is this a vital aspect of the philosophical endeavor? Haack’s
answer depends on her particular understanding of the concept of consilience.
What consilience means is that there is only one real world, which is complex
and varied, but whose truths are expected to fit together. Particularly
interesting is the way she thinks these truths must fit together:
Not, however (as
reductionists dream), that all the other truths about the world must be
derivable from some privileged sub-set of truths, but rather that they must
interlock, as entries in a crossword puzzle do (2015, 1.2).
It is
easy to see (taking only one of her examples) that Neo-Darwinian evolutionism
interlocks with Mendelian genetics, which interlocks with molecular genetics,
which in turn interlocks with geology, etc. The idea is that in the same way as
different domains of science interlock with one another, as well in philosophy
we should expect an interlinkage among its different sub-domains, together with
its still living history and the present stage of sciences.
This interlinkage is, she thinks, hindered by premature philosophical
specialization. Here things are very different from the developed sciences. In
recent science, specialization is made against a background
of well-warranted theory that is needed to make it productive. In
philosophy, on the other hand, we do not have this background of
well-established truths, which means that premature specialization will develop
based on the feeble foundations of merely speculative work, in a way that isn’t
prone to move the philosopher forward. As she writes:
When premature
specialization becomes commonplace, the prospects for achieving something solid
to build on seem to recede indefinitely; and so, people keep themselves busy
arguing over and over the same puzzles – until boredom sets in, and they set
off in pursuit of a new fad. Problems are never solved, but simply
abandoned. (2016, 1.2)
Moreover,
our present academic system promotes what she calls perverse incentives,
rewarding quantity over quality, producing too many PhDs, evaluating work by
received grants, honoring publication in prestigious journals, building
incredibly corrupted rankings of graduate programs, in ways that corrupt the
field by “discouraging patience and painstaking and encouraging efforts to
create the appearance of progress…” (2017, II). One result of this is an
overspecialization that unnaturally fragments the philosophical quest:
Our discipline becomes
every day more specialized, more fragmented into cliques, niches, cartels, and
fiefdoms, and more determinedly forgetful of its own history. More and
more journals are crammed with more and more unread, and sometimes unreadable,
articles about what X said about Y’s interpretation of Z’s response to W.
(2017, II)
This is
my summary of Haack’s diagnosis of the maladies of current
philosophy.
I
Although
I essentially agree with her, I am not as radically pessimistic. Not all
philosophical work associated with science is burdened by scientism. The speech
acts theory of J. L. Austin and John Searle was surely not. The new theories of
consciousness, from D. M. Armstrong to D. M. Rosenthal, Daniel Dennett, Ned
Block, and Bernard Baars, have deepened the philosophy of consciousness in
unquestionable ways. D. C. Williams’ trope theory points to a possible
revolution in ontology whose originality could only be compared with that of
the venerable traditions of realism and nominalism.
Moreover, well-intentioned scientistic reductionism in philosophy is rather an
expected reaction to the development of new scientific fields and might be
somewhat fruitful, even if in error, by showing its possibilities and limits.
This was the case of the well-intentioned scientism of Hilary Kornblith’s
naturalized epistemology, as Haack recognizes. This can well be the case of the
speculative modal adventure of David Lewis’ realism of possible worlds and Saul
Kripke’s theory of reference, which limits the mechanism of reference to an
external causal-historical chain. Scientistic reductionism, which typically
could in my view be called expansionist scientism, isn’t even
something new. The rise of mathematics led Pythagoras to a form of mysticism in
which the world would be constituted by values given by numbers, and the way of
purification would be mathematical work, expanding the proper grasp of
mathematics in ways that today have merely historical value.
In my view, Haack’s diagnosis finds its best application by showing the
obstacles posed against a comprehensive philosophical approach in the context
of current philosophy. This is the point I wish to consider.
A first remark concerns the origins and nature of scientism in today’s
philosophy. In 1932 Wittgenstein told us in few words the reasons for his
pessimism regarding much philosophy in his time. According to him:
Philosophers
constantly see the method of science before their eyes, and are
irresistibly tempted to ask and answer questions in the ways science does. This
tendency is the real source of metaphysics, and leads the philosopher
into complete darkness. (1975, 18)
Surely,
these words echo Wittgenstein’s experience with the Logical Positivists some years
earlier. He believed in philosophical comprehensiveness (Übersichtlichkeit)
(1984, I #122), having in his Tractatus noted that the
difficulty with philosophy is that one cannot solve any of its problems unless
one has solved all the others. This means that he also saw the coherence given
by interlinked concerns as a way to reinforce the plausibility of philosophical
views, which scientism isn’t able to do. Interlocking among theories makes them
heuristically stronger, as in the case of neo-Darwinian evolutionism, made
stronger by the development of molecular genetics.
Although Wittgenstein’s own descriptive therapeutic dissolution of
philosophical problems was inadequate, the problems he found in the scientistic
approach to philosophy were similar to those identified by Haack. The
philosophers of the Vienna Circle embarked on a kind of premature enterprise
similar to that considered by Haack, for instance, by restricting philosophy to
the logical analysis of language. The strategy was the standard example of
expansionist scientism: explaining as far as possible by means of instruments,
standards and categories developed by sciences, particularly the new logic, and
paying for this the price of excluding from discussion all dissonant problems
that cannot fit with the chosen methodology, like the problems of metaphysics,
ethics, aesthetics, etc., which makes the enterprise reductionist. Even if the
heritage of logical positivism was not void, their initial goal of debunking
all the old philosophical problems was a derisory failure.
Logical positivism was, in fact, only a harbinger of things to come. For the
scientistic-reductionist attitude became a tradition continued by American
philosophers like W. V. Quine and Donald Davidson, to give
two names, until it became as today an almost invisible commonplace.
It usually belongs to mainstream contemporary philosophy, and most of its
practitioners are so immersed in its haze that they do not even perceive its
presence. The great difference is that present-day scientistic philosophy is
much less restricted. Today, there are many scientific fields and sub-fields
that foster their corresponding scientistic reactions. Expansionist scientism
is indeed very much welcome in a world like ours, where new ramifications of
science are constantly appearing.
Attention to science, even if conditioned by well-intentioned scientism, is
acceptable for the already given reasons. However, this has negative
consequences clearly perceived by Haack. Present-day philosophers seem to be
anxious to attain something that approaches scientific knowledge, even if by
imitation, even if by betting, that is, by using the method of shooting in the
dark, once leaders of their sub-domain have shown the direction supposed to be
plausible. One could say that scientistic philosophy driven by science today
plays a role comparable to the role of the pseudo-argumentative rhetoric common
to much of 20th-century French philosophy, which was driven by their
strong literary cultural tradition. However, it robs philosophy of
its comprehensive goals by condemning much of its efforts to either hollowness
or implausibility. The really damaging problem, as I wish to point out, is that
philosophical attempts at more general syntheses are from the
start excluded.
This philosophical fragmentation is institutionally fostered. In my view, the
ultimate reason for this was foretold by Max Weber’s metaphor of the iron cage resulting
from the process of disenchantment of the world (Entzauberung
der Welt) (Costa 2018, xi-xii): increasing bureaucracy and steering towards
science tends to suffocate and exclude all that belongs to the old humanistic
culture and cannot be incorporated into the inevitable process of
disenchantment of the world, including philosophy. The iron cage furthers
scientism, as well as mass culture, as deficient but inevitable forms of
re-enchantment in a scientifically and technologically loaded world. Moreover,
it exchanges valuing reason for instrumental reason, which leads to a
debasement of moral standards.
It is not difficult to see how it works in practice. Philosophy has for a long
time been institutionalized by universities, which are today competitively
directed towards scientific and technological development. Departments are
evaluated within an inter-institutional dialogue on the basis of their scientific
contributions by means of articles and technical advancement. This same frame
that should promote science is also imposed on departments of philosophy, what
means that practitioners are forced to mass produce papers and invent new (or
apparently new) common problems able to be evaluated by proficient specialists.
This, however, will only be an easily achievable task if the parameters of
evaluation by peers remains restricted to sufficiently specialized
domains of the present discussion, generally linked with some scientific field.
Under such conditions, it is not surprising that overspecialized work wins the
competition by the sheer force of quantity.
Not that these efforts are totally futile for the development of particularized
knowledge. Philosophy can often have only a harmless limited scope. In fact, I
guess it could be complementary with comprehensive philosophy in a way that
recalls the way experimental physics is complementary with theoretical physics.
This isn’t, however, the usual case. Scientistic philosophy, at least, is
symptomatically accompanied by contempt for comprehensive philosophy. One
cannot imagine, under such institutional circumstances, philosophers like Kant,
Hegel, or even Peirce, who could need decades to fully develop their comprehensive
views. The first two could do it in a detached cultural milieu that gave them
sufficient support, and the last one had the blessing of ostracism, being
forced to work outside the society of ideas. Today, if someone dares to do this
kind of work, it will surely be unavailable by the narrow standards of the
dominant overspecialized philosophical community, the results buried under an
unimaginable amount of unchecked published academic junk. In other words, those
who are able to do it, but are wise enough to understand what is happening,
would not even try. And this is the real problem: the scientistic
fragmentation of present-day philosophy has dessicated the
intellectual soil that could allow the development of more comprehensive forms
of philosophy.
To this, we can add the problem of the right minds. Why
a person able to write dozens of very specialized papers in a few years would
be the right person to do a comprehensive philosophical work? Now, if this
person is selected as the top guardian leader of the philosophical pyramid,
what kind of pyramid would we expect to be built?
Against these views, one could object that there is no alternative. The amount
of knowledge now accumulated is so immense that philosophical overviews are
condemned. The usual advice is: those who have tried have failed. However, are
such failures an objective matter, or a sign of the times? Are they not limited
by the context of discovery? Are not the demands of accuracy and of a detailed
discussion of alternatives artificially exaggerated by scientistic distortions
of the field?
An optimistic answer is that things are not necessarily so. It is true that
human knowledge is now overwhelmingly vast. But many philosophical results are
superimposed, displaced or simply misleading. And a philosopher often does not
need to know all the details of different sciences in order to do comprehensive
work. What a philosopher needs is often to understand the results of
established science. Moreover, electronic media are giving us an increasing
possibility of reaching a level of knowledge unimaginable some decades ago.
A
last objection would be that the philosophical quest could be slowly and
imperceptibly approaching its limits. It is possible to think that sooner or
later all the apparently intangible central philosophical problems inherited
from tradition will either be reassigned to science, or will be dissolved as
pseudo-problems, or both. In this way, the disenchantment of the philosophical
world will be completed.
This is a plausible point, particularly if we understand the word ‘science’ in
a broad way, as any inquiry able to reach consensual agreement among those who
are sufficiently prepared to deal with it (“consensualizable public
knowledge”, according to Ziman 1968, Ch. 2). The question, however, is of
knowing what kind of scientific work will replace central areas of philosophy
like epistemology, metaphysics, philosophy of mind, ethics? There are two kinds
of answer. If we believe in the future of fragmented scientistic philosophical
guesswork, we will have reductionist results. We will, for instance,
replace folk psychology with neuroscience; we will replace
analytic-conceptual epistemology with naturalized epistemology as a branch of
experimental psychology; or we will replace a more complex
cognitivist-causal understanding of reference with more regimented external
causal views… The alternative to this, however, is that the central sub-domains
of philosophy will be developed and interlocked in the form of science in a
non-reductionist form. These central philosophical realms will build scientific
fields of their own, possibly as complex and well-structured as modern physics
and resulting from collaborative work. I would not have any complaint against
this last possibility.
Literature
Costa,
Claudio (2018). Philosophical Semantics: Reintegrating Theoretical
Philosophy. Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing.
–
(2002). The Philosophical Inquiry: Towards a Global Account.
Lanham, MD: University Press of America.
Haack,
Susan (2017). Scientism and its Discontents. Rounded Globe.
–
(2016). The Reintegration of Philosophy. Springer Verlag.
Wittgenstein,
Ludwig (1984a). Philosophische Untersuchungen. Berlin:
Suhrkamp.
–
(1975). The Blue and the Brown Books. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Ziman,
J. M. (1968). An Essay Concerning the Social Dimension of
Science. New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Nenhum comentário:
Postar um comentário