This is a draft of a chapter of the book "How do Proper Names Really Work?" (De Gruyter 2023)
II
CAUSAL-REFERENTIALISM
In 1970, Saul Kripke gave lectures at Princeton
that were recorded and subsequently published as Meaning and Necessity. This extraordinarily original text contains
an enormously influential assault on descriptivist theories of proper names. It
also contained (among other things) the outline of an innovative referentialist
or causal-referentialist conception of proper names, in its principles
influenced by J. S. Mill’s direct reference view, though also extending it to
include terms applicable to natural species. Since then, the old descriptivist
orthodoxy in vogue from Frege to John Searle was gradually eclipsed by
referentialist or causal-referentialist views of reference, which for many
specialists became the inherited wisdom (See Raatikainen 2020).
While
recognizing that these new ideas have definitively transformed the landscape of
the discussion, making it more complex, intricate, and disorienting, I am
convinced that they are not in themselves sustainable. Besides introducing
the new orthodoxy, the main purpose of this chapter is to reveal its most
serious shortcomings.[1]
1. Three arguments against descriptivism
I begin my presentation didactically, by
exposing and showing the limitations of three well-known arguments against
descriptivist theories of proper names, extracted from Kripke’s text.[2]
Although in no way exhaustive, they give us a point of departure. They have
been called (i) the modal argument (objection of rigidity), (ii) the semantic
argument (objection of ignorance and error), and (iii) the epistemological
objection (objection of unwanted necessity). I will limit myself here to a
very short critical examination of these arguments, leaving aside a more
detailed discussion of important counterexamples, since it will make use of the
neodescriptivist theory to be explained in the next chapter.
Let’s
start with (i): the modal objection of rigidity (Kripke 1980: 53; 61-63;
74-76). Before presenting this objection, I need to introduce Kripke’s concept
of the rigid designator, which he
finds distinctive for proper names. I prefer to define a rigid designator as a term that designates the same object in
every possible world where this object exists and does not designate anything
in any possible world where this object does not exist (Kripke 1971: 173;
1980: 48). A rigid designator contrasts with a non-rigid or accidental
designator, which does not have this property (Kripke 1980: 48; 1971:
145-146). In simpler terms, a rigid designator would designate the same object
in any actual or counterfactual circumstance in which this object exists. The
important point of Kripke’s distinction can be seen when we compare the
behavior of proper names (which are the primary models of rigid designators),
with the usual behavior of definite descriptions, which are typically non-rigid,
accidental, also called flaccid, designators.
The
difference between rigid and accidental kinds of designators is made evident by
means of examples. Compare the proper name ‘Columbus’ with the definite
description ‘the first European navigator to set foot on Hispaniola’.[3]
The name Columbus would still refer to the same person in a near possible
world, even if in this world it wasn’t Columbus, but rather Vasco da Gama who
discovered the Island of Hispaniola, and Columbus instead preferred to lead an
uneventful life as a merchant in his Italian hometown of Genoa. The reference
of the proper name Columbus, however, remains the same. According to Kripke,
the reference of ‘Columbus’ does not change in different possible worlds,
because Columbus is a proper name, and proper names are rigid designators. But
in the above considered possible world, the reference of the definite
description ‘the first European navigator to set foot on Hispaniola’ changed
from Columbus to Vasco da Gama, since this is an ordinary empirical definite description,
and such descriptions are accidental. The definite description is also
applicable in a possible world where Columbus didn’t even exist, insofar as
Vasco da Gama or some other European had discovered Hispaniola. On the other
hand, if Columbus existed, the proper name ‘Columbus’ would still refer to
Columbus, even if an unexpected cosmic cataclysm had prevented any European
from setting foot on Hispaniola, eschewing the application of the definite
description.
Beyond
these comparisons, Kripke proposed an intuitive test for the identification of
a rigid designator (1980: 48), which can be explained as follows:
Ask yourself whether it is true that:
Something other than x might have
been x. Or: ask yourself whether x might have been other than
(different from) the thing that is in fact x.
In addition to these, Christopher Hugues
suggested his own incremented test (2004: 20): ask yourself whether it is true
that:
x
could have existed without being x.
If the answers are negative, then x
is a rigid designator.
Applying the test to the above definite
description, we could ask if the following statements are true: “Someone other
than the first European to set foot on Hispaniola might have been the first
European to set foot on Hispaniola.” Or, more clearly: “The first European to
have set foot on Hispaniola might have been other than the one who was in fact
the first European to have set foot on Hispaniola.” The answer is in the
affirmative: it could have been another person. Finally, “The first European to
have set foot on Hispaniola could have existed without being the first European
to have set foot on Hispaniola” can be accepted as obviously true. Hence, the
given definite description must be an accidental designator.
However, the proper name ‘Columbus’ does not behave like the description
above. Are the following sentences true? “Someone other than Columbus might
have been Columbus”, or “Columbus might have been other than the person who is
in fact Columbus”. Certainly not, they must be false. Finally, “Columbus could
have existed without being Columbus” is obviously also false. Hence, ‘Columbus’
is a rigid designator. It is worth considering this point because the theory of
proper names to be developed in Chapter III furnishes a neo-descriptivist
demystifying way to explain rigidity that makes it clear why proper names pass
the test while corresponding definite descriptions fail to pass.
There
is also controversy concerning those possible worlds where the bearer of the
name does not exist. In the case where the bearer is a so-called abstract
object like the number 2, it seems easier to conceive the bearer as existing in
any possible world (for this reason it is also called an obstinately rigid designator). But this is not so easily accepted in cases of
ordinary empirical names like ‘Columbus’. In his original presentation of the
notion of a rigid designator, Kripke acknowledged this point:
When I use the notion of rigid designator, I do
not imply that the object referred to necessarily exists. All I mean is that in
any possible world where the object in question does exist, in any situation in which the object would exist, we use the designator in
question to designate that object. In a situation where the object does not
exist, then we should say that the designator has no referent and that the
object in question so designated does not exist. (1971: 173)
This is surely the most reasonable view
regarding our robust common sense, for it is a basic conceptual rule of our
language that we can use a word to refer
only when its object of reference exists, otherwise not (Stroll 1996). Consequently, in
counterfactual situations where the object does not exist, we cannot use the
proper name to refer to its bearer. If a name could refer to non-existent
objects, then I could invite 1,000 non-existent persons to a party in my small
apartment, and all of them would find enough free space to be well
accommodated.
Unfortunately, Kripke spoiled his useful
tool by making the concept unreasonably complicated. In his 2019 talk “Naming
and Necessity Revisited” he emphasized again that in his most important book, Naming and Necessity, there are two
notions of the rigid designator: (i) a de
facto definition in the main text of the book, according to which: “a
designator is rigid iff there is an object a that it designates with respect to every possible world in which a exists, and (he now adds) “never
designates another object with respect to any world”, intending “to be neutral about whether the term
designates with respect to worlds where the object does not exist”. On the other hand, there is (ii) a de jure rigidity, for which “the main thing is that a name
designates an object independently of other
considerations”, having as a corollary that it “designates that object with respect to every world” (see also 1980: 21n).
However, the only lesson one can learn from
this de jure definition is trivial:
the best it can significantly mean is that a proper name is made (has the job) to designate
something in every possible world, even if it does in fact designate (refer)
only in those possible worlds where its designatum
exists.
Since
this merely curious issue will have no impact on our further arguments, I
prefer to ignore the question about a sense in which a proper name could
possibly refer to an object in a possible world where this object does not
exist. Henceforth, I will understand a rigid designator as what is called a persistent rigid designator, namely, a
term that only refers in possible worlds where its object of reference actually
does exist (Salmon 1980: 34).
Now we
are in position to understand (i): the modal argument caused by the rigidity of
proper names in contrast to that of descriptivism. The point is that if
proper names are always rigid designators, and definite descriptions are
typically not, proper names cannot be equated with definite descriptions or
even with clusters of definite descriptions. Since definite descriptions
are typically accidental designators, designating contingent properties, and
only possibly referring to the same object in counterfactual situations, proper
names and descriptions have different modal profiles. Implicit is the
suggestion that the mechanism by which a proper name refers must in some way be
intrinsically different from the one by which a definite description usually
refers: they cannot mean the same thing.
Indeed, it seems that for any definite description that we choose as the
constituent of a proper name, it is always possible to imagine cases in which
the object exists, but the description applies to another object or simply does
not apply to any object. As Kripke wrote against Searle’s version of cluster
theory:
It just is not, in any intuitive sense of
necessity, a necessary truth that Aristotle had the properties commonly
attributed to him (1980: 74). (…) It would seem that it is a contingent fact
that Aristotle ever did any of the
things that we attribute to him today, any
of these great achievements that we so much admire (1980: 75).
In fact, we can imagine a near possible world
where Aristotle existed but died in adolescence. In this world, he does not
satisfy the definite descriptions of having been the founder of the Lyceum, nor
the preceptor of Alexander, nor the person who wrote the great philosophical
texts for which his name is remembered. Even descriptions containing his place
and date of birth are not guaranteed. We can perfectly well imagine, as Kripke
did, a possible world where Aristotle lived five hundred years later but could
still be recognized as our own Aristotle (1980: 62).
However, the modal objection of rigidity applies only to descriptive
theories that identify the meaning of a proper name with a definite description
or even with some precise set or sub-set of definite descriptions – a cluster
supposedly shared by all the competent speakers of a language. For those who
read the previous chapter, it must have been clear that Frege’s view implies
that proper names might have different senses according to the descriptions or
sub-sets of descriptions their users have in mind, which relativizes the modal
objection. Moreover, Russell explicitly understood that the descriptions in our
minds can vary from speaker to speaker, forming vague masses of historical
knowledge, which also contrasts with the inflexibility demanded by the modal
objection. Finally, a theory such as Searle’s explicitly appeals to the
relation between a changeable variety of descriptions a speaker can have when
using a proper name and an open cluster of descriptions, which allows
flexibility. This last theory is in an explicit way immune to the modal
objection, by emphasizing that no specific description belonging to the
cluster necessarily must be satisfied, although a sufficient yet unspecified
number of them must necessarily be satisfied. Against such
interpretations, the modal objection of rigidity is impotent, since the cluster
theory does not require any description or combination of descriptions to be
applied in any possible world where the bearer of the proper name exists.
Furthermore, even if it is possible to imagine, as Kripke did, that
Aristotle does not necessarily satisfy the vast majority of descriptions
attributed to him, or any chosen description, it is crucial to see that it
is not possible to imagine that he does not satisfy any of the descriptions
belonging to the cluster’s name. It is not possible to imagine that he is a
prime number, that he is a waiter in the restaurant where Searle usually had
his meals, or that he was not a philosopher, but instead, a famous Greek
shipping magnate who lived in the twentieth century, seduced Maria Callas, and
married Jacqueline Kennedy, or even, taking Searle’s example, an illiterate
fishmonger who lived in Venice in the Renaissance, since these persons
certainly could have nothing to do with our Aristotle.[4]
Even an Aristotle who in a near possible world lived 500 years after the
Aristotle who was born in our world should have at least something relevantly
“Aristotelian” about him to be recognized as our Aristotle. For instance, he
could have written the Nicomachean Ethics…
In sum: under a more careful view, the modal argument of rigidity is unable to
warrant that proper names and ordinary definite descriptions are semantically
incompatible.
Notwithstanding, the modal argument leaves a serious question lurking in
our minds: how could a descriptivist theory warrant the intuitive rigidity of
proper names? The answer is that in the present stage of descriptivism even
Searle’s cluster theory does not have the resources to answer this question.
This is, however, one of the questions our neodescriptivist theory will
decisively answer in the next chapter.
Now, I
will consider (ii): the semantic argument (e.g., Kripke 1980: 79-85).[5]
According to this argument, whether a proper name refers to an object does
not depend on its satisfaction of definite descriptions. This is well
exemplified by cases of ignorance and error. Concerning ignorance, Kripke shows
that even when we associate a single indefinite
description with a proper name, we are still able to refer with it. This is
the case with the name ‘Feynman.’ Many people associate this name only with the
indefinite description ‘an American physicist’. Only a few would be able to
answer by saying that he was the originator of quantum electrodynamics, and
still fewer would be able to explain in detail his main contribution to
micro-physics. Even so, people are sometimes able to refer to Feynman by
uttering only that indefinite description. An indefinite description, however,
is incapable of warranting the singularity of the reference. Therefore,
descriptivism must be a faulty theory. As for the problem of errors, Kripke
noted that in his time there were people who associated the description ‘the
inventor of the atomic bomb’ with the name ‘Einstein’. Although the description
is wrong, those people were referring to Einstein even though they had a wrong
description in mind. Now, if so, then it seems that descriptions have little to
do with the relevant way proper names refer to their bearers.
To
this kind of objection, Searle would answer that what matters most is the content that the members of the
linguistic community to which the speaker belongs see as relevant to the
object’s designation (1983: 253).[6]
Thus, for Searle a person may utter the name ‘Einstein’, while having in mind a
description such as ‘the individual my community calls Einstein’. This may
suffice to neutralize the inadequacy of the content.
Nonetheless, the answer offered by Searle cannot be satisfactory. If it
were, we could appeal to the same stratagem to warrant the reference of any
proper name whose reference we do not know. A better proposal would be that a
description like ‘Einstein was the inventor of the atomic bomb’, although
erroneous, remains convergent in the sense that it already classifies
him correctly as a human being and a scientist, as much as the use of ‘Feynman’
as ‘an American physicist’, since the bearer is correctly classified as an
American and a physicist. Based on these vague convergences, hearers are
already able to recognize the speaker as having the intention to identify
someone who satisfies the descriptions they also associate with these names.
This is not only true for the hearer who really knows a lot of the cluster of
descriptions typically associated with the names Einstein and Feynman, but also
for the many hearers who know only generalities about these names and see that
the given description falls under those generalities. They are all able to
guess whomever the speaker is trying to refer to. Consider, for instance, the
many hearers who only know about Einstein that he was a great German physicist
who originated relativity theory, or that Feynman was an American physicist who
did research on microphysics at Caltech. These vague uses of the proper name
parasitically echo the effective reference that could only be made by the most
competent users of the name; and the less competent are free to borrow the reference
from the last ones, insofar as they assume their existence. If this answer does
not seem very satisfactory to you now, a more complete answer will be given in
the next chapter.
Now we
will consider (iii): the epistemic objection of unwarranted necessity (e.g.,
Kripke 1980: 86-87). It is different from the semantic argument. The semantic
argument says that it need not be the case that the name’s referent satisfies
the intended description. The epistemic argument, on its side, says that even
if the referent satisfies the associated description, we do not know it a
priori, even if from the descriptivist perspective we should.[7]
If the name Aristotle replaced the description ‘the author of Metaphysics’, such descriptions should
be known a priori in the analytical
sense of conveying information known solely by reflection on the concepts
involved, and without resort to sensory experience.[8]
However, we can be wrong about this accomplishment attributed to Aristotle.
Even if the name Aristotle replaced a cluster of descriptions, at least some of
them should be known a priori about him, though this is also in no way
guaranteed. After all, one can be totally misled concerning what one thinks is
the reference of a proper name.
However, even the epistemic objection hardly refutes a cluster theory of
descriptions such as Searle’s, which does not require an a priori or
necessary satisfaction of any individual description or of any particular group
of descriptions belonging to the cluster to allow the application of the proper
name to its bearer. The only necessity that must be supported by a cluster
theory is that at least a previously
unspecified minimal number of weightier definite descriptions belonging to the
cluster is necessarily satisfied by the named object, in cases
where this object exists. Hence, there is no requirement of a specific
description or even of a conjunction of descriptions to be analytically a
priori satisfied by the proper name’s bearer. If we think in this way, then
Searle’s cluster descriptivism can still be seen as allowing – though not
explaining – the treatment of the proper name as a kind of rigid designator. In
the next chapter, we will develop a more complex form of cluster theory and
show that, surprisingly, it implies and explains rigidity.
As
already noted, it is difficult to find any decisive objection to a formulation
of the descriptivist theory of proper names such as that developed by Searle.
The reason for this is that it was presented in a non-simplifying and
sufficiently vague way. But, as will become clear later, this advantage is also
its greatest weakness, because, due to its own vagueness, this theory lacks the
resources to provide more effective and complete answers to a variety of counterexamples
and objections.
There
are other challenging and revealing objections to descriptivism, particularly
in the form of examples. But before dealing with them we need to develop a more
complex descriptive theoretical apparatus, which allows us to answer objections
in depth. Hence, I ask you to wait until Chapter IV to read what I regard as
the most convincing and, in fact, only answers. However, the few considerations
offered above are already able to suggest that Kripke’s objections to
descriptivism do not seem as decisive as his most convinced supporters would
like us to believe.[9]
2. Kripke on
individuation and trope-theory
Kripke’s critique of descriptivism is
attractive in part because it is complemented by a challenging conception of
the mechanisms of reference – a conception that is in ways similar to the view
introduced by J. S. Mill. Before explaining it, I will consider more carefully
the phenomenon of the rigidity of proper names compared with the accidentality
of definite descriptions.
A
proper name like Columbus applies to the same referent in any possible world
where Columbus exists, differently from the description ‘the first European to
set foot in Hispaniola’. But how can we explain this curious phenomenon? For
those sympathetic to the solution attributed to Mill, the explanation is
obvious. It comes from the idea that descriptions refer indirectly, by
connoting attributes of objects, while proper names refer directly to their
bearers as if they were labels that had been pinned to them. This fact makes
the references of proper names independent of the many descriptively
representable properties of their bearers. It seems as if the act of referring
were a kind of sorcery by means of which an
object could be directly connected to its name.
Kripke
thinks in kindred but more sophisticated ways. As in Mill’s case, proper names
also refer to their objects without connotative intermediaries like
descriptions of identifying properties. This alone should explain why, unlike
definite descriptions, the objects of reference of proper names remain the same
in any possible world. There is, however, an ontological question to be
considered here. Which would be the specific entities to be used as identifiers
for the reference of proper names? Kripke considers two possible alternatives,
creating what he considers a false dilemma. As he writes:
What I deny is that a particular is nothing but
a ‘bundle of qualities,’ whatever that may mean. If a quality is an abstract
object, a bundle of qualities is an object of an even higher degree of
abstraction, not a particular. Philosophers have come to the opposite view
through a false dilemma: they have asked: are these objects behind the bundle of qualities, or is
the object nothing but the bundle?
Neither is the case: this table is wooden, brown, in the room, etc. It has all
these properties, and it is not a thing without properties, behind them. But it
should not therefore be identified with the set or ‘bundle’ of its properties,
nor with the subset of its essential properties. (1980: 52)
Indeed, the dilemma as he poses it isn’t
acceptable: individuals (particulars) are neither bundles of abstract
properties without possible individuation criteria, nor bare particulars, which
should be accepted as unknowable naked substrates. But in the end, Kripke
rejects the dilemma simply by assuming that there is no matter of fact in it:
individuals are simply given to us like the brown wooden table in the room.
Accepting that there is no alternative, he just asks us to accept that we
identify individuals as what they are without requiring any further ontological
explanation: it simply happens.
Kripke’s solution, however, sounds like a clear shortcut: a magical way
to justify reference, which solves the problem by rejecting its existence
without giving sufficient reasons.[10]
It defies our more commonsensical way to avoid magic, which would be the search
for an explanation that assumes that the identification of individuals happens
in some way by our usually tacit recognition of the right object-identifying
spatiotemporally located properties, whatever they may be. Indeed, when we
think that there might be criterial identification rules descriptively ordering
the valid combinations of object-identifying properties, we begin to see that
not all doors are closed.
If
there were no other ontological alternative, Kripke’s answer would be
admissible, and our dissatisfaction with it could be qualified as an
anthropological, rather than an ontological problem. However, there is an
alternative! It consists in adopting the emerging ontology of tropes. This seems clearly the most
reasonable way to avoid the dilemma, and, although this ontology was already
present at the time Kripke developed his ideas, but only today is it more
widely appreciated.[11]
Since it will be useful later, as an explanation for the applicability of
criterial rules attached to definite descriptions, I will make a short
digression, explaining the essentials of an ontological view that might be the
most important ontological alternative after more than a thousand years of
endless realist and nominalist discussions.
Trope
theory is a radically new empiricist one-category ontology, first introduced by
Donald Williams.[12] According to him, “any
possible world, and hence, of course, this one, is completely constituted by
its tropes” (2018: 28). But what are tropes? Tropes are what Williams called abstract
particulars: they are what is left behind when we sort out one or more
spatiotemporally given properties of an individual, separating them from all
the others (2018: 27). Thus, the redness, the smoothness, the shape, and the
fragrance of a rose picked up by me are tropes. But the rose is not a trope,
since it is an individual, a concrete particular: it is constituted by its
tropes. The too obvious existence of tropes is made clearer by the fact that
they are objects of selective attention: if you are on the beach, you can pay
attention to the colors of the sea, the forms of the waves, their sounds, the
local temperature, and these are all tropes (Loux 1988: 81). As Williams also
wrote, not only are physical qualities, geometrical forms, and relational
properties tropes, but also events and processes, like a smile, a sneeze, a
scream, a cold snap, a storm, a conspiracy… a musical performance… and, as he
also wrote, not only Mary’s figure but also her complexion and digestion… There
are also psychological tropes, like an acute pain, feelings of love, sorrow,
and pleasure, as much as mental acts, thought-processes, dispositions, beliefs,
moral decisions, desires, purposes... Socrates’ wisdom and Mary’s beauty, he
wrote, are all tropes. And there are also mixed tropes (partly conscious and
partly behavioral) such as a love affair, an act of constriction, or a piece of
impudence. (Williams 2018: 30-38) Abstract particulars or tropes are to be
contrasted with concrete particulars, the wholes that are the
individuals, most often material objects, which he sees as also totally
constituted by their tropes. Thus, for Williams the rose, Socrates, Mary, a
household, a nation, the humanity, are not tropes (2018: 38).
Like
many theorists, I prefer to define “abstract particulars” or tropes as any
spatiotemporally localizable properties in the widest sense of the word,
since this understanding gives more clarity to the ubiquitous ontological goals
of trope ontology. All the above-given examples of tropes can be viewed as
properties, insofar as we can predicatively attach them to individuals. Thus,
Socrates’ wisdom and Mary’s beauty are non-relational properties of these
persons, a musical performance and a conspiracy can be respectively seen as
processual properties of an orchestra and a society. A love affair is a
relational causal property between two human beings, and a psychological
process of thought can be seen as a property of a person.
The
decisive difference between trope theory and traditional realist two-category
ontologies is that according to (Platonic or Aristotelian) realism a property
is an abstract, general, non-spatio-temporal entity, able to be instantiated in
many spatiotemporally existent individuals while strangely remaining one and
the same, whereas for a trope theorist a property-trope is usually a
spatiotemporally localizable constituent of a spatiotemporal individual. A
decisive difference between trope theory and nominalism is that according to
the first one predicates have proper references, which are tropical properties.
Considering tropes as spatiotemporally localizable properties, we can easily
extend the view to the basic forces of nature, which can be seen as dispersed
localizable properties.[13]
This is not so easy when we consider things apparently abstract in the Platonic
sense, like numbers. But even in this case, considering that numbers are
experientially learned in applied mathematics, they can possibly also be seen
as tropes. Consider, for instance, a book that I take from a shelf. I see that
it is just one book. It is true that I cannot see this applied number
one. But I reach this conclusion by means of sensory-perceptual experience, and
this number one seems to be localizable when I ask you how many books I am
holding. If on a dark night someone looks at the Via Lactea and says, “I am
looking at the Three Sisters, Alnitak, Alnilam, and Mintaka… maybe they still
exist”, the applied number three results from counting and seems to be localizable
there and not elsewhere. Therefore, it also seems possible to treat an applied
number one as a higher-order non-sensible but localizable property or trope,
though depending upon sensible properties, in a way that recalls the
Frege-Russell treatment of the property of existence. If a similar view could
be extended to abstract mathematics, we could solve an old puzzle, which is the
possibility of applying abstract mathematics to the physical world, since they
would not be categorially distinct. (For a sketch explaining how we
could reduce abstract numbers to tropes, see the Appendix of the present book).
It is
clear to me that trope theory is an attempt to salvage our common-sense concept
of property, which can be seen as having for too long been corrupted by
philosophers. Consider the following: When asked what a property is, ordinary
persons will not point to abstract properties; they will naturally begin by
pointing to things belonging to their surroundings, like the hardness of the
table or the blueness of the sky, and not by mentioning some directly cognizable
abstract entity, assuming that this is possible.[14]
For this reason, in this book tropes will also be called tropical properties,
t-properties, or simply properties.
Trope
theory has its own ontological ways to build material objects and universals.
Accordingly, individuals such as physical-material objects no longer need to be
identified with sets of abstract properties. These objects are diversely
organized compositions of concurrent
(i.e., suitably co-temporal, co-located) tropical properties (Williams
2018: 28-29).[15] Such tropes have nothing
to do with the problematic abstract-general properties (building those ‘still
more abstract bundles of qualities’) targeted by Kripke’s criticism since trope
theory identifies universals with sets or classes of tropes precisely
similar (qualitatively identical) to each other (Williams 2018: 29). It is
true that this last suggestion from Williams was criticized because it could
possibly multiply tropes by adding tropes of precise similarity between two
tropes of precise similarity, since they are also precisely similar to each
other, and so on infinitely (Campbell 1990: 32 f.). However, in my view, as it
stands Williams’ suggestion is inadequate for another reason, namely because we
usually do not have any cognitive access to such sets or classes of tropes,
which can have immense and changeable sizes, while universals have no magnitude
and no size. To circumvent the demand for cognitive access to immense and
changeable sets of tropes and other difficulties, I prefer to think that from
the viewpoint of trope theory the universal can be seen as consisting of any randomly chosen trope T, or any other
trope precisely similar to T
(Costa 2018: 165). From this operation, we could derive sets, of course,
though this is not necessary when we consider a property as something enabling
us to say one of many, which is the cognitive-linguistic function of the
universal. We do not need to stuff our heads with innumerable samples of red
when thinking of the universal of redness.
Trope
ontology is a metaphysical theory. But from a linguistic perspective tropes,
complexes of tropes, and the bundles of tropes constituting material objects
could in principle be identified by means of criterial identification rules
able to be expressed by means of descriptions, so that spatiotemporally
given properties of individuals could satisfy the criteria demanded by those
rules.[16]
Therefore, at least in principle, we have in our hands the instrument for an
auspicious response to the Kripkian objection that there is no set or sub-set
of essential properties to be identified with the object.
A
trope-theoretical ontological alternative would also fit very well with what
Kripke should mean in the quoted passage where he identifies a table as (having
the spatio-temporally located properties of) “being wooden, brown, in the room,
etc.”. Kripke could not consider trope theory, because in the 1960s, when he
developed his ideas, this theory was still largely ignored. Moreover, it would
have been of no value to his theory of reference, since trope theory seems to
conform much better to some version of descriptivism that picks out properties
based on their satisfaction of criterial rules expressed by definite
descriptions. After all, if the object referred to by a proper name is
something like a more or a less organized composition of compresent tropes, it
seems that the way a proper name refers to it must be by identifying changeable
appropriately chosen tropes or combinations of tropes by means of which a
singular object can be selected by us and distinguished from all others. These variable
individuating tropes and their combinations, in turn, would eventually be able
to satisfy the criterial conditions required by the identification rule (Ernst
Tugendhat’s Identifikationsregel)
belonging to the proper name and in some way able to be expressed by definite
descriptions. We will see in the next chapter how this kind of rule can be
effectively constructed.
3. Baptism and the causal-historical chain
The next question is how Kripke explains the
attribution of names to their bearers without the intermediation of
descriptions connoting their individuating properties (1980: 88-97). The answer
he offers is based on his picture[17]
of the referential relation, according to which a proper name gains its
reference to its bearer through an appropriate causal-historical and
communication chain. Here is how he presented his view[18]:
A rough statement of a theory might be the
following: An initial ‘baptism’ takes place. Here the object may be named by
ostension, or the reference of the name may be fixed by a description. When the
name is passed ‘from link to link’ the receiver of the name must, I think, intend when he learns it, to use the
name with the same reference as the man from whom he heard it. If I hear the
name ‘Napoleon’ and decide it would be a nice name for my pet aardvark, I do
not satisfy this condition. (My italics) (1980: 96)[19]
There are two stages here: first that of reference
fixing, then that of reference maintenance and transmission.[20]
The reference fixing of the proper name is obtained by a process that he calls
baptism. There are two kinds of baptism: (i) by ostension, that is, the
baptizer indicates the object he is naming by means of acquaintance; (ii) the
baptizer refers to the object he is naming by means of a description.
The two kinds of baptism often occur together, for instance, “this newborn, the
son of Nicomachus, will be called ‘Aristotle’”, accompanied by a gesture.
There
are proper names that are introduced by a descriptive baptism without an
acquaintance, as Kripke himself acknowledged. He considered the case of the
proper name of an inferred object, such as the planet Neptune. The astronomer
Le Verrier calculated that there should be a previously unknown planet located
in a certain region of space, which would be responsible for deviations in the
orbital axis of Uranus. Le Verrier called this planet ‘Neptune’ even before he
located it in the sky, keeping in mind descriptions corresponding to its
approximate location and mass (1980: 79). Kripke also notes that the definite
description used to fix the reference does not commit us to
descriptivism, since it does not need to be synonymous with the name (1980:
96). It is even possible to be a wrong description, insofar as it picks out the
right bearer of the name.
After
baptism, a process begins that may be called reference maintenance and
transmission: the name of the referred object is transmitted from speaker to
speaker in a causal-historical-communication chain.
Kripke’s causal-historical view has major implications. It means that if
I now write the name ‘Aristotle’ it is because this name appears at the end of
an immensely complex causal-historical chain that began when someone for the
first time baptized the newborn Aristotle with that name in 384 BC in Stagira.
If my writing of the name ‘Aristotle’ now came at the end of a
causal-historical chain that began with the naming of the shipping magnate
Aristotle Onassis, this would be the wrong chain, and I would not be speaking
of the philosopher Aristotle. The condition for the correct reference of a
proper name must be its belonging to the right causal-historical chain, which must
have as a criterion the intention of speakers to refer to the same object
referred to by the baptizer. Finally, we should note that for Kripke the
first link of the causal-historical chain isn’t the bearer, but the baptism.
After all, a causal-historical chain can begin even with empty names that were
not ultimately caused by any bearer.
An
important question concerns the role of causality. Kripke assumes that the
historical chain that begins with the act of baptism is causal. However,
concerning the relationship between the object of reference and the act of
baptism, Kripke avoids a full commitment to causality, since he accepts
mathematical entities like the number p as non-causal bearers of proper names, along
with inactualia like Lauranda, the hypothetical girl who could have been
born if the sperm that fertilized the egg from Laura had fertilized the egg
that generated her sister Amanda. (See Hugues 2004: 45; Burgess 2013: 32).
Some
have tried to deflate the more controversial causal element by emphasizing the
historical-communicational web (e. g., Burgess 2013: 33). However, it is clear
that the historical-communicational chain must also be causal, since any
communication chain is causal, as much from the cognitive as from the physical
viewpoint.[21] Moreover, it remains
defensible that the relation between the baptizer and the object of reference
is also causal. Cognitive causality is a form of causality like any other.[22]
An informational-historical chain is also, physically considered, a causal
chain since there is no information without any physical correlatum. And
the relation between the first speaker, the baptizer, and the bearer of the
name can be plausibly always causal. It is true that if the baptizer is
having a hallucination, he is failing in referring to anything. But even if he
were baptizing his hallucination, it would be because of the causal effect of
the hallucination within his mind. Moreover, the potentially infinite number
3.141592… can be always further calculated and thought, and this can
already be a causal mental factor in the production of the name p.[23]
Furthermore, there is no problem in constructing the imaginary Lauranda, who
would then be a mental causal factor in our choice of her name. Consider,
finally, the case of the discovery of Neptune. It was the awareness of the
change in the axial orbit of Uranus, along with the knowledge of the laws of
gravity that causally produced in the mind of Le Verrier and others the
hypothesis that the planet is attracted by another planet, one that he called
‘Neptune’. It is not the kind of direct causation that involves observing
Neptune through a telescope, but it is, notwithstanding, a series of causal
relations. Even if causal input from the referent does not need to be
considered the first link of the causal chain (we will see that there are real
causal chains produced by empty names like Vulcan), some form of causality
must be involved in the formation of any non-empty proper name.
4. Some attempted
counterexamples
John Searle (1983: 238 f.) has pointed out
several difficulties in causal-historical theory by means of counterexamples,
showing that in some cases a causal-historical chain isn’t even necessary.
Here I am a bit more on Kripke’s side. Causality is an unavoidable element of
naming. In what follows, I will discuss some of these counterexamples, since I
find their exploration instructive.
A
first counterexample concerns names that do not seem to have any causal
relationship with their references. I want to start by considering two examples
given by Searle, for whom the cause of the proper name’s utterance by its
bearer does not seem to exist. First, knowing that there is a 5th
Avenue, we can infer that there is also a 4th Avenue, thus referring
to a street in New York that we have never heard of and that consequently
cannot be at the causal-historical origin of our utterance. The second example
concerns Pharaoh Ramses VIII. All we know about this hypothetical Pharaoh is
that his name would have to occupy the space after Ramses VII and before Ramses
IX. But with this information, we can already infer that Ramses VIII did exist,
without any causal-historical chain having reached us from his baptism.
To
these examples, it is possible to respond considering that what we call an
efficient cause is only what we see as a more relevant element of a distinctive
set of causal factors that constitutes a situation, a state of affairs, and
even an unified process, many of these factors being such that they can be
inferred as existing.[24]
Thus, knowing that 5th Avenue is the effective causal factor that is
at the origin of the causal chain that allows us to name it, and knowing that
parallel avenues are usually consecutively numbered, we infer that a 4th
Avenue must be part of an unified state of affairs constituted by a sequence of
numbered avenues assumed as associated causal factors, and, consequently, that
a 4th Avenue should probably also exist. Along with this, we also
conclude that 4th Avenue could potentially be a baptized cause of our
referential use of this name by means of acquaintance (which is not only
irrelevant to the theory of Baptism but can also be a false hypothesis).
Likewise, Ramses VII and Ramses IX are part of an unified causal process of
succession of pharaohs that of course should include Ramses VIII. This last
pharaoh, though unknown to us, is an element of the unified causal process that
contains the causal chains beginning with Ramses VII and Ramses IX, which
effectively reach us, allowing us to recognize Ramses VIII as an associated
unknown causal factor. It doesn’t matter that such causal factors are not part
of the efficient causal factors that reached us, like those initiated with the
baptism of 5th Avenue or of Ramses IX; important is that they must
have been part of the respective state of affairs and process that formed the
main complexes of causal factors that initiated the causal-historical chains
that have come down to us.
Other
examples are baptisms of things that will only exist in the future, such as the
hurricane called ‘Katrina’, which received this name before it came into
existence. The question is how it is possible to baptize something that will
occur in the future? For Kripke this would not be a problem since he does not
demand a causal relationship between the act of baptism and the reference.
Anyway, we still could find, as with the case of the planet Neptune, present
causal circumstances enabling us to predict the hurricane. I could add to this
the example of the planned city called ‘Brasília,’ which received this name in
1823, a name given by José Bonifácio de Andrada e Silva, who was the first to
propose moving the capital of Brazil to the dry and almost uninhabited interior
of the country. Only in 1956, by decision of President Juscelino Kubitschek,
did work begin on the new capital with the name Brasília. Causal circumstances
seem to be here out of question regarding the visionary idea of José Bonifácio.
But there is in fact no problem. The real name Brasilia was simply borrowed
from José Bonifácio, and the real causal circumstances were the decisions and
plans of Kubitsheck and his government to build the so-called new capital. We
can consider, finally, the baptism of things belonging to the remote past, for
instance, the ‘Snowball-Earth’. Geophysicists think that 650 million years ago
the Earth was totally covered by an icecap many hundred meters deep. Existing
geological evidence, combined with knowledge of laws causally lead scientists
to the conclusion that the earth was once frozen in a glacial ice age lasting
for millennia, and the baptismal name ‘Snowball-Earth’ was given by such causal
reasons, which generated a causal-historical chain preserving the name. Even
if, unlike the cases above, it is physically impossible to have any immediate,
direct physical acquaintance with something that occurred in the past, we can
still speak – in divergence from Kripke – of causal acts of baptism.
Another type of objection is one that results from the elaboration of
imaginary situations in which a causal-historical chain does not exist. Searle
envisioned a small linguistic community in which each proper name is
established indexically in the presence of all other speakers so that no causal
chain needs to develop (1983: 240).[25]
His argument demonstrates that under special circumstances a causal-historical
chain could be unnecessary. However, it does not prove that baptism has no
point, or that no external causal relation is necessary for the constitution of
the referential function of proper names.
It
seems plausible to conclude that Kripke’s positive doctrine ends up by being
reduced to two causal conditions regarding non-empty names: (i) the causal
condition of acquaintance with the bearer of the name, valid even for the
so-called abstract entities reconsidered by trope theory. (ii) the condition of
having circumstances causally producing a baptism. Both conditions can be
united in the following causal condition for the introduction of a proper name,
followed by some causal-historical-informational network (considering that
there is more than one only chain):
C-condition:
Effective referential introduction of a proper
name is only possible if:
(i) a baptism occurs as the consequence of some
kind of acquaintance producing a shared causal factor or a
causal-historical-informational network that preserves its name.
And/or if
(ii) there are circumstances somehow involving
a possible object of the name’s reference as something conceived; these
circumstances causally produce the awareness that would allow us to name an
object of reference, initiating a causal-historical-informational network that allow
us to give and preserve the name. In many cases (ii) can give place to (i).
Once we assume the ontology of tropes,
C-condition seems to be the most plausible way to think about what is true in
Kripke’s idea of an act of baptism and the subsequent causal-historical chain.
It starts causally and ends causally. However, the admission of C-condition has
a crucial limitation regarding our real goals: it does not mean the acceptance
that such causal network is able to give any useful or even principled
explanation or justification of proper names’ references, as will be made
gradually obvious in the sequence of this chapter.
We can
still ask if there are more resistant difficulties with the causal-historical
view, concerning references of proper names that turn out to be causally
inexplicable.
It
seems we can imagine situations where the successful referential use of a
proper name is possible, even without C-condition. Let’s say there is a
fortune-teller called Wanga who, gazing into her crystal ball, can guess proper
names she has never heard before, and inform us of all sorts of things about
their reference. She peers into her crystal ball and exclaims ‘Kamchatka!’,
referring to the many volcanoes on this remote peninsula. She looks again and
exclaims ‘Tom Castro!’, going on to talk about the life of this notorious
villain. If, after making all the conceivable tests, we did not discover any
trick, we would begin to suspect that she can tell all these details without
knowing them beforehand and without having to resort either to causal-historical
chains or to any circumstances that would enable her to infer the causes for
her assertions as to the existence of the bearers of the proper names. By
peering into the glass, she effectively refers (even if she resorts to
descriptions to prove her reference).
The
problem with this thought experiment is that even so, we would not abandon our
assumption that a name requires a causal connection with its reference to use
it referentially. Even if the causal relationship of what she sees is never
clarified by means of causal chains, this does not prove that they do not
exist. A final objection against this example is its extreme lack of
plausibility when we consider our known physical laws.
We can
try to conceive of an extreme situation: a possible world endowed with
pre-established harmony, in which people live like Leibnizian monads; they do
not need to learn the senses or references of proper names and communicate them
to each other to teach and learn their uses. Each person would have proper
names popping up in his or her mind, with an inexplicable agreement between the
senses and references that each person gave to each name; one person would utter
a proper name only to communicate something (apparently) contingent about its
bearer that other people still do not know. Nevertheless, this hypothesis seems
still more implausible than the last one. This is not how we use proper names
to refer in our world, nor are we able to imagine how that would occur in any
possible world where proper names could be used. We are interested in
explaining the reference of our proper names and not in the reference of
something called ‘proper names’ in a wildly improbable Leibnizian world.
It
seems that none of the objections considered so far is strong enough to
discredit the causal-informational or causal-historical aspect of naming’s attribution
as presented by the C-condition, even though this condition, as will be clear
later, must be interpreted in ways that considerably weaken Kripke’s original semantic
intuition of it as the royal road to explain reference. In fact, the
C-condition will be unmasked as a philosophical elaboration of the almost
trivial idea that the referential use of proper names invariably involves
causal relation, notwithstanding how indirect.
5. Coincidental
reference
There are still possible examples that at first
glance seem to resist the idea that the C-condition is indispensable to their
reference: they concern what we might call purely
coincidental references.
Consider the following imaginary case of a proper name with no causal
relationship to its reference. In an insane asylum in Georgia, an inmate dreams
that there is a volcano named Osorno on the border of a lake in southern Chile.
He even draws a picture of a snow-covered volcano and is convinced of its
existence. Indeed, as a matter of fact, there is a beautiful volcano called
Osorno with those characteristics in that region. But suppose that there is
absolutely no causal relationship between the name that appeared in the dream
and the volcano. This would be a case of merely coincidental reference.
To
give a more detailed example, let us say that a teenager called Jaime, who
likes to play childish games, knows a girl named Elaine very well. Suppose now
that he creates a name, ‘Ivny,’ for a crockery doll he imagines belongs to
Elaine, adding to his story that the doll was given to her when she was younger
and that she has stored it in the back of a wardrobe. By mere guesswork, Jaime
has already produced a considerable group of merely invented descriptions which
he associates with the name ‘Ivny.’ Let’s just suppose that by an incredible
coincidence his guesses turn out to be correct. In that case, could we say that
Jaime has referred to Ivny? Shouldn’t we admit that he has referred to that
doll, even if only by an absurd coincidence? It seems it would be possible to
claim that the name ‘Ivny’ has a descriptive meaning, a Fregean sense, and that
therefore it would even be possible to determine its reference in this way. In
this case, the conclusion seems to be that, although there is no causal
chain between the object and the utterance of its name, there is a
coincidental reference, and this reference is authentic.
This
phenomenon seems to be even more convincing if it is found in indexical
utterances. Suppose that Mary is blindfolded and tries to guess what was placed
on the table in front of her by saying:
1. There is a flowerpot on this table.
Suppose that by pure chance she hits on the
truth: a flowerpot was placed on the table. Does Mary, when guessing, thinking,
and saying the sentence (1), correctly refer to the flowerpot on the table?
Favoring this conclusion, it should be remembered that the sentence is true;
since it is true, Mary seems to have truly referred to the flowerpot.
Nonetheless, an advocate of an indispensable causal relation between the
act of naming and its reference might with good reasons reply that in these
cases there is confusion. In the case of the mentally disturbed inmate of an
asylum, his judgment is impaired, and one can find neither internal nor
external reasonable justifications for his application of the name in a true
statement. In the case of Jaime, the name gains reference only for those who
already know there is a doll in the wardrobe and only afterward for Jaime,
since his guess wasn’t backed by any justification; this is the only reason the
name ‘Ivny’ seems to have reference in the mouth of Jaime before Elaine’s
agreement with its truth. And in the case of Mary, she herself does not know that the sentence is true,
because although the thought expressed by the sentence is in fact true, it is
only true for witnesses, for example, an interpreter who hears the sentence and
compares the thought it expresses with the corresponding fact, verifying its truth,
which gives us the illusory impression that Mary could be successful in
referring.[26] It might be that we have
the impression that in this case, as in the previous one, the reference is
made, albeit in a purely coincidental way. But this impression would be nothing
beyond the kind of linguistic puzzlement often pointed out by Wittgenstein as a
philosophical trap (1984b sec. 116-133).
In the
face of these considerations, we conclude that a non-causal purely coincidental
reference is merely an illusory form of reference. It is as unreal as a name
engraved on a stone in an isolated region, which by chance is the same as the
name of a traveler who happened to find and read it. A representational process
is causal in nature, however indirect this relationship may be. Reference is an
association we make between the word and the world, and this association must
inevitably involve some form of causation from world to word and, as one could
complementarily add, some form of intention from word to world.
7. Internal
problems
Now I want
to move on to a critical analysis of the Kripkian approach, beginning by
considering some internal difficulties of his causal-historical theory of
reference.
The first problem concerns what we could
call intentional emptiness. In the passage where Kripke introduces his
idea of the causal-historical-communication chain, he explicitly resorts to at
least one intention, which is “to use the name with the same reference as the man from whom he heard
it.” This intention serves to select and preserve the object referred to in the
communication link of the causal-historical chain as being the same, both for
the speaker and for the hearer (Kripke 1980: 91, 96).[27]
However, there is a problem here. It seems unavoidable that the intention to
use the name with the same reference must include cognitive contents to
preserve this same reference. It must have some more intentional content. If a
hearer uses the name ‘Aristotle’, preserving the intention of referring to “the
baby born in 384 BC, son of Nicomachus, the physician of Macedon’s court”, this
makes sense. Furthermore, the degree to which this intention succeeds in
preserving the same reference must correspond to the degree to which it
includes relevant cognitive contents associated with the name. If I say, for
instance: “I will use the name of Aristotle, preserving your intention to refer
to the person who was born in 384 BC in Stagira, son of Nicomachus, the physician
in the court of Amyntas II, who crossed the Aegean Sea to meet Plato in Athens
and later wrote the Aristotelian opus”, I will have a much better chance of
preserving the same referent than if my intention were only to refer to someone
born in 384 BC. These considerations seem to lead directly to a falling back into descriptivism, simply because these
intentional contents are already those that, to be interpersonally accessible
and efficient, must be expressed through descriptions. But if so, descriptivism
emerges from the heart of the Kripkian causal-historical view, ruining the
supposed advantage of his picture.
One
can try to circumvent the problem of intentional emptiness by suggesting that
the relevant intention is only one of preserving the same reference
independently of being able to conceive anything like tropical properties
externally or internally associated with its intentional object. Nonetheless,
if the hearer does not need to have any idea of what the speaker’s intention
might be, then the intention of referring to the same object with the same name
is reduced to an arbitrary wager. It would be as if someone says, “I am going
to buy the same things you bought, but you don’t need to tell me what you
bought” – which expresses an empty intention that serves no purpose. Or suppose
that an inebriated gambler says before placing his bet in playing roulette: “I
do not know the number you chose when you won, but now I have the intention to
bet on the same number, whatever it may be!” Such a statement would be a
blunder, since the intention to refer to the same thing without knowing
anything about it is empty, and its explanatory power is null (another term for
this could be ‘wishful thinking’). Moreover, if “to have the same intention”
means an intention empty of content, this cannot prevent all kinds of errors
concerning the right referent: I can intend to refer to the same Aristotle you
are referring imagining that Aristotle is the name of a prime number. It
would not be of any help if, asked who Aristotle was, someone gave the answer:
“You, follow the same causal chain I am following when I utter the name
‘Aristotle’... but don’t forget to have the intention of referring to the same
person I am referring to”.[28]
An empty intention is no intention.
The
conclusion is that if Kripke wished to be fully consequential in his
anti-descriptivism, he should drop the demand of intentionality. This means
that his causal-historical chain should be solely what Searle called an external
one, in the sense of a third person accessible physical chain.
A
minor but telling difficulty concerns change in reference. Gareth Evans
formulated an interesting counterexample to the causal-historical view, which
concerns the proper name ‘Madagascar’ (Evans 1973: 11). According to him, the
name ‘Madagascar’ was once used to refer to the easternmost region of the
African continent. But when Marco Polo visited that region, an incorrect
translation led him to think that Madagascar was the name of the great island
situated near the east coast of Africa. Later, due to Marco Polo’s accounts,
people came to call the island itself Madagascar, forgetting the original
reference. Certainly, if the name’s reference were fixed only by appeal to an
initial baptism, this change could not have occurred. Marco Polo surely also intended
to refer to the same thing as the person from whom he first heard the proper
name and not to introduce a new reference for the same name; but since the
intentional content was misleading, the reference changed.
An
answer to this type of objection was suggested by Michael Devitt. According to
him, the meaning of a proper name does not have to do with the reference
itself, but with the ability to designate an object. (1981: 2.1-2.3)
This ability, or habit, is seldom acquired from a single baptism, but more
often from many, in a process called by him multiple
grounding. Thus, the name Madagascar had been fixed through multiple
baptisms as an eastern region of the African continent, until it was
inadvertently renamed by Marco Polo. If Polo and his auditors subsequently
referred again and again to the island, the multiple grounding came into
effect, forming a new habit of referring, and thereby giving a different sense
to the name.
This
appeal to multiple grounding which creates a habit or custom seems in some
cases to really occur. Consider the case of an encampment of diamond seekers
that is called ‘tents’ because people standing on the mountains around it could
only see the many tents below. With the passage of time, the encampment grew
into a village, which then received the official name of ‘Tents’ (a kind of
postponed baptism). However, this cannot be generalized. We can suppose that Marco
Polo confused Madagascar with the island and, later, when he was in prison, he
dictated this error to the writer of the book Il Milione. They didn’t
afterward need any multiple grounding to spread the new name. Aristotle also,
after his baptism, would not have it reinforced by having his name repeated.
Repeating is not like renaming.
Kripke
himself (1980: 163, Appendix) gave the most convincing answer. For him, an
intention, in this case, Marco Polo’s intention to refer to an island, overcomes the intentions of past users
of the name and establishes a new social practice. His intention gave the
proper name a new meaning and a new reference. The change of reference,
therefore, turns out to be a mere case of homonyms. Although this response may
be more appropriate, it inevitably suffers from camouflaged descriptivism by
reflecting a new element of cognitive intention. After all, Marco Polo’s
intention to refer to the island must be able to be expressed by a definite
localizing description such as ‘the great sub-equatorial island near the
eastern coast of the African continent’, since he could have had something like
that in mind.
A
descriptivist would have no difficulty with Evans’ example. There were indeed
two occasions on which identifying-localizing descriptions were created. The
first is the reference to ‘Madagascar’ as ‘the eastern region of Africa,’ which
could have been maintained and increased by local people over a long period of
time. On the second occasion, Marco Polo unwittingly called ‘the great
sub-equatorial island near the eastern coast of Africa’ ‘Madagascar’,
introducing a homonym with a new localizing description.
Another
counterexample from Evans concerns two babies, one baptized as Jack, and the
other baptized as John, which were accidentally switched by a nurse. The nurse
mistakenly gave John to Jack’s mother, and Jack to John’s mother, The
respective parents did not notice the switch and they and their relatives
simply continued calling their child by the wrong name. If causal-historical view
were correct, the boys would always be known by the name that was used for
them, despite the original baptism under a different name. The best Kripkian
answer is to accept a less strict idea of baptism. John was unwittingly
rebaptized as Jack by his parents, giving rise to a much more extended
causal-historical chain.
An
additional difficulty, which I want to briefly consider, concerns the meanings
of more than one proper name of the same bearer. There are cases where these
proper names have the same informative content (e.g., “Everyone calls Beatrice Bia”). But there are cases where
the informative content differs. For instance, Father Marcial Maciel was the
founder of the Legionnaires of Christ order and unfortunately also a scoundrel.
Among his many illegal activities was the use of false identities. One of them
was that of Raúl Rivas, an alias with which he claimed to be a Shell employee
and CIA agent. In 1976 Rivas met Blanca Gutiérrez, a naive woman who fell in
love with him, knowing him only as Raúl Rivas and fully unaware of his true
biography. Rivas had two children with her without her having discovered his
secret identity. The informative contents of the names ‘Marcial Maciel’ and
‘Raúl Rivas’ are certainly very diverse, although they referred to the same
person.
Cluster theory would find no problem in explaining this difference. A
supporter of this theory would say that the set of descriptions abbreviated by
the false name Raúl Rivas would have been publicly regarded as being completely
different from the set of descriptions abbreviated by his real name, which is
why their meanings were seen as so diverse. All that occurred is that later it
was discovered that the first set of descriptions was only a subset of the second one; that is, the
meaning-content given by the sub-cluster of descriptions associated with the
false name Raúl Rivas was part
of a more complete meaning-content, namely, that of the entire cluster of
descriptions to be associated with the original name Marcial Maciel. This
explains not only why the two identities belonged to the same person, but also
why it was possible for Blanca Gutiérrez not to know that they were the same
person: she was only aware of the cluster associated with Raúl Rivas.
It
does not seem impossible to find an explanation for what happened from the
perspective of the causal-historical view, though it lacks convincing power.
Supposing that the source of the referential function is the act of baptism,
then we can imagine that there were two different acts, one of them was the
original baptism of Marcial Maciel, while the other was the baptism that
Marcial Maciel gave to himself under the alias of Raúl Rivas, which he used
with Blanca Gutiérrez. One could now object that in this case we no longer have
any intrinsic reason to say that the two names do not refer to the same object.
However, the causal-referentialist can still hope to answer this objection by
remembering that, although the baptismal acts of the two names had the same
referent, the imposter only told Blanca Gutiérrez of the causal chain
associated with his identity as the self-baptized Raúl Rivas. He concealed his
other pseudonym and identity because he wanted her to only refer to him using
this alias. He concealed from her the causal-historical chain initiated by the
baptism of Marcial Maciel with the intention that this name should be used in
referring to him.
Even
so, the causal-referentialist will find persisting problems. How could the
causal-historical view be able to explain that Raúl Rivas and Marcial Maciel
were in fact the same person? How could the causal-historical view explain why
Blanca didn’t become aware that Raúl Rivas was Marcial Maciel, considering that
the two baptisms were of rigid designators of the same bearer, who stood there
in front of her? (“Raúl Rivas = Marcial Maciel” is a necessary identity.) How
could she only much later come to the shocking discovery that Raúl Rivas was in
fact the same person as Marcial Maciel, by means of information and cognitive
awareness communicable by descriptions? By now it begins to be clear that a
causal-historical theory based upon baptism is quite incapable of standing
alone.
8. The radically consequent Kripkian automaton
Several authors have objected
that referentialist views have been unable to give an adequate account of the
relation between semantics and psychology. As Francesco Orilia wrote:
…a complete
semantic theory must be, say, cognitivist, i.e., capable of going hand in hand
with a plausible psychological account of mental processes that are involved in
the generation or interpretation of a linguistic token and of the mental
representations that such processes give rise to. (2010: 5).
The aim of this section is to show the
indispensability of the debased cognitive-representational and potentially
descriptive element by means of a reductio ad absurdum. For this, we
need to draw on the idea of what one could call a complete Kripkian automaton.
This would be an automaton capable of creating and using proper names
satisfying Kripke’s anti-cognitivist causalism in a fully consequent way. It is
complete in the sense that it does not run any risk of implying descriptivism,
since it does not need to satisfy even the requirement of the intention to use
words with the same reference as the other automatons of the same kind in any
cognitive sense of the word ‘intention.’ It is, therefore, a primitive
mechanism, devoid of any form of mind or consciousness, but still capable of
“identifying” people through their photoelectric sensors and “baptizing” them
with “proper names”. Imagine now a “society” of these automatons. They would be
able to retain images and behavioral traits of the persons they have “baptized”
with proper names like ‘Rwzf’, and even transmit them to other similar
automatons, relating them to the same bearers (the physical mechanism can be
here called “K-intentionality”), in this way “communicating” them. This would
enable them to repeat the person’s “name” when they “see” its bearer, or when
appropriately “asked” about what a person with such and such characteristics is
called. It seems that the reference mechanism is reduced here to a purely
external causal-historical chain,
that is, to a third-person accessible causal chain devoid of any psychological
content.
What
is interesting about this thought experiment is that it makes evident how
unconvincing the act of referring becomes in the absence of any truly cognitive
element. We do not really understand how it is possible for a complete Kripkian
automaton to really refer in the proper sense of the word. Words such as
‘denotation’, ‘name’, ‘identification’, ‘reference’, ‘K-intention’,
‘communication’, ‘seeing’, ‘society’, were all applied with quotation marks due
to the simplified and analogical use that was made of them. What these
automatons would be able to do would only produce mechanical imitations of the referential processes
that take place in our conscious minds, which is demonstrated by their almost
complete lack of flexibility, inferential complexity, and behavioral
sophistication.
Imagine, however, that there are no longer complete Kripkian automata,
but instead extremely sophisticated androids, such as those appearing in Steven
Spielberg’s popular film A.I. Artificial Intelligence: they can
perfectly share our way of life, learn all the details of our natural language,
using our own names as correctly and competently as we ourselves do. In that
case, we would no longer be prone to consider their acts as naming terminal
links of purely external causal chains. By analogy with ourselves, it will be
inevitable to attribute mental capability to them. That is, we would be
compelled to treat some unknown nodal points of their external causal pathways
as internally describable in psychological terms such as cognitions,
representations, and intentions.
After
all, we cannot prevent ourselves from identifying the consciousness of others
by analogy with our own.[29]
We are not able to imagine that androids completely devoid of consciousness
would be able to speak and behave in the same way as human beings. Even if they
came to talk to us, trying to convince us that they were completely devoid of
consciousness, not really possessing thoughts, having no intentions, no will,
we would not believe such statements, for they would sound ridiculously
incoherent. We would be irresistibly persuaded to endow them with
consciousness.
It
seems that if we want to use proper names, other users can tell us by
themselves something about their references. External third-person processes,
like neuro-physiological ones, will have to be so elaborate that they will
inevitably appear to us to have the form of internal psychological processes.
However, in them the cognitive-representational-intentional element must have a
preponderant role, forcing us to return to the initially rejected assumption of
the necessity of a descriptively explicable cognitive constituent.
9. Empty and imaginary
names
A resilient problem left insufficiently
explained by the causal-historical theory concerns empty proper names. Here are
some examples:
1. Vulcan
2. Eldorado
3. Zeus
4. Rumpelstiltskin
5. Gandalf
6. Urville
There is an important difference between the
names from (1) to (3) and from (4) to (6). Only the first three are empty
proper names in the full sense of the word. They are what we could call
proper names of non-existent real objects. They are meant to be applied to
references belonging to the domain of our real world (the first because they
are empirically empty, the other two because of their mythological character).
The last three are proper names of merely
fictional (imaginary) objects.
They are not empty insofar as they are applied to referents belonging to the
proper fictional or imaginary domain, where they were conceived to be applied.
They only appear empty if they are misleadingly seen as applying to references
belonging to the domain of the real world.
None
of these examples of proper names constitutes a problem for descriptivist
theories. The first three do not, because their status as proper names depends
on their descriptive meanings and not upon the existence of referents in the
domain of our real world. After all, for descriptivists, what constitutes the
status of a proper name, its referential function, its meaning, belongs to the
modes of presentation given by its associated descriptions, not the ultimate
success of its referential function. About the last three proper names, they
are also abbreviations of descriptions that give them their meanings, making
them able to refer in fictional worlds which recombine elements of our own,
where they can appear as terms in true (ex: “Gandalf was a wizard”) or false
(ex: “Rumpelstiltskin was a dwarf”) statements, insofar as they are consistent
with these imaginary recombinations.
However, the admission of names without a reference can be a real
problem for causalist-referentialist theories, which tend to make the status of
a proper name dependent on its reference, leaving aside the problem of its
signification.[30] Anyway, Kripkian
referentialists would have the means to invent strategies to save the
causal-historical theory of proper names belonging to a fictional domain.[31]
They could easily suggest that fictional names like Rumpelstiltskin, Gandalf,
and Urville, were respectively “baptized” by their creators, who were
respectively the Brothers Grimm, J. R. R. Tolkien, and Gilles Tréhin, which
would produce an informational causal chain. And, as was said, the baptismal
relation can be seen here as a causal-mental relationship belonging to
fictional worlds.
However, this solution would open the doors
to the objection that no matter what kind of “baptism” is performed, a petitio
principii haunts the causal-referentialist. Such characters can only be
identified by those who know their roles in the fictional stories. Only with
the help of cognitive descriptions of these characters, their intentions, their
actions, are people able identify them and understand their places in the
respective fictional worlds. Since all these things must be described, it seems
that the causal-historical theorist must here assume the priority of
descriptivism in a wide-open way. I say it is worse, because the possibility of
an automatic or tacit form of tagging or baptism – still conceivable in our
real life-world – would be excluded in these fictional worlds.
A greater problem for causal-historical
referentialists, however, concerns what I call proper names of non-existent
real objects[32], like ‘Vulcan’,
‘Eldorado’, and ‘Zeus’. If they do not have references, it also seems that they
will never be able to be really tagged or baptized. They cannot have a direct
referential causal function, which seems to deflate their significance as real proper
names. There is an extensive debate about these issues among referentialists,
whose discussion would lead us too far from our present intentions.[33] Along
causal-historical lines, however, the most auspicious answer to the problem
departs from remembering that the first link of the causal-historical chain is
not the object referred to, but the baptism itself. If this is so, then the act
of baptism, even though it can be empty, is already sufficient to produce a
causal-historical chain... Thus, as Keith Donnellan brilliantly suggested, the
empty proper name is one whose historical explanation ends up by presenting
empty indications. As he wrote concerning a statement like “Santa Claus does
not exist”:
When the historical
explanation of the use of a name (with the intention to refer) ends in this way
with events that preclude any referent being identified, I will call it a
“block” in the history. (1974: 23)
The explanation for the
existence of Santa Claus ends up in a “block” because one cannot point to its
bearer in the actual world.
This answer is helpful in showing how the
C-condition works in the case of an empty name. However, the associated
Kripkean causal-historical view is not without problems. If the causal effect
of a given referent in the baptizer’s mind is indifferent to the
characterization of a proper name, how can we distinguish the historical chains
that start with a real reference from those chains that begin with empty
baptisms? Should the existence of some causal relationship between the referent
and the act of baptism not be essential to real naming, allowing the proper
name to pick out its reference in a way that justifies the all-important
property of rigidity? If not, would these empty names still deserve to be
called authentic proper names?
10.
Empty names descriptively understood
Instead of trying to figure out how the
defenders of the causal-historical view would answer questions like those
presented above, I wish to consider another referentialist response, according
to which empty names are not true proper names, but only disguised definite
descriptions. For an advocate of this view, if there is one[34],
since empty proper names are only disguised descriptions, they are made to
refer by means of a mechanism completely different from the direct
causal-historical baptismal way proper names usually refer. Consequently, they
do not deserve to be called real proper names, and empty proper names do not
really exist!
This
view is certainly, implausible and would be rejected by Kripke. However, I do
not choose to consider this view, because of its plausibility within the
causal-historical or referentialist framework. I do this here only as an
exercise for a better understanding of how empty proper names could be
interpreted from a descriptivist viewpoint – as a springboard to what
will be explained in the next chapter.[35]
What I wish to make clear is that a careful examination reveals that empty
proper names for real objects (just as much as proper names for fictional
objects) are too much like the most common proper names to force us to
distinguish seriously between the two cases – a conclusion that will favor
descriptivism concerning proper names.
First,
consider again examples (1) to (3). If we examine them more closely, we will
see that these names do not replace a single definite description, but a
variety of descriptions, leading us back to a cluster theory. In the case (1)
of Vulcan, it is the name of a small planet postulated by Urban Le Verrier in
the 19th century as orbiting about 21 million km from the Sun, to explain
changes in Mercury’s perihelion (which after 1915 were precisely explained by
general relativity theory). It is possible to replace this last sentence with a
single composite definite description, formulated to localize and characterize
a referent that in fact does not exist.
Examples (2) and (3) can be seen as proper names with more elaborate
informational content, not differing too much from what we expect from cluster
theories of proper names. The proper name (2) ‘Eldorado’ comes from various
indigenous accounts and rituals, which led the Spanish conquistadors to believe
that in some regions of the western Amazon there could be a city whose king
dressed in gold and possessed unbelievable riches. Based on these and other
localizing and characterizing descriptions, adventurers and explorers descended
to the mouth of the Amazon searching for it in vain and sometimes ending up as
feasts for cannibals. If an implausible place like Eldorado were found, it
would be because at least some of those descriptions of the cluster would
apply. Consider now (3): the name ‘Zeus’. He was considered in Antiquity to be
the ruler of all the gods on Mount Olympus, the sixth son of Chronos and Rea...
There is a whole range of localizing and characterizing descriptions that
mythology has associated with the name ‘Zeus’, which makes it a cluster not
very different from the clusters of our usual proper names.
Now
compare the functioning of the name ‘Eldorado’ with that of the name ‘Troy’. In
the latter case, all that was available was a very limited cluster of
localizing and characterizing descriptions taken from Homer’s Iliad. It was seen as a mythological
name. However, unlike the previous cases, the site of Troy was discovered in
modern Turkey by Heinrich Schliemann. As is well known, having taken seriously
the localizing descriptions, Frank Calvert indicated to Schliemann where he
could find the ruins of the historical city of Troy, which enabled him to
discover the site and build a well-grounded causal chain. What is the difference
between the name ‘Eldorado’, on one side, and the name ‘Troy,’ on the other? In
my view, only one thing: the former name is certainly empty, the latter not.
Other than that, they behave the same way. Therefore, a word like ‘Eldorado’ is
certainly a truly empty name, and a causal-historical theory does not seem very
apt to explain why it is rigid or why it seems informative and meaningful.
It is
true that the description clusters of the above examples are still poor and
uncertain if compared to those of common proper names such as Paris and
Aristotle. But this is not because these names are misleading descriptions. The
main reason is the simple fact that the
real bearers of the usual proper names persist in their complex causal
interaction with the world, often allowing us over time to accumulate
identifying information, continually enriching their clusters of descriptions.
In contrast, empty proper names are in a situation as fragile as that of the
planet Neptune shortly after the discovery of its existence by Le Verrier. None
of the considered examples adumbrates the necessity of postulating some
mysterious identification mechanism essentially different from what possibly
could be given by well-grounded definite descriptions supposedly demanding the
satisfaction of variable complexes of tropical properties. Furthermore, as we
will see with the proper name ‘Urville,’ poverty of descriptions is not an
unavoidable property of empty names.
Let us
now consider once more the fictional names (3) to (6), which, unlike (1) to
(3), are meant as referring to merely imaginary objects. Here we also have
often rich clusters of identifying descriptions of the object, only they are
not made to be applied to the real world but are limited to the domain of
objects that exist only in our imagination. ‘Rumpelstiltskin’ abbreviates the
identifying description of a greedy dwarf in a fairy tale, ‘Gandolf’
abbreviates detailed characterizing descriptions of a wise magician belonging
to the fictional world created by J. R. R. Tolkien. It seems clear that the
identification mechanisms remain similar. What changes is the domain of
application, which in these cases is the second-order domain of merely
fictional reality.
The
last case I would like to consider is that of (6): Urville. This city is
located in the southeast of France. It was founded in the year 1,100 BC by the
Phoenicians, was transformed into a city-state in the Middle Ages, and was
occupied by the Nazis during World War II... These are the main descriptions by
which we build the rule that enables us to locate the city in space and time.
Urville is also the largest city in Europe, the present capital of France, with
about 12 million inhabitants... These are only a very small part of the
uncommonly complex cluster of localizing and characterizing descriptions
constitutive of the criterial rule by means of which we are enabled to identify
Urville. The only problem is that Urville, obviously, does not exist. This city
is the product of the imagination of an autistic artist named Gilles Tréhin,
who for more than twenty years conceived and drew that city in its smallest
details. He created for the name ‘Urville’ a precise and extraordinarily
complex fictional cluster of descriptions that should work as its
identification rule. Although constructed in the most realistic possible way,
this rule does not apply to our actual world. It is as if it belonged to a
close possible world, in which history had undergone a small but significant
change: Urville in the place of Paris. The case of the proper name ‘Urville’
shows beyond any doubt that an empty proper name cannot simply be reduced to a
definite description, even to a composite one. Urville is an empty proper name
replacing an immensely complex cluster of descriptions, since realism was
Tréhin’s main aesthetic goal. Searle’s cluster theory would be at home
concerning Tréhin’s city: in a possible world where a sufficient but
undetermined number of localizing and characterizing descriptions associated
with the name ‘Urville’ were satisfied, the city would certainly exist.[36]
Finally, it is worth noting that localizing and characterizing
descriptions were present in all the examples of proper names given above. In
the next chapter, we will see that their place is fundamental in the
articulation of the proper meta-descriptive rule for proper names in general,
and why it must be so.
11. Causal chains and cognitive links
Even if I am convinced that some causal
relation satisfying the C-condition is indispensable for any given proper name
to have a reference, the crucial and until now unanswered question is that of
explanatory power. A fully consequent causal-historical theory should be able
to be fundamentally constructed without the admission of any psychological link
such as content-filled intentions, cognitions, conscious representations –
things that in general could be expressed as descriptions. But it does not seem
that the mere use of an external causal chain – that is, a causal chain
consisting only of interpersonally accessible elements like neurophysiological
phenomena, sound waves, bodily movements, etc. – could be sufficient to explain
the reference. Even if Kripke admits that we need to have the intention of
referring to the same object, we have already seen that to be fully consequent
we would need to reduce it to an intention to reproduce an unknown content,
which would be nothing more than a wager.
More
serious difficulties arise when we effectively try to explain or justify the
reference of a proper name through a purely external causal network. A first
difficulty is that there are countless causal chains to which we are
continually being exposed but whose final link can be anything but the
referential use of a proper name.[37]
How then can we identify the causal chain that has as its final link the
referential use of a proper name? How do we know, for example, that from an
eternal viewpoint the spelled word ‘White’ is being used as a person’s name and
not as the name of a color? How can we know that a person is using the proper
name ‘Aristotle’ correctly, as the last link of an appropriate causal-baptismal
chain? Let’s imagine that when first hearing the name ‘Aristotle,’ a schoolboy
concludes that the speaker wants to refer to a school in his city that bears
that name. How can we know that this is not the correct causal-historical chain
without resorting to cognitions-descriptions that we relate to Aristotle’s own
person? Imagine, giving wings to our imagination, that in the act of baptizing
Aristotle, the sounds of the words being uttered made a nearby mirror swing,
which because of this reflected a photon that crossed the stratosphere and sped
toward the Moon, from whence it was reflected back again, returning by chance
to the surface of the earth, where it was absorbed by a carbon atom in a field
of grain; suppose then that this tiny amount of energy remained stored in that
atom, even if it passed through the bodies of animals that were fed grain,
dancing about for millennia until the moment when it somehow contributed (very
slightly!) to the movement of the vocal cords of someone who uttered the name
‘Aristotle.’ Would this photon reflection be part of the causal chain that
caused the person to utter the name ‘Aristotle’? Certainly not!
We
have difficulty in seeing the physical absurdity of the issue, because we are
normally unaware of the fact that we are continuously immersed in an
inextricably complex causal ocean of interconnected events. That is, our
universe is an incredibly intricate causal network, where events are constantly
causing and being caused by other events on multiple sides and in myriads of
ways.[38]
Considering such an inconceivably complex ocean of external causal chains that
simultaneously occur and intersect, how
can we identify those responsible for a particular act of naming?
Suppose I utter the name ‘Aristotle’. It is undeniable that I can only
designate this philosopher if there is, within the indescribably intricate
causal ocean, an already vastly complex causal chain that (at least partially)
had its beginning in the act of baptism of the newborn Aristotle and that ended
with my current utterance of the name… However, just as certain as the very
existence of external causal-historical chains linking the first speaker (and,
we would add, the referent) with its name is the certainty that if searched
only in itself and by itself, this search would give us no clue for its
criterial identification, revealing the real chain as impossible to identify
and isolate from the innumerable other connections forming the incommensurately
vast causal network in which we are immersed. Now, is there any procedure that
allows us, at least in principle, to pick out some relevant causal link?
Although at first view the situation seems hopeless, we can imagine a
procedure for the identification of links of the relevant external causal chain
that can teach us something. It is based upon the assumption that there are
neurophysiological external causal links (those accessible to a third person)
that may also in some way be described in psychological terms, namely, as
coinciding with cognitions, representations, or intentions to designate a
single object. This would allow
us to locate some external neurophysiological causal links of a causal chain.
The trouble, however, is that the appeal to this resource makes it seemingly
inevitable that we should first identify cognitions (or internal
representations) in order to become able to perceive a correlation between
these cognitions and their physical third person counterpart in the form of
neurophysiological links of the external causal chain, whatever they may be.
Since these cognitions and communicable internal representations are typically
expressible through descriptions, if we admit that this is the proper way to
identify causal chains, it seems that we will end up committing ourselves to
some form of descriptivism. Hence, a way out of this commitment does not seem
humanly possible.
We can
also perform thought experiments helping us prove the conclusion that
cognitions and connected descriptions are inevitable for the identification of
correct causal chains. The first is the following: Imagine that a very powerful
brainscope is invented. This brainscope is a device able to identify when a
person A, an Aristotle-specialist, by remembering and saying the name
‘Aristotle’, articulates the final link of the correct causal chain by reading
the appropriate type[39]
of neurophysiological link in the neuronal behavior of A’s brain. With this
information, the brainscope will be able to tell us that another person B is
using the word ‘Aristotle’ in the final sequence of the correct causal chain,
simply by reading in B’s brain the same type of neurophysiological link as that
of person A. A problem emerges when we consider that it will only be possible
to know that the brainscope is reading the correct final causal link if both
speakers, A and B, agree that they are referring to the same Aristotle –
the philosopher – and not to another referent, like Aristotle Onassis or Greta
Garbo or, say, the Cheops pyramid (even if always uttering the same word
‘Aristotle’). This agreement, however, is cognitive and in the end descriptively
expressible. Worst of all, this agreement is the ultimate criterion for
the conclusion that the brainscope identified the correct final causal link. In
other words: the identification of the right neurophysiological type of causal
link will depend on cognition and the related descriptions, which shows a fatal
petitio principii in the explanatory
goal of Kripkian’s causal-historical referentialism.
An
example of psychological explanation can illustrate the same crucial point of
cognitive indispensability. Suppose I decide to buy a gift for a friend named
Kate to thank her for a favor. If someone asks me, “Why did you decide to buy
the gift?” I will answer, “I was feeling grateful for a favor she did for me.”
In this case, it is a decision at the psychological level, which is explained
by a feeling that is also psychological. Both the explicandum and the explicans
concern the same psychological level. But suppose it is possible to explain my
decision to buy the gift and my reason for making it by appealing to
neurophysiological processes in my brain corresponding to my feeling of
gratitude for the favor. Would this isolated explanation be appropriate to
explain and justify my decision to buy the gift? Surely not. For it can only be
considered appropriate if it is already known in advance that the
neurophysiological process in question coincides with the reason and decision
to buy the gift, and the feeling of gratitude can be explained as a reaction to
another person’s mental states and behaviors. In other words: an external
causal explanation of mental acts could only be justified to the extent that we
are able to translate it into some sort of supervening internal
causal-psychological explanation.
Something similar happens when we consider a possible explanation of the
reference by appealing to external causal chains as a whole: such explanations
will only make sense to the extent that some of their links are seen as
containing external correspondences to internal mental events. Taken by
themselves, external causal-historical networks are like shadows in the dark;
they are only able to tell us that proper names refer by means of causal
mechanisms, which is as true as it is worthless as an explanation.
Imagine now that nearly omniscient alien beings, while visiting our
planet, decided to study our linguistic praxis. Suppose they were able to
record all our communicative acts and identify the causal-historical chains
that lead us to utter our proper names in the most diverse contexts. It seems
reasonable to think that they would eventually become able to identify these
chains without recourse to our descriptions of cognitive-representational
links. This seems to suggest that a purely causal third person explanation is
logically possible. However, even this
suggestion would be illusory. After all, to identify our language as a proper
language, and our referential uses as such, the aliens would need to be aware
of our language by identifying in us cognitive-representational states
corresponding to those they themselves
would have. In other words, it will always be necessary to find patterns
consisting of cognitive-representative-intentional states at some previous
stage of the process, explicit or not, which for this reason are demonstrated
to be the true causative links interpretable in physicalist terms. Our
conclusion is that some cognitively given state must be the ultimate
criterion for the identification of external, third person causative links,
even though the latter are irreducible.
To sum
up, the central point of my criticism of Kripke’s causal-historical view is
that considered as an anti-descriptivist
attempt to explain reference, causal-historical referentialism inevitably ends
up begging the question, by demanding some kind of descriptive explanation.[40]
A purely external causal chain can always be appealed to, and we all know that
external causal chains are needed. But since the only satisfactory way to find
the links that would lead to the correct utterance of a proper name within an
external causal ocean is with the help of internal mental states, cognitions,
representations, intentions… which to be communicated, must be able to be
descriptively translated, one cannot avoid a descriptivist commitment.
The
foregoing considerations are not only true concerning possible
neurophysiological links, but also concerning occurrences in the external world
like someone baptizing a baby, Aquinas citing Aristotle, a professor teaching
about him, etc. Being necessary, but extremely meandering and independently
unachievable, these external causal chains are in themselves inscrutable. The
final conclusion is that if taken in themselves, these chains have
no explanatory power, being unable to justify our referential application of
any chosen proper name.[41]
Kripke’s positive view is, therefore, unable to explain how proper names refer.
12. Causal records
Should we conclude from the above arguments
that the appeal to external causal chains is always incapable of playing any
role in explaining reference? Not exactly. Although screening external causal
chains (sounds given in baptismal acts, specific effects on the brains of
participants, multiple resulting actions, etc.) is practically impossible, it
is often possible to identify what we might call a causal record, which can be characterized as the cognitively
recoverable relevant manifestations resulting from the
causal-historical-communicational chains initiated by the object of reference
of a proper name or at least relevantly related to it. Although the idea of a causal record
can include the causal chain initiated by a relevant baptism, almost all
recorded events related to the bearer of a proper name belong to its causal
record. Consider, for instance, the fourteen books of the Metaphysics and the remarkable historical fate of this work in
connection with the name ‘Aristotle’.[42]
The
idea of causal records leads us to see another important point, namely, that
the broadness of causal-historical chains associated with the bearer of a
proper name stretches far beyond a mere baptism. Consider, for example, the
name ‘Socrates’. Although we know he was born about 470 BC, we know nothing
about his baptism. What we know about Socrates is taken from the testimonies of
contemporaries who knew him personally, such as Plato, Xenophon, and
Aristophanes, who were later remembered in writings by Aristotle, and the minor
Socratics. We can discern in these reports causal records – relevant
manifestations – obviously resulting from causal-historical chains, which,
through many ramifications, have come down to us. Although we will never have
access to the causal occurrences associated with the real Socrates, we know the
causal repercussions that his acts and words had on the brains of Plato,
Aristotle, and the minor Socratics... which produced causal records that have
left permanent, memorable landmarks, such as the descriptions of Socrates’
trial and his condemnation to death, as reported in the Platonic dialogues Apology
and Phaedo. A definite description belonging to the causal record such
as ‘the Greek philosopher condemned to die by drinking poison hemlock’ in
association with the name ‘Socrates’ has come to us with the help of
causal-historical chains and belongs chiefly to its characterization. As we
will see later, information about causal records may become relevant to the
explanation and justification of reference, and we can be aware of it.
Conversely, the complete absence of causal records could even lead us to reject
a supposed historical reference to the bearer of a proper name as illegitimate.
It is
important to have in mind that causal records can only gain any explanatory
force concerning the determination of the reference because we can represent
their components cognitively, which means making them susceptible to
descriptive representation. Therefore, a descriptivist theory of proper
names should also be able to incorporate
information about causal records into the cluster of descriptions constitutive of the meaning of a proper name,
thus requiring that the linguistic community (at least through its privileged
members) be able, at some point, to produce descriptive representations of this
story in order to justify the referential use. We will see at least one
concrete case justifying this view in Chapter IV, when we critically examine
Donnellan’s example of Thales, the first philosopher of the Western tradition,
who simply because he was the first left particularly relevant causal records.
13. No need to fear causal chains
After the foregoing arguments, we are led to
ask the question: if the existence of a referred object is at the origin of so
many causal-historical chains, why should we give baptism such a special place?
Consider the example of something that appears in a horror film and is known to
exist, but has received no name, except “the thing”. Would the lack of baptism
be more important for our identification of the thing than its terrifying acts?
Furthermore, besides baptism, there is a whole network of
causal-historical chains initiated by the bearer of a proper name that
effectively reach us, and there are as many as the number of satisfied
descriptions we associate with the name. Consider the case of Aristotle. That
he wrote the Corpus Aristotelicum seems to be an extremely important
fact about Aristotle, which presupposes a causal-historical-informative chain
that has come down to us, and without which we could not gain knowledge of
those writings or attribute them to him. That Aristotle was born in Stagira in
384 BC and died in Chalcis in 322 BC are also very important historical events
concerning Aristotle. But they are only known by us because there are
causal-historical chains that extend from the recording of these facts by
others up to our awareness of them. It is also by means of causal records
(grounded on causal chains) that we know that Aristotle traveled to Magna
Greece when he was 17 years old to meet Plato, that he was Alexander’s preceptor,
that he married Pythias, that he founded the Lyceum, and that he was called by
Dante ‘the master of those who know’. Our awareness of these and many other
events is always ultimately assured not just by one, but by a multiplicity of
associated causal-historical chains, a network whose existence we are prepared
to consider beyond reasonable doubt, even if they remain completely unknown to
us, though leaving many main traces in causal records. But then, why select a
specific causal-historical chain – that of baptism – as the only appropriate
one? What does a person’s baptism – a perfectly accidental sound or visual
linguistic sign – do that is necessarily superior to other causal-historical
links like those producing relevant cognitions associated with a proper name,
such as the localizing and characterizing cognitions of its bearer? What is so
special about baptism as to justify its causal priority in so many cases? The
answer is: not very much.
It is
not difficult to show that the causal-historical effect of baptism can be
superseded. I can give two examples showing this with the help of
counterfactual situations. The first concerns a possible world very near to
ours, where in the remote hamlet of Obljaj, in July of 1894 a baby was baptized
with the name ‘Ligzarb Rijab’. He was the second son of a married Christian
orthodox Bosnian-Serbian peasant couple. Although the mother was not called
Marija and the father not Petar Princip, soon after his birth Ligzarb Rijab
began to have, in all details precisely the same life history as our Gravilo
Princip: he excelled as a student, went to Sarajevo, became radicalized, joined
the black hands terrorist group and, with his two friends Trifko Grabez and Milan
Ciganovic, planned the assassination of the Austrian Archduke during his visit
to Sarajevo. As expected, Ligzarb Rijab murdered Archduke Franz Ferdinand and
his wife on 28 June 1914 at 10:15 a.m., which as we know, was the fuse that
ignited World War I. As also expected, Ligzarb Rijab died in prison some years
later in appalling circumstances. Would the baptism of Ligzarb Rijab under
those somewhat different circumstances make us identify a person who would not
be the Gravilo Princip of our world?[43]
Intuitively not. He would be identified as our Gravilo, only with another name
and somewhat different circumstances of birth and genetic design. The baptismal
causal-historical view, even if reinforced by Kripke’s here artificially
sounding essence of origins, is too poor even by its own standards.[44]
Another example of this kind could concern the name ‘Napoleon’. Gareth
Evans (1973) imagined a Napoleon who was impersonated by a Doppelgänger after having fled from Elba in 1814… This idea
can be explored further. In the biography of Napoleon, it is well known that in
1769, in Ajaccio, Corsica, a newborn was baptized as ‘Napoleone di Buonaparte’.
Suppose, however, that the following discovery is made. In fact, there was a
super-smart malevolent orphan of the same age called Nicólo, whom no one could
distinguish by physical features from the real Napoleon.[45]
Knowing that the Buonapartes were a minor aristocratic family, the boy studied
them and did what only his nature would enable him to do. He killed Napoleone
when he was almost ten years old, taking his place in his family and entering
military school when he was ten years old. The rest of this story you already
know. This Napoleon went to France, had a military career, fought the
Napoleonic wars and self-proclaimed himself emperor of France… only to commit
the fatal mistake of invading Russia, which led to his final defeat at Waterloo
and bitter exile on the remote island of Saint Helena, where he dictated his
deceptive Memorial to Las Casas and died of cancer four years later.
Now,
the question is: who was the real Napoleon? Napoleone di Buonaparte or
Nicólo? For Kripke
it should be the former, the so-baptized ‘Napoleone’. Moreover, he satisfies
the individuating essence of origin, since the bearer of this name by baptism
is the real son ofthe true parents. Consequently, it should not be Nicólo, but
the child killed by him. Napoleon’s family, once knowing the facts, would also
think like Kripke, and I have nothing against this choice. Nevertheless, we are
interested in our Napoleon, and our
Napoleon is the Napoleon who made history. From the last perspective, our
linguistic intuition could say something very different. For some it could even
say that now that we have discovered all this, we have even uncovered a mystery
surrounding our Napoleon. We see that the world’s most infamous megalomaniac
couldn’t easily be a true Buonaparte. Our historical Napoleon should be, as he
in fact was, the clever but evil psychopath called Nicólo. This would explain
Napoleon’s enormous narcissism and his almost complete lack of sensitivity
concerning the lives of other people... In the future, historians will forget
Buonaparte and write biographies of Napoleon’s Great Deeds, speaking about
Nicólo. The conclusion is that the localizing
descriptions (his birth in 1769 in Ajaccio, his further life in France, his
retreat from Russia, his time in exile on the Isle of Elba, and his death on
Saint Helena in 1821) added to the characterizing
descriptions (a military genius who conquered much of Europe, fought the
Napoleonic wars, changed the legal order, self-proclaimed himself Emperor of
France, invaded Russia and was decisively defeated by European armies at the
Battle of Waterloo…) overcame by far
the force of his baptism. The true Napoleon – our historical Napoleon – was not
the person literally named ‘Napoleone di Buonaparte’, but a very clever and
ambitious impostor, a military genius who with more justification was called
Napoleon, but at least regarding his birth name was called Nicólo.
Summarizing the results, we can say that we have two meanings for
the name ‘Napoleon’: (i) the meaning of ‘Napoleon’ that takes the name of
baptism as central and therefore concentrates on his parental origin; (ii) the
meaning of ‘Napoleon’ that considers what at most counts as the characterizing
and localizing descriptions regarding the whole life of the man called
‘Napoleon’, regardless of his baptism. Although both determinations usually
converge, in the present case they diverge.
Another remarkable point is that in essence,
what we said above about causal historical chains regarding proper names also
applies to definite descriptions, contributing to dissolve the impression that
the distinction of proper names as rigid designators gives them a radically
different way to pick out their references, in contrast with definite
descriptions. A definite description usually also has a kind of baptism.
Cervantes “baptized” Don Quixote with the description ‘El caballero de la
triste figura’, and Dante “baptized” Aristotle as ‘Il maestro di color che
sano’ in La Divina Commedia, and these baptisms generated causal chains
that have reached us. In Burkina Fasso there is a building called La maison
du people; it was certainly so baptized. The same can be said of the
Champaner-Pavaghad Arqueological Parq, the Aga Kahn Palace Building, the Tomb
of Abdul Rahim Khan-I-Khana, all of them located in India. Although the words
of such descriptions often begin with capital letters (like proper names), no
one would deny that they all have connotations associating them semantically
with their bearers. Moreover, there is no reason to deny that satisfied
definite descriptions are known because of causal-historical chains that
usually begin with their causal associations with their references, as much as
it should be in the case of baptism, following a C-condition. For instance:
‘the defeated general at Waterloo’ came to us by means of a causal-historical
chain, like any other definite description, and the “baptismal” causal chains
of descriptions, since they reflect the connotations inscribed in them, seem to
be more important than those we associate with typical proper names. A
consequence is that the puzzling difference between rigidity and accidentality
must be looked for somewhere else (see chap. III, sec. 11).
It is
also worthwhile to note that according to Kripke, bearers of proper names have
an essentiality of origin. His main example is that of Queen Elizabeth II
(1980: 112 f.), since she would not be Queen were she not the daughter of
Albert, Duke of York, and his wife, Lady Elizabeth Bowes-Lyon.[46]
This example is, however, biased, since in the case of a queen, biological
origin acquires maximal importance. If we look at theories of parenthood, we
see that the point is highly conventional (see Ahlberg & Chobli 2017).
Often the true parents are considered those who educated and nurtured the
child, independently of its biological origin, which is superseded.[47]
Thus, the importance of origin must be relativized, as much as the importance
of baptism.
If we
relativize the role of baptism, then the appeal to causal chains, though
unavoidable, does not contribute to categorially distinguishing proper
names from descriptions, since definite descriptions are also only able to
refer because they are, if satisfied, in some way or other causally related to
their references. Consider the definite description ‘the man who wrote that form,
unlike matter, is what gives a thing its identity’. Independently of being
Aristotle or any other person, if the person existed, this person, by means of
his writings, was a causal factor in a direct or indirect way related to a
causal chain responsible for the description’s reference. Moreover, some
definite descriptions can explanatorily go back to acts of baptism. One example
is the definite description ‘the Eagle of The Hague’. It was initially
suggested as an epithet for Joaquim Nabuco, though by chance it ended up as a
description to be satisfied by Ruy Barbosa, who instead of Nabuco went to The
Hague.[48]
Even fictional descriptions are causally determined. The definite description
‘the man in the iron mask’ is causally related to a dramatic story originally
written by Alexandre Dumas. The fact that the relationship between naming and
reference is in the end causal does nothing to differentiate the mechanism of
reference of proper names from that of definite descriptions.[49]
14. A
very simple example
Before ending, I wish to recap by giving a
didactic example. It concerns a very simple proper name for a playful dog named
Dodó (a corruption of ‘Dona’), which my wife and I once owned.[50]
Before this female dog had a name, we already knew how to identify her as ‘our
dog.’ We identified her perceptually by t-properties like her size, the brown
color of her fur, the shape, and the white color of her nose, not to mention
the localizing fact that she was the only canine living in our house. When she
came to be called Dodó, we used the name, keeping in mind the creature with the
described characteristics, along with some peculiar behavioral traits.
Moreover, we also remember some causal records left by Dodó, like being chased
by a furious Owl after unwisely sticking her nose in its nest… Thus, what we
did was to associate the name with representations capable of being
interpersonally shared and to a good extent expressible in the descriptive form
of a spoken portrait, if necessary. Those who really knew Dodó, knew a
description with a characterizing and a localizing form: ‘the female dog with
such and such t-properties, who belonged to such and such people and who lived
in such and such a place.’ Of course, I was able to tell the name to other
people who had never seen her without the aid of that description, saying she
was our dog. These people knew, therefore, the representation expressed by the
very secondary description: ‘Claudio’s dog’, even if unable to identify the dog
by themselves. They borrowed the reference from me (in Searle’s terms, their
reference is parasitic on my non-parasitic reference.)
It
should be noted that we are here considering a variety of causal factors,
including a causal-historical chain (the satisfaction of a C-condition)
regarding the baptism of the dog with the name ‘Dodó’, necessary to explain how
it is possible after all these years to speak about that same dog. However, it
is even more important to note that the causal factors and some links of the
causal chain come to be cognitively registered as internal
cognitive-representational contents, which can occasionally be updated (perhaps
in a non-reflective way) in peoples’ minds, being typically
expressible-communicable through definite descriptions expressing what could be
called criterial identification rules (criterial description-rules, as we will
see).
It is
true that when we speak of Dodó, we satisfy the requirement of having the
intention of referring to the same object... However, this intention was at no
time devoid of cognitive content. It was the intention to designate the same
object by sharing cognitive elements in the form of definite descriptions
mostly known and shared by the name’s privileged users. Of course, these
intentional elements only exist because the links of the causal chain are in
the case neurophysiological events of a certain type, whatever they may be,
which could be presented to us internally in terms of
cognitive-representational contents which are normally able to be descriptively
communicated in proportion to their relevance... These links, when thought of
by various speakers, present an indispensable degree of similarity and
complementarity to each other. The example also suggests that some broadly
constructed causal-historical network is a necessary background condition for
the cognitivist-descriptivist explanation and justification of our acts of
naming. However, the work of explanation is on the descriptivist side: the more
weighted definite descriptions we add, the more we know what that dog was like,
and the better we are able to referentially identify that individual.
15. Conclusions
As I feel I have shown, the existence of a
C-condition, including some broadly constructed external causal or
causal-historical connection between the name and its reference – no matter how
indirect – remains an indispensable condition for a proper name to possess a
reference. This is an indisputable background condition and (as far as I am
informed) was already agreed upon by sophisticated descriptivist philosophers
such as P. F. Strawson.
However, if our goal is to explain how a proper name refers, taken
alone, a C-condition and any broadly constructed external causal-historical
connection are useless. Explanatory relevance, as our examples have suggested,
seems to appear only when external causal factors are cognitively interpreted
in the form of mainly localizing and/or characterizing definite descriptions
which are as a whole sufficiently weighted to support reference to a unique
individual.
The
conclusion of the ad nauseam argumentative evidence collected in this
chapter is that with his view of causal-historical baptism, Kripke has tried to
suggest as a necessary and sufficient explanatory condition for the reference
of many proper names something that, albeit pointing to a real fact – the
C-condition – when closely viewed betrays either a begging of his question
against descriptivism or an explanatorily empty condition for the name’s
reference. All the illuminating aspects of his views ask for the development of
some neodescriptivist explanatory approach. Hence, it seems that descriptivist
views of how proper names refer do not deserve rejection, but rather
improvement. This is what I expect to do in the next two chapters.
[1] I will restrict myself to a critical examination
of Kripke’s ideas, since with the time they have established themselves as a
kind of explanatory paradigma for the reference of proper names. My intention
is to show in the next chapters that a dialectical change to an internalist
neodescriptivist paradigma is not only possible but desirable.
[2] See Salmon 2005: 23-31; G. W. Fitch
2004; Burgess 2013: 19-24, 53-55; Cf. also Ahmed 2007: Ch. 2.
[3] I am only avoiding the often-noted
inaccuracy of the description ‘the first European to visit America’. (Searle
1958: 68; Kripke 1980: 83-84).
[4] As noted by Karen Green, Searle’s
requirement that the bearer of a proper name “must necessarily have the logical
sum, inclusive disjunction”, of properties commonly attributed to it (1958:
172) was never really met by Kripke’s objection (Green 1998).
[5] I will leave aside for now the more
important and difficult counterexamples of Gödel, Thales, etc. for Chapter IV
since they are better dealt with after the presentation of my own theory.
[6] Searle dedicated the last chapter
of his 1983 book to a brilliant defense of his descriptivist cluster theory
against the objections of Kripke and Donnellan. I am not the first to note the
curious point that his defense remained virtually unanswered by partisans of
the new orthodoxy.
[7] See Ahmed 2007: 37.
[8] See Salmon 1980: 27.
[9] This is also the conclusion of
specialists like David Braun and Marga Reimer in their respective articles for
the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
For a supportive defense of Kripke, see Scott Soames (2002, Ch. 2). For a
well-balanced critical approach, see Arif Ahmed (2007, Ch. 2).
[10] Arthur W. Burks, for example, following our
robust common sense, suggested that a proper name refers by means of the
satisfaction of changeable and generally non-indispensible properties (1951: 39
f.).
[11] Today trope theory is already a
major player in the ontological discussion, together with realism and
nominalism. See, for instance, J. W. Carol and Ned Marcosian (2010: Chap. 9).
[12] D. C. Williams’ ground breaking
work (1953) was the proposal of a radical naturalist alternative to the
traditional but always controversial realist and nominalist answers common
in ontology. A relevant attempt to develop
a trope-ontology was made in Keith Campbell’s 1990 book. Since then, the
literature devoted to trope-ontology has grown steadily, though often weakening
Williams’ original insight. The development of a fully adequate theory of
tropes remains an unfinished task. For bibliographical access, see Anna-Sofia
Maurin (2018).
[13] Keith Campbell (1990) called them quasi-tropes, though from the here
explained perspective there is no good reason to do this.
[14] Friedrich Nietzsche (e.g., 2017:
sec. 9; 2021: sec. 372) made a case on what he saw as an ascetic
supernaturalism that had afflicted philosophy since Socrates, continuing
with Plato, Plotinus, and most Judeo-Christian philosophers. It is very
possible that the real explanation for the fact that trope theory emerged only
in the XXth Century was a psychologically grounded form of escapism, together
with the enlightenment provided by the sciences and the effects of technology
in the human life world.
[15] The details concerning these
compositions of concurrent or compresent tropes are, however, more complex and
diversified than it seems at first sight (See Simons 1994). Speculatively, I
suggested that the trope of what physicists call inertial mass could be
considered the fundamental criterion for the identification of a multitude of
individuals, since it comprises all physical individuals, from macroscopic
objects, including persons, to microphysical particles, though excluding energy
waves (Costa 2018: 172).
[16] Consider the form “Ce [Ci => A]”
in the addendum of the last chapter.
[17] Kripke prefers to use the term
‘picture’ instead of ‘theory’, since what he presents is a rudimentary sketch,
not even applicable to all proper names; ‘Jack the Ripper’, for example, is
better explained descriptively, since the identity of the murderer was never
discovered (1980: 79-80, 94). Kripke’s sketch is of a theory of reference, not
of a theory of meaning, since he tends to share Mill’s idea that proper names
have “no signification”.
[18] There are other versions of the
view, such as those of Keith Donnellan (very similar to Kripke’s) and Michael
Devitt (a deviant view). To simplify my explanation, I present only that of
Kripke, which over time established itself as the standard version.
[19] See also p. 91. Keith Donnellan
held a similar hypothesis: “It seems clear to me that in some way the referent
must be historically, or, we might say, causally connected to the speech act.
But I do not see my way clear to say exactly how in general that connection
goes. Perhaps there is no exact theory” (1970: 377).
[20] E.g., Noonan 2013: 117.
[21] Gareth Evans has rightly spoken of
the “causal theory of names” (1973). Indeed, it seems too implausible to assume
a historical-communication chain made up of non-causal successions of events,
since this succession would either be arbitrarily chosen or at least graspable
by means of cognitive relationships among their components which, being
descriptively representable, would lead us in the most direct way back to some
form of descriptivism.
[22] The view according to which
cognitive states like reasoning have causal effects was convincingly introduced
in the analytic discussion by Donald Davidson (1963).
[23] Assuming a consequent trope
ontology, as Williams do, we are committed to see “abstract” entities like
numbers as causally effective. For an explanation of how it could be so, see the
Appendix of this book.
[24] In his classic work on causality,
J. L. Mackie (1974, caps. 2 and 3) showed that what we call the ‘efficient
cause’ is the result of a merely pragmatic choice of a causal factor that is an unqualified but non-redundant part of a set
of causal factors that is itself an unnecessary but sufficient condition for
the effect to take
place. There is much more to say about causation, but Mackie’s definition
remains arguably the most powerful, serving well in the context of the present
discussion.
[25] Searle added that this reference is
only possible because people form intentional representations of objects when
baptizing them. (1983: 240-241).
[26] It could be if the proposition were
something a-temporally true. Here it is important to note that by presupposing
trope ontology, as we do here, there is no thought in the Fregean realist sense
of a non-spatiotemporal abstract proposition (Frege 1918). A thought must be
either a trope or (corresponding to the Fregean thought) a universal in the
sense of a sum or set of precisely similar tropical thoughts or, as I prefer to
understand it, a tropical thought used as a model or any tropical thought regarded
as precisely similar to it.
[27] Searle
realized the difficulty by noting that the explanations given by Kripke and
Donnellan for introducing proper names are entirely descriptivist:
“Implicitly,” wrote Searle, “he also resorts to an intention when he speaks of
the perception of the object by the speaker and hearer in the act of baptism
since the perception has an intentional content, which ends up presupposing
descriptivism.” (Searle 1983: 234-235) However, a causalist-referentialist
philosopher could still suggest that the act of baptism (even if intentional)
includes a mechanical (non-conscious), unintentional sharing of the reference,
insisting that this could be all that really matters as a causal factor.
[28] The emptiness of a descriptively
unsalvageable intention was already made clear by Gareth Evans’ example of
someone who identifies Kingston correctly as the capital of Jamaica, when the
person from whom he picked up this scrap of information was actually making a
racist remark about Kingston upon Thames, in England. (1973)
[29] I say this assuming it is
physically possible to construct such androids. It seems to me much more
defensible to claim that only biological beings produced by processes of
organic chemistry, alive in the same way we human beings are, would be able to
use natural languages as we do. One does not have to know much about biology
and human brains in comparison with silicon-chip based computers to realize
that computer “brains” and human brains made up of living nerve cells are immeasurably
different. It is only our present ignorance of how the human brain really works
that allows such approximation.
[30] Some causal-referentialists, like
Kripke, tend to dismiss the meaningfulness of proper names. Hard externalists,
like Nathan Salmon and David Kaplan, attributed meanings to their references.
[31] Independently of any objection, the
most recommendable work about related issues is Kripke’s Reference and
Existence (2013).
[32] There are also proper names for
non-existent non-real objects: in Samuel Beckett’s play “Waiting for Godot”
(1953), the characters are anxiously searching for something that is almost
certainly a creation of their minds (for fictional-fictional circumstances cf.
Kripke 2013: III).
[33] See, for instance, van Inwagen
1977, Braun 2005, Salmon 1998, Caplan 2004.
[34] I was verbally informed about this
implausible alternative, probably taken with changes from Russell’s view of
proper names as disguised descriptions.
[35] This illustrates what Avrum Stroll,
a Wittgenstein specialist, called philosophizing by examples; a painful
consideration of individual cases to avoid the dangerously reductive character
of excessive formalism.
[36] The history of the fictitious city,
together with more than 300 drawings, was published in the form of a book in
2006.
[37] Even advocates of Kripke’s view
have difficulties with the problem of finding the right causal-historical
chain: “…if one, say ‘James,’ uses that expression attributively as a proper
name, and has in mind no particular source, how do we decide which branch to
follow?” (Kaplan 1989: 583)
[38] As Richard Feynman noted in an
interview: “…even the trajectory of the light waves that allow us to see the
most differently things when from different places and perspectives… makes a
tremendous mess, and this without counting short and long invisible electromagnetic
waves, like the many radio waves of different frequencies that simultaneously
reach us in the same spot… only this already gives us a quaint idea of the
absurd causal complexity of the universe, the inconceivable nature of nature.”
Cf. BBC-Series “Fun to Imagine”.
[39] I say type, because I wish to sidestep a possible objection suggested by
the controversial concept of multiple realizability (See Polger & Shapiro 2016).
[40] This conclusion can be easily
extended to any anti-descriptivist causal-historical-communicational chain view
(cf. Donnellan 1972: 337; Sterelny 1983).
[41] It is worthwhile to note that without
using as many arguments as possible Searle came to a similar conclusion forty
years ago: “The external causal chain plays no explanatory role whatever in
either Kripke’s or Donnellan’s account… The
only chain that matters is a transfer of intentional content from one use of an
expression to the next, in every case reference is secured in virtue of
descriptivist Intentional content in the mind of the speaker who uses the
expression.” (1983: 244-245).
[42]
The astonishing story of the more than 200 years in which the original
Aristotelian manuscripts called by him ‘Writings of First Philosophy’ passed
from one hand to the other, were hidden in a cave, sold to a bibliophile,
acquired by the Roman conqueror of
Athens, crossed the sea, and were finally published in Rome by Andronicus of
Rhodes under the new title of ‘Metaphysics’ is told by W. K. C. Guthrie,
1981, Vol. VI, Ch. III. The causal-history of the manuscripts left a series of
descriptive registers belonging to what in the next chapter will be called the
spaciotemporal career of the object of reference.
[43] Curiously, in photos Ligzarb Rijab
looks somewhat like our Gravilo Princip, and his parents look a bit like Marija
and Petar Princip.
[44] Certainly, there are cases, like
that of Queen Elizabeth, where the essence of origins, namely, to be the
daughter of the official parents, takes priority, but this is an ad hoc example.
[45] This phenomenon of practically
indistinguishable persons who lack any family relations in common is rare, but
really exists. Anyway, its real existence does not need to be part of the
story.
[46] Her father became king when his
brother abdicated the throne, and this made her next in line of succession for
the throne. For a discussion of the essentiality of origins, see Costa 2018,
pp. 98-100.
[47] For Kripke, the essentiality of
origin is shown by the fact that if one were born to parents x and y, then one could
not have been born to any other parents (1980: 113). But so understood this is
nothing beyond a trifling tautology like ‘If A’s only cause is B, A
cannot be caused by anything other than B”.
[48] Both men were Brazilian writers,
diplomats, and statesmen.
[49] The same point could be extended to
indexicals. If a host says to her servant, “When the dinner table is set, take
that chair with red upholstery you can see in that corner and put it at the
head of the table,” the host, by the act of pointing, together with a
complementary description, is creating a localizing and characterizing
identification rule for the chair. This rule is causally grasped by the
servant, who is aware of it and at the right time will take the chair and put
it in the required position.
[50] Any similarity with Michael
Devitt’s dog called ‘Nana’ is a mere coincidence.
Nenhum comentário:
Postar um comentário