Quem sou eu

Minha foto
If you wish to be acquainted with my groundbreaking work in philosophy, take a look at this blogg. It is the biggest, the broadest, the deepest. It is so deep that I guess that the narrowed focus of your mind eyes will prevent you to see its full deepness.

sábado, 7 de dezembro de 2024

THE BULK OF METADESCRIPTIVISM (3 de 5)

  This is a draft of a chapter of the book "How do Proper Names Really Work?" published by De Gruyter 2023

 

 

III

META-DESCRIPTIVISM:

DEVELOPING A THEORY

 

 

The mainstream of our philosophical community sometimes behaves like a pendulum, which first oscillates to one side and then to the other.[1] One result of this is that, when considered over a short period of time, it offers us the illusory reassurance that the pendulum will continue to move in the same direction forever. The theory of the direct reference of proper names allegedly proposed by John Stuart Mill did not have a long lifetime. It lost credibility with the appearance of the descriptivist theories of Frege, Russell, Wittgenstein, P. F. Strawson, John Searle, and others. In the sixties of the last century, it seemed as if the true theory of reference for proper names had finally been outlined. However, what a surprise it was when in the early seventies the philosophical world was presented with a new conception of how proper names refer that sounded like a rebirth of Millianism, re-conceived in the form of the causal-historical view of proper names advocated by Saul Kripke, Keith Donnellan, and later in somewhat different forms by Michael Devitt and others, in a movement that persists to the present day? As I endeavored to show in the previous chapter, it is not at all certain that this movement is definitive. Indeed, my goal in this chapter is to reverse the direction of the pendulum’s trajectory in the direction of a kind of neo-descriptivist theory. Notwithstanding, my approach must be considerably more complex and nuanced, since it must take enough account of the considerable range of reflections produced for and against the later causal-referentialist view. Although the argument I will present in what follows is very lengthy and detailed, requiring some effort from the reader, I believe it is in the end clear and convincing – in fact, the only reasonable alternative.

   My working hypothesis on descriptivist theories of proper names is that they fail due to “lack of structure.” A proper name cannot take the place of some haphazard cluster of non-differentially weighted descriptions, as orthodox cluster theory seems to claim. For instance, a look at the examples analyzed in the last chapter seems to make somewhat intuitive the idea that definite descriptions concerning the spatiotemporal localization of the object of reference (“localizing descriptions”), as much as those definite descriptions concerning the main reasons why we use a proper name (“characterizing descriptions”), must occupy a place of pride against more fortuitous descriptions. That is, it seems that the descriptions that make up a cluster must be subject to some structuring principle.  It is indeed plausible to think that the main reason why Searle’s version of a cluster theory lacks explanatory power resides in its not taking account of the internal organization of the cluster, giving the impression that a causal-historical view constitutes a plausible option.

   Now, what is the structuring principle we are searching for? The natural answer arises when we consider what we have seen in the appendix of Chapter I: the constitutive descriptions of any cluster can be seen as what could be called description-rules, i.e., linguistic expressions of what might be called semantic-cognitive criterial rules, insofar as they must be able, somehow and to some extent (even if minimal and only tacitly understood) cognitively[2] to connect a proper name with its bearer. Now, since the definite descriptions constitutive of a cluster summarized by a proper name are expressions of rules, the structuring principle must be a rule of rules, namely, a meta-rule, a higher-order rule having as its field of application first-order description-rules belonging to the cluster of descriptions of proper names in general. Hence, I call this structuring principle a general meta-description rule since my aim is to apply it to the descriptions of any proper name in general. Because of this, I call the version of descriptivism that I am searching for a meta-descriptivist theory of proper names. (It would not be fair to call it a form of ‘causal-descriptivism,’ since even if it assumes an indispensable causal element, this element, as we have seen in the last chapter, has no explanatory power, being therefore unable to tell us how a proper name reaches its reference.[3]

   Before trying to explain and justify the general meta-descriptivist rule, some classificatory investigation of the types of descriptions belonging to the clusters is necessary. The reason is that not all definite descriptions seem relevant or even minimally relevant. Consider the following one: ‘the person who in the winter of 1938 lay in the grass of the dikes that enclose the Mississippi, and in the presence of the moving waters of that magnificent river experienced one of his rare moments of peace’.[4] This is an irrelevant definite description that can be found in the autobiography of Bertrand Russell, irrelevant because almost no one knows or knew it. To select the more important kinds of definite descriptions, I start by systematically investigating the main types of descriptions  belonging to the proper name’s clusters, since it is certain that if there is a general meta-descriptive rule, it will not apply to irrelevant descriptions    Before arriving at the proposed classification, however, it is worth noting that philosophers who defended descriptivist views of proper names have often taken vivid but in fact arbitrarily chosen definite descriptions associated with a proper name as examples. These descriptions were arbitrarily chosen for their often-alluring character. Nonetheless, they are deceitful and can often be dismissed as having almost no importance for the real identification of the object to be referred to by a proper name. Frege, for example, suggested that the name ‘Aristotle’ could be used in place of the descriptions ‘Plato’s greatest disciple’ and ‘the tutor of Alexander the Great.’ Wittgenstein suggested that the name ‘Moses’ could be used in place of the description ‘the man who as an infant was discovered in a basket floating in the Nile by pharaoh’s daughter.’ And Searle remembered in connection with Aristotle the description ‘the founder of the Lyceum school in Athens’. But, as we shall see, none of these folk descriptions plays a relevant role in identifying the person they indicate.

 

1. Fundamental description-rules

There are undoubtedly more, and less weighted definite descriptions associated with proper names. Consider, for example, the proper name ‘Moses.’ The description ‘the man who led the Israelites to the promised land’ seems far more relevant than ‘the man who as an infant was found in the Nile by pharaoh’s daughter.’ After all, it is intuitively clear that the falsehood of the latter description would cause far less semantic damage than the falsehood of the former.

   To hierarchize description-rules, I want to distinguish three groups of definite descriptions capable of expressing parts of the informative content of proper names:

 

 groups A and B, containing what I call fundamental descriptions,

 and

 group C, containing what I call auxiliary descriptions.

 

I want to show that groups A and B are those of descriptions that are truly relevant to the identification of the object, while group C is that of descriptions which, although often exemplified and having greater or lesser value for the connection with the object, do not play a really grounding role in the identification, although, as we will also see, they might gain an important communication role, particularly in borrowed or parasitic references. The rationale for these distinctions will be given in what follows.

   Let us first look at what I called the fundamental descriptions belonging to groups A and B. To make sure that they are not an arbitrary invention of mine, I would like to begin by showing why they are the most relevant description-rules in the game of naming. But how to do this? Unexpected as it might seem, there is an easy way. As some know, J. L. Austin, the ordinary language philosopher, advised that when working with philosophy one should always have the Oxford English Dictionary at hand.[5] This can be helpful when we need to get a pre-philosophical understanding of the plural meanings of concept words that are central to our understanding of the world, for instance, the meanings of the verb ‘to know’.

   However, many have objected that we cannot look up the most important types of descriptions associated with proper names… After all, proper names are generally not found in dictionaries. This is a reason why some philosophers have decided that proper names have no meaning. But this should not discourage us. Even if proper names are not usually included in dictionaries, at least many of them are placed in encyclopedias. Hence the new advice: “if you wish to find the descriptions that matter for a proper name, you should start (if possible) by consulting its article in encyclopedias!”

   To begin with, look at what I have found in the ‘Aristotle’ entry of my pocket Penguin Philosophical Dictionary. I chose this because it is the shortest competent entry I could find. There it is written:

 

Aristotle = (384 BC – 322 BC) was born in Stagira, northern Greece, Aristotle produced the greatest philosophical system of antiquity. (What follows is a short list of Aristotle’s main works.)

 

When we examine this or any other encyclopedia entry for the proper name ‘Aristotle,’ we always find a similar pattern. They especially abbreviate two description-rules, one establishing the place and time of Aristotle’s life, to which are added the stages of his career in space and time,[6] while the other establishes the most important properties attributed to Aristotle, those which constitute the very reason why we apply the name. These properties are, above all, the central ideas and arguments presented in the Corpus Aristotelicum.

   We can now abstract from this concrete case two types of fundamental description-rules justifying what I called groups A and B, respectively:

 

A) Localizing description-rule: expressed by the description that establishes what we consider to be the object’s space-time location and career (with the possible inclusion of spatiotemporal antecedents and consequents).

B) Characterizing description-rule: expressed by the description that establishes what we consider to be the object’s most relevant properties – those that constitute the very reason we name it (– possibly including relevant antecedents and consequents).

 

We must note that the spatiotemporal career may include causal paths before and after the object’s existence, as the final clauses of (A) and (B) show, insofar as they are seen as relevant. Thus, it is relevant (concerning causes) to the name ‘Aristotle’ that he was the son of Philip of Macedon’s court doctor; it is particularly relevant to Queen Elizabeth II that she was the daughter of Prince Albert, Duke of York, who later became King George V… Moreover (concerning effects), it is relevant to the name ‘James Mill’ that he was the father of John Stuart Mill; and it is still more relevant to Gavrilo Princep, the Bosnian Serb student who assassinated Archduke Franz Ferdinand of Austria and his wife, that his act triggered the First World War. However, it does not seem of any relevance to know who the parents of Anaxagoras were (there are no historical references to them). Kripke reserved a completely different place for such things with his story about the essentiality of origins, while my intention is to link them to descriptivism.

   Let us now consider Aristotle’s localizing and characterizing description-rules, by more explicitly stating them. Both descriptions are highlighted in encyclopedias and can be briefly summarized as follows:

 

(a) Localizing description-rule of the name ‘Aristotle’: the person who was born in Stagira in 384 BC as the son of Philip of Macedon’s court doctor, who lived most of his life in Athens, had to flee to Asos, returned to Athens, but in the end had to flee to Chalkis, where he died in 322 BC.

(b) Characterizing description-rule of the name ‘Aristotle’: the author of the relevant philosophical doctrines explained in Metaphysics, Physics, Nicomachean Ethics, Organon, Topics, and other main works of the Aristotelian opus.

 

Such fundamental description-rules or conditions can be more and more descriptively detailed; for instance, we know that he crossed the Aegean see when he was 17, and that after the death of Plato he lived for two years on the island of Lesbos, where with help of Theophrastus he conducted important biological research… And we could give detailed summaries of the 14 books of his Metaphysics or his Ethics or his Organon. In Aristotle’s case, these accounts are ultimately justified by historical testimonies and the many surviving writings. Moreover, it seems that in this case, the characterizing rule is somewhat more relevant, which would give it greater weight. Anyway, both description-rules are clearly relevant and, as you should have noted, not completely separable.

   To underline the importance of fundamental description-rules, here are some examples of definite descriptions of group A, which I took directly from the headings of Wikipedia entries.[7] They are presented as conditions for localizing identifying properties of the objects referred to by proper names:

 

1.     Churchill (Sir Winston Leonard Spencer Churchill): a person who was born in 10/11/1874 in Oxfordshire and died on 24/1/1965 in London. He lived most of his life in England, except for some short holidays in cities like Venice, though as a young man he worked as a correspondent in the British colonies…

2.     Taj Mahal: a mausoleum commissioned in 1632 near the city of Agra, India, existing from 1653 to the present day.

3.     Paris: city of more than ten million inhabitants situated in the center of northern France, on the banks of the River Seine. Its emergence as a city dates back to the 9th century.

4.     Amazon: a river whose source is in the mountains of Peru, and which empties into the Atlantic, following the line of the equator. Together with its tributaries, it forms the world’s largest watershed. It has existed since time immemorial…

 

 Note that the localizing description has at least one characterizing element, which consists in classifying the kind of object referred to. Thus, Churchill is classified as being a person, the Taj Mahal a mausoleum, Paris a city, the Amazon a river, Venus a planet… This minimum characterization is indispensable for the localizing description to make sense. Furthermore, the kind of object has some priority in weight: it would not be possible to name ‘Churchill’ if he were a dog, ‘Taj Mahal’ if it were a shack, ‘Paris’ if it were a longhouse, ‘Amazon River’ if it were a stream, ‘Venus’ if it were an asteroid.

   Group B of description-rules is also fundamental. One can make this clear by scanning the headings of encyclopedias in general. In the same order, here is what Wikipedia briefly says:

 

1.     Churchill = was a remarkable British statesman, who was the prime minister of the United Kingdom from 1939 to 1945, in the critical years of the Second World War, and again from 1950 to 1955.

2.     Taj Mahal = the wonderful marble mausoleum constructed by Emperor Shah Jahan for his beloved wife, Mumtaz Mahal.

3.     Paris = the capital of France, economic, cultural, and political center of the country, and one of the most beautiful cities in the world.

4.     Amazon = the river carrying the most water and possibly also the longest river in the world, source of 1/5 of the fresh water flowing into the oceans.

 

I want to demonstrate that the primacy of these localizing and characterizing descriptions is in no way an extravagance of encyclopedias. It is pretty much because of the importance of properties denoted by the definite descriptions of these two lists that we are able to apply these names. These properties can be considered of greater importance, as they result from an agreement among privileged users about what would be the most fundamental properties associated with their bearers.

 

2. Auxiliary description-rules

Now I want to consider the definite descriptions that have been left out. They are what I call the auxiliary description-rules belonging to group C. They are many, some of them colorful and used in everyday life in the place of names. That’s why, as I have suggested, they have often confused philosophers, making it difficult to determine what really matters concerning identification. In the following, I present a classification that, although unsystematic, can be helpful.

(1) The first case of group C consists of descriptions that can be called metaphorical, often used in place of the proper name. Examples are descriptions such as ‘the lady of the camellias’, ‘the eagle of The Hague’, ‘the city of light’, ‘the knight of the sad figure,’ ‘the master of those who know’. The properties they allude to are not, in general, those that draw attention to their peculiarity. But they do draw attention to their usefulness as suggestive and picturesque mnemonic devices. Thus, ‘the iron marshal’, for instance, draws attention by pointing to a striking characteristic of Marshal Floriano Peixoto, which was his authoritarian and uncompromising character. But this is of little value in the sense of helping us to identify Floriano Peixoto unequivocally, because there were many other persons with similar character traits. What most properly allows us to identify Floriano Peixoto is, certainly, awareness that he satisfies the localizing description (a) of having been ‘the military officer born in Joazeiro in 1839, who served in the war between Paraguay and Acre and died in 1895 in Barra Mansa,’ in addition to the characterizing description (b) of having been, mainly, ‘the second president and the first vice-president of Brazil, responsible for those acts of repression that consolidated the republic’. Both descriptions are unavoidably found in encyclopedias.

(2) There are also non-metaphorical auxiliary description-rules, which we can classify as accidental, but well-known. Examples of well-known accidental descriptions are ‘the man who as an infant was found in the Nile by pharaoh’s daughter’ and ‘the tutor of Alexander the Great.’ These descriptions are known to most people who can be said to know what is meant by the names ‘Moses’ and ‘Aristotle’ and often also by some who do not know. Yet they are quite accidental, for surely neither Moses nor Aristotle would cease to be the persons we consider them to be if the information provided by these descriptions were false.

   To this type also belongs a very peculiar definite description, which has the form of ‘the bearer of the name “N”’, for example, ‘the bearer of the name “Aristotle”’, understanding this description as referring to only one distinct individual, namely, our ancient Greek philosopher Aristotle.[8] Definite descriptions of this kind are accidental, for their referents would not cease to be what they are, nor to be easily identifiable as such if they had received a different name, or if they had later changed their name. Indeed, it is a mere accident that Aristotle was baptized with the name ‘Aristotle,’ while it does not seem to have been equally accidental that he wrote the Aristotelian opus or that he belongs to the classic period of ancient Greece. Imagine that in a possible world Nicomachus, a physician at Philip’s court, instead of baptizing the son born in Stagira in 384 BC as ‘Aristotle’ had baptized him with the name ‘Pittacus’. Supposing that Pittacus had studied with Plato, written the entire Aristotelian opus, and had the same biography as Aristotle, we would not hesitate to say that in this possible world Pittacus was our Aristotle, only with a different name.

   That the description-rule of the form ‘the bearer of the name “N”’ is not fundamental to the identification of a particular object is made evident by the fact that we can use a name – as a phonetic-graphic sensible form, a name-word – and, after discovering that it is incorrect, replace it with the correct name-word for the same person. In addition, we can know who a person is – her appearance, where and when to find her, what is relevant about her – without remembering or even knowing what the person is called (some people lack a memory for names). The proper name, understood as a sensible form, is like the label on a binder that contains a cluster of description-rules: We can replace the label (‘Aydes’ changed his name to ‘Adilson’), we can even be deceived as to the most appropriate label, as, in the case of the baptized name (‘Raúl Rivas’ was actually called ‘Marcial Maciel’). However, what really matters here is the content of the binder, seen as a kind of identification rule for the name’s referent. After all, even if some sensible mark and a disambiguating context are necessary for us to know which binder we are considering, such a mark is, in the end, the result of almost arbitrary and potentially changeable choices (the Russian city currently called ‘Volgograd’ was previously called ‘Stalingrad’, although it was originally called ‘Tsaritsyn’). The content, however, should have epistemological and ontological import.

   This last remark leads us to a curious conclusion. If we admit that in our reflections on language a philosophically relevant explanation is one that has epistemological and ontological import, then a philosophical theory on the semantics of proper names is not a theory restricted to what we usually call a ‘proper name’ in the current language, which is a phonetic or orthographic expression of what we mean with a proper name.[9]  This expression is what, for example, leads us to regard the word ‘Köln’ as a different proper name than ‘Cologne’ (name as a symbolic expression), while we could also say that they are respectively the German and the French forms of the same proper name (a name as an expressed cognitive content). A philosophically relevant theory of proper names should be essentially a theory of semantic-cognitive contents constitutive of proper names, which should be seen as identification rules for the proper names’ bearers, associated with names as sensible marks, such as ones we are searching for. If this is so, a theory of proper names must be essentially a binder theory and not a label theory, since although required for communication, labels are arbitrary and capable of substitution.

   Although many would disagree, I think we can make a distinction here parallel to the distinction between the lexical sense and the semantic content of indexicals. Indexical terms are singular terms like ‘this’, ‘that’, ‘I’, ‘you’, ‘she’… which can refer to different things in different contexts. However, they have a fixed lexical sense, for instance, ‘“This”’ should usually indicate something near to the speaker’, ‘“I” should usually indicate the speaker when she utters it.’ However, indexical terms must also have semantic content, the sense they gain when applied to an object given in a particular context (for instance, when I say this and am referring to this notebook or use I to mean myself). Correspondingly, the lexical sense of a proper name is that of a term whose sense isn’t expressed through syntactic complexity and that is used to identify a single object, distinguishing it from a multiplicity of others (Tugendhat 1976: 425 f.).

   Theories of the lexical meaning of the proper name are possible, I concede, but they will lack any epistemic or ontological import, since they will not give us the rules that would allow us to individuate any name’s bearer. A theory of the semantic content of a proper name, in turn, is a theory like that of Fregean sense, of its cognitive meaning, or of the rules establishing the criteria for the identification of its bearers and what is common among them. Only such a theory will have explanatory force to clarify the epistemic relationship between the proper name and its object. But for this very reason, the sensible mark of a proper name becomes, in the end, something accidental, explaining why a set of different sensible marks can conventionally express an identical or similar semantic content, thereby not failing to produce the act of naming the same referent. Therefore, for us, a proper name is an identifying (internal) semantic content plus a conventional sensible mark that makes that content communicable. For a philosophically relevant theory of proper names, these sensible marks are only their unavoidable symbolic expressions, in no way exhausting what we understand as the content of proper names.

 

(3) There are also accidental and generally unknown description-rules. Examples are ‘the husband of Pythias’, ‘the lover of Herphyllis’, ‘the grandson of Achaeon’. Not many people know that these descriptions are all associated with the name ‘Aristotle’. Such definite descriptions can, of course, be multiplied at will, and are found in abundance in biographies. There are, however, still less well-known definite descriptions, for instance: ‘the first naturalist to open a fertilized chicken egg and to describe the living embryo within it’, whose bearer was also Aristotle when he lived in Lesbos. Because such descriptions are known to only a few persons, they have in themselves almost no relevant function in their association with the proper name. Thus, imagine that all a speaker knows about Aristotle is that he was Achaeon’s grandson. In most cases he will not be able to make use of this name to communicate with other people, since a description that is shared by only a few cannot help people recognize it as referring to Aristotle as the famous Greek philosopher, rather than, say, the Greek multi-millionaire Aristotle Onassis, who could also have a grandfather called Achaeon[10]here could the contexts of the utterance and of the learning of the proper name eventually disambiguate the word ‘Aristotle’.

(4) Finally, there are adventitious auxiliary descriptions, such as that expressed by the dsescription ‘the philosopher mentioned by the teacher’ or ‘the girl who was introduced to us at the party.’ The rules expressed here associate the name with some context in which it was properly used. They are typically provisional: at first spontaneously produced in public speech, then used for some time, and later abandoned and forgotten. They are therefore not permanent semantic constituents and characteristics of the name. However, because these description-rules refer to a context known to a group of speakers in a certain period, they may suffice for a speaker to be able to use them alone or associated with the proper name in conversations. Consequently, the speaker will be uniquely recognized by interlocutors, with the possibility of subsequent exchanges of information about the proper name’s bearer.

   At this point, the following objection could be made. Apart from the fact that they appear in the headings of encyclopedia entries, there does not seem to be any compelling reason to privilege so-called fundamental description-rules of groups A and B. After all, just as auxiliary descriptions are contingent, the same can be shown to be the case with fundamental descriptions themselves: that Aristotle did not write his philosophical works, that Churchill did not become a British statesman, that the Taj Mahal was not built near Agra, and that Paris did not arise where it did, but rather in the south of France, are very improbable empirical possibilities, but not necessities. We can, after all, imagine possible worlds where neither the rules of characterization for Aristotle and Churchill, nor the rules of location for the Taj Mahal and Paris are applicable, but even then, the philosopher and the statesman, as well as the ivory-white marble mausoleum and the city of light still exist. In isolation, fundamental description-rules do not designate anything necessary for the identification of a proper name’s bearer. On the other hand, it seems that we can identify a single object through a single auxiliary description: according to the circumstances, to know that someone is talking about Aristotle may be enough to know that he is speaking of the founder of the Lyceum, or Alexander’s tutor, or even to know that he is speaking of the Lyceum’s founder, Pythias’ spouse, Herphyllis’ lover, etc.

   The only thing I can do in the face of objections like these is to ask the reader for patience! What we have done so far is to consider with some attention the main pieces of a puzzle. Only after the introduction of second-order rules capable of selecting the weighted combinations of first-order description-rules able to justify the application of a proper name, will the importance of the descriptions of groups A and B become indisputable.

 

3. Disjunctive rule

From our working-hypothesis and from what was said above, it seems to follow that we need to search for ways of identifying combinations among the description-rules of a proper name’s cluster that make possible the name’s referential application. To do this we need to look for a second-order rule (or description-rule) that can be applied to the cluster’s first-order description-rules associated with any proper name, so that the second-order rule is able to select the combinations that make it possible to apply any name. This rule of rules should therefore be a general meta-rule, a meta-descriptive rule applicable to bundles of descriptions that we associate with proper names in general.

   Is there such a general meta-descriptive rule? If there is, we should be able to find it. Assuming by hypothesis an affirmative answer, the question becomes: how can we find such a rule? The strategy I propose is the following. To begin with, it seems quite advisable to dismiss group C descriptions as insufficiently relevant. They seem to be identifiers only in the sense of assisting the speaker in his social connection with the object by means of a parasitic reference. This function is realized to the extent that they enable us to insert a name into a discourse, understood as a communication medium, assuming we already know the true identification rules of the object capable of completing this connection. If the true identification rules are not known by all, they can at least be known by privileged users of a name, or partially known by each of them, under the assumption that they may have different and complementary focuses of specialization.

   What evidence can be offered for this suggestion? It is not difficult to find. Whenever the fundamental description-rules belonging to group C are accepted as applicable, the auxiliary description-rules could be absent, even on the whole. To prove this, imagine that the group of conditions A and B for the name ‘Aristotle’ are satisfied. Imagine that the proper name ‘Aristotle’ satisfies (a) its localizing description rule of being the person born in Stagira in 384 BC as the son of Amyntas II, the court doctor, who lived most of his life in Athens, had to flee to Assos, returned to Athens, but later had to flee to Chalkis, where he died in 322 BC… and (b) its characterizing description-rule of being the author of the relevant philosophical doctrines explained in Metaphysics, Physics, Nicomachean Ethics, Organon, Topics, and other main works of the Aristotelian opus. Now, try to imagine that he didn’t satisfy any auxiliary description rule usually attributed to him. Thus, suppose that he was neither Alexander’s tutor, nor Nicomachus’ son, nor Pythias’ husband, nor Herphyllis’ lover, nor the founder of the Lyceum. You can even imagine that his grandfather was not called Achaeon, that he did not have a son named Nicomachus, that he was never in Lesbos, that he was not called by Dante the master of those who know, etc. Even so, he could perfectly well still have been the greatest Greek philosopher, together with Plato… that is, our Aristotle! 

   However, the same cannot be said of fundamental descriptions. We cannot conceive that no fundamental description-rule applies; we cannot conceive of “~A & ~B.” Suppose that neither the localizing nor the characterizing description-rule applies, and the person is still called Aristotle. Then he will not be our Aristotle. To make this clear, just remember the example presented by Searle of the expert on Aristotle who informed us he had discovered that Aristotle could not have written any work attributed to him, since he was only an illiterate Venetian fishmonger of the late Renaissance... (1967: 490) We will answer that at most he may be talking about some homonym of ‘Aristotle’, who has nothing to do with the person we have the right reasons to call by this name, since none of the fundamental description-rules that we associate with the name ‘Aristotle’ was minimally satisfied by him.

   If the meta-identifying rule excludes “~A & ~B,” would it be reduced to “A & B”? Would it require the conjunction of the localizing description with the characterizing description, or should it perhaps just reject its disjunction? It would surely not require the conjunction. For although the objects referred to by proper names usually satisfy a conjunction of groups A and B of description-rules, it is not difficult to conceive of unusual situations and cases where a name refers without the descriptions constitutive of one of these two groups being satisfied.

   To highlight this point, consider once again the name ‘Aristotle’. It is not difficult to imagine possible worlds close to ours where he existed without satisfying the conjunction of the rules of location and characterization for that name. The spatio-temporal localizing rule for Aristotle does not necessarily need to be what his identification-rule demands: we can perfectly well conceive of a possible world close to ours where he wrote the Aristotelian opus, even though he was born and died in Rome a few centuries later, and there was no disciple of Plato named Aristotle who was born in Stagira in 384 BC.

   We can also conceive of a possible world where only the localizing rule for Aristotle is satisfied, but not the characterizing rule, for in this world the philosophy of Aristotle never existed. Suppose that in this world Aristotle was born in Stagira in 384 BC, the son of Nicomachus, the physician at Philip’s court and that at age 17 he moved to Athens to study under Plato. Unfortunately, shortly after his arrival, he was afflicted by a brain fever that left him unable to pursue intellectual activities for the rest of his life, until his death in Chalkis in 322 BC. Despite this, it seems that we have enough elements to recognize that person as our Aristotle “in potentia.” But here only the localizing rule is satisfied.

   Another piece of evidence that a conjunction of descriptive identification rules is not always necessary is that there are proper names that by convention refer to a single object only through its location or solely through its characterization.

   As an example of the first type, let’s say someone decides to call the center of a circle Z. This point satisfies the condition of type A of having a well-defined space-time location. Suppose this point has no relevant function. Nonetheless, to make the identification it is not necessary for a point to have any relevant distinctive characteristic. In our example, it is just a point, which once established can be used, say, for some geometric measurement. This is what I call a one-foot identifying rule.

   Another example that can be recalled in this context is ‘Venus’. The localizing rule is ‘the second planet in the solar system, orbiting the Sun between Mercury and Earth, which was identified thousands of years ago (and has probably existed for more than four billion years)’, while the characterizing rule should be ‘a planet with a third of the Earth’s mass and a very hot, dense, poisonous atmosphere’. However, what matters here is that the localizing rule must be satisfied, while the characterizing rule matters least. We see that even if Venus lost part of its mass or all its atmosphere, which is what makes it the brightest planet we can see with the naked eye, as long as it remained a planet – a condition already included in the localizing rule – it would remain Venus. We can also imagine that Venus lost so much of its mass so that it shrank to the size and form of an asteroid. In this case, it would satisfy neither its characterizing nor the relevant part of its localizing rule, which already demands that it must be a planet, for it would change from a planet to an asteroid. We can also imagine that it could for some reason cease to orbit the sun. In this case, it would not cease to satisfy the localizing rule, as we might think, because at the time when it was named (and so baptized) it would satisfy that rule, orbiting the Sun as the second planet. Even if it were discovered that it did not belong to the early solar system, but was a late comer, only having drifted in from outer space a million years ago, it would still satisfy the localizing rule, still being called ‘Venus’. On the other hand, it would be wrong to identify Venus by the satisfaction of the characterizing rule alone, as the disjunctive rule allows, since in this case any planet could be called Venus, insofar as it satisfies that rule. We need to accept that the identification rule for Venus is very much another case of a one-foot localizing rule.

   Perhaps the best way to paraphrase what happens in the cases above is to say that for them the characterizing rule is the localizing rule itself. Let us remember that the characterizing rule was defined as the reason why we chose to use the proper name. But in the case of the Z center of the circle, the only reason is the location itself, and in the case of Venus, the localization as the second planet from the Sun during and after naming is in fact the only reason that really counts.

   There are also examples that require only the satisfaction of the characterizing rule. One of them is offered by the name ‘Almostásim,’ which appears in Jorge Luis Borges’ short story entitled El aciercamento de Almostásim. Almostásim is a being, possibly a person, who when in contact with people emanates perfection. We do not know where this being is, and if it really exists somewhere in space and time. Some believe that we can approach it through contact with human beings who have become limited repositories of its infinite glory. Only these vague indications constitute the characterizing rule of that name. But there is no rule identifying its spatio-temporal location, as no one has ever encountered Almostásim, and some even commit the heresy of denying its existence. This is a case of a one-foot disjunctive rule.

   There is, finally, an example of a proper name that by definition cannot have a localizing rule: this is the word ‘Universe’ (or ‘Multiverse,’ as preferred by some). The object referred to by that name has a one-foot characterizing rule: it is all that could be shown to exist empirically, including things that are still to be verified. But it cannot have a localizing rule, because it contains all space and all time, since the Universe cannot be in space or time.[11]

   If we exclude the possibility of “~A & ~B” and also the need for “A & B,” it seems that the better candidate for a meta-descriptive condition for the application of the proper name could be “A ˅ B,” that is, an inclusive disjunction of the localizing and characterizing descriptions. We can conclude these considerations with a first and more rudimentary version of the general meta-identifying reference rule for proper-names, to be applied to fundamental first-level description-rules belonging to groups A and B. This meta-rule, to be called a disjunctive rule, will be inadequate, but furnishes a working model that in the following sections will be corrected and complemented.  

   Calling ‘N’ any chosen proper name, and using quotation marks to stress the arbitrariness of the choice involved in the rule’s instantiation by a proper name (Aristotle could be called ‘Pittacus’), calling G the nearest class of objects to which the proper name refers that does not mix with its descriptions (Aristotle does not belong to the class of prime numbers, but rather to that of human beings), and calling L and C respectively the localizing and characterizing description-rules, we can formulate the following second-order disjunctive rule:

 

      DR:

A proper name “N” refers properly to an x object belonging to a class G of objects

iff,

(i-a) x satisfies L: its localizing description-rule

and/or

(i-b) x satisfies C: its characterizing description-rule.

 

To DR we can add two tacit assumptions: (1) that there is a cluster of descriptions associated with ‘N’ that includes the localizing and the characterizing description-rules, and (2) that a non-empty ‘N’ must be in some unknown way causally associated with its reference (a C-condition).

   An example will make the application of the disjunctive rule clear: we can apply the proper name ‘Aristotle’ to an object of the class of human beings (G), if and only if there is an individual who (i-a) satisfies the localizing rule (L) for ‘Aristotle’, which is that of being a person born in Stagira in 384 BC, being the court physician’s son, having lived the main part of his life in Athens, taking refuge for some time in Lesbos, returning to Athens and, in the end, again as a refugee, dying in Chalkis, in 322 BC and/or (i-b) satisfies the characterizing rule of ‘Aristotle’ (C), of being the philosopher who produced the entire Aristotelian opus. This instantiation of DR can already be considered an identification rule for the bearer of the name ‘Aristotle’. Nevertheless, an identification rule that takes this form, as we will see later, is still unqualified and rudimentary.

   Some additional considerations about DR are indispensable. First, the applicability of DR assumes the satisfaction of some causal precondition like a C-condition, since some kind of causality is indispensable for a name to have a bearer. However, since the C-condition is an assumed background condition, without any independent explanatory or justificatory power, it does not take part of what explains how a proper name refers to its object or of what explicitly justifies its application. Thus, it does not need to belong to DR. Moreover, the disjunctive rule assumes as probable the satisfaction of auxiliary description-rules, though these conditions do not belong to DR.

   The second additional consideration is that ‘N’ refers properly or self-sufficiently to object x. We define a proper or self-sufficient reference as a reference made by idealized users of the name who know the rule well enough to employ it alone. This is often only possible for privileged namers (specialized, primary users, baptizers…). Here is the case of a reference of its own in the sense that it is made with a sufficient cognitive basis, for instance, by an Aristotle scholar. Often this is not what happens. For instance, one can refer to the pop singer Amy Winehouse, even if one knows only that she wrote a song called ‘Back to Black’, which is a central part of her characterizing rule, and even without knowing the proper name ‘Amy Winehouse’, in the right context others will instantly understand.

   A third additional consideration is that class G corresponds to a genus proximum, a concept used by Aristotle as part of the definition of concepts to distinguish the nearest class of properties to which the specific differentia belongs. In our case, G has the limiting function of establishing the nearest, most relevant genre of things to which object x belongs, such as living beings, material objects, celestial bodies, etc. The use of class G serves to limit the scope of the definition in advance, because without this we would have to pick out just one thing among all the objects in the universe, which could be a cognitively impossible task. Concerning the name ‘Aristotle,’ for example, G can designate the class of human beings, since the class of philosophers is already embedded in Aristotle’s characterizing description-rule as the greatest philosopher of antiquity. Consequently, with G we exclude in advance that ‘Aristotle’ is the name of a college or a computer program. Even if in a possible world an extremely advanced supercomputer with a program called ‘Aristotle’ produced the Aristotelian opus, assuming G we would not need to admit that this program is our Aristotle, even in the case where it was built by aliens in the year 384 BC in Stagira, used for more than twenty years in Athens, and finally dismantled in 322 BC in Chalkis. We would consider this a coincidence or a forgery. Differently from what Kripke would think, even if someone believes that Aristotle is an extra-terrestrial being, or supposes that he is an android, he will nevertheless be seen as human, that is, a human extra-terrestrial being or a human android (Cf. Soames 2002: 64). In sum: using a stricter G-class (not necessarily a scientific one) can be particularly useful for disambiguating proper names. If G is understood to be the class of ancient philosophers, this excludes the possibility that Aristotle could be the name of a 20th century philosophy student at the University of Athens.

   Here we could still ask the following question: in the DR, auxiliary descriptions disappear; but what then is the role of auxiliary descriptions? The answer begins to emerge when we ask ourselves whether auxiliary descriptions alone would be able to identify the bearer of a proper name. Suppose that a certain object satisfies many or all auxiliary descriptions associated with its name, but without satisfying any of the fundamental descriptions. Consider again the Searlean illiterate fishmonger who lived in the 16th century in Venice. But suppose he still satisfies many auxiliary descriptions for the name. He was the son of a man named Nicomachus, he was Achaeon’s grandson, he was Pythias’ husband, and had a lover called Herphyllis… he taught Alexander and he founded a Lyceum… However strange these coincidences would be, they would not be relevant, as they would lack the appropriate contexts of localization and characterization. After all, this Nicomachus could not be the physician named Nicomachus, who we know served at the court of Philip of Macedon, nor can the grandfather Achaeon be the same one who lived in the 4th century BC, and neither Pythias nor Herphyllis could be women of ancient Greece, despite their names. The Alexander whom this pseudo-Aristotle taught could not have been the famous general and conqueror from Macedonia. And the Lyceum that this inept person founded could have nothing to do with the Lyceum of the ancient Aristotelian School. The conceptual mess created in attempt to conceive a situation where only the auxiliary descriptions remained the same is not able to produce more than a series of curious, odd coincidences, which present themselves to us as a strange imitation of reality. It is unable to convince us that the proposed Aristotle is the real one. One can even imagine circumstances where the application of auxiliary descriptions would be justified. Suppose that the fishmonger called ‘Aristotle’ were a laughable comic figure who worked near a school called the Lyceum, and that schoolboys called his lover Herphyllis… or that by chance he had as a helper a young fishmonger called Alexander… No matter how much they complement each other, auxiliary descriptions alone are unable to provide us with the true identification rule. As we will see, the leading role of auxiliary descriptions is much different; they help us to insert the proper name into discourse (including public dialogue or communication), where they can, in senses to be explained later, at least point in the direction of the ultimate identification rule.

   Finally, what about the one-foot fundamental rules? One possibility is that the DR could in these cases be transformed into a rule of either the kind “A ˅ A” or the kind “B ˅ B”. In cases of complete absence of one foot, like the proper name ‘universe’, from which the localizing disjunction is simply missing, the best form must be “B ˅ B”, while in the case of the center Z, the best form will be “A ˅ A”. Consider, finally, the case of the planet Venus. The DR form “A ˅ B” cannot be applied to this case, since if it were the case, then any planet in the universe with the internal characteristics of Venus (any planet with almost the same size as the earth, and a very hot, dense, poisonous atmosphere) will be, according to the disjunctive rule, an exemplar of the planet Venus.  Instead of “A ˅ A”, this case can also be represented by the conjunction “A & B”, where B would be almost redundant, as it includes the characteristic of being a planet. These anomalies are important, because they will remain in the more complex rules to be considered in what follows, which are modified extensions of DR.

 

4. Meta-identifying rule: a preliminary version

Although the disjunctive rule is important, because it highlights the role of descriptions that really matter, it is by no means sufficient, since it is too narrow on the one side and too broad on the other. Regarding narrowness, we will soon see that there are cases of application where just one of the fundamental description-rules is satisfied, and even so only partially, while the other is not satisfied at all, although the name is still found to have a reference. As for breadth, where there is excessive amplitude, there could be cases of application of the proper name where both fundamental rules are applicable, and even then, the name still has no reference!

   Let us first consider a case that demonstrates the disjunctive rule’s narrowness of application. This is the obvious case where the localizing rule is incompletely but sufficiently satisfied, and the characterizing rule is not at all satisfied, even though the proper name applies. Imagine a possible world close to ours, where there was never an Aristotelian philosophy, but there was an Aristotle who died at a young age because while jouneying to Athens to study with Plato, his ship sank, and he drowned in the Aegean see. Even so, if we learn that he was born in Stagira in 384 BC, was the son of Nicomachus, the physician of Philip’s court, and was sent by his grandfather Achaeon to Athens at the age of 17 to study philosophy with Plato, we will have no doubt that he was our Aristotle in potentia, even if DR is not satisfied. The localizing rule, we see, is only partially satisfied, since the information we have about Aristotle’s biography ends at the age of 17. The characterizing rule, on its side, is not satisfied at all, since this young man, whose life was so tragically cut short by fate, left behind no writings. Our intuition is that even in this counterfactual situation our Aristotle would have existed, though the disjunctive rule is too coarse-grained to satisfy it.

   Let us now consider a case where only the characterizing rule is satisfied, and even that incompletely. Imagine a possible world close to ours where there was no Aristotle and no Aristotelian opus in the ancient world, although Plato and other Greek philosophers existed. Imagine that in that world, in the 10th century, in Damascus, an Arab philosopher who had read Greek philosophical works wrote in Arabic the main parts of Aristotle’s work, including the Organon, the Metaphysics, and the Nicomachian Ethics, using the pseudonym ‘Aristotle.’ In such a situation we would also tend, without much reluctance, to recognize this person as being our Aristotle, despite being an Arab philosopher and not Greek.

   Of course, there are limits involving too partial satisfaction of fundamental description-rules. Suppose that, in a possible world close to ours, where there was never an Aristotelian philosophy, in 384 BC the court doctor in Stagira had an anencephalic son who was called Aristotle, but as could be expected, died shortly after birth. In this case, although a minimum of the localizing rule and none of the characterizing rule is satisfied, this minimum seems unqualified, and we will have difficulty believing the newborn was our Aristotle. Also, if in a possible world an Arab philosopher with the pseudonym Aristotle had written only the first two paragraphs of book Alpha of Metaphysics, without any other contextual clue we certainly wouldn’t be able to recognize him as our Aristotle, since the characterizing description-rule would not be sufficiently satisfied. A case like this would be recognized by us as a strange, inexplicable coincidence. We conclude that the satisfaction of only one fundamental condition does not need to be complete, as DR demands, though it should also not be too weak.

   To make this suggestion more plausible, let us now consider cases where the characterizing descriptions are conjunctively satisfied, though only partially. In such cases, it appears that the minimum threshold of satisfaction required for each description would become lower than the minimum threshold of satisfaction for the description in the case where only one of the fundamental description-rules is incompletely, but sufficiently satisfied. So, if in a possible world a single Aristotle had been born in 384 BC, not in Stagira, but in Athens, had studied with Plato, written only the Categories, and then died, it seems that this would be enough for us to admit that he is our Aristotle. In this case, it seems that limited satisfaction of each disjoint results in fully sufficient satisfaction of the disjunctive rule as a whole. In other words, the requirement of sufficient satisfaction of inclusive disjunction must include consideration of the sum of the satisfactions of the disjoints. Our conclusion is that the disjunctive meta-descriptivist rule must be supplemented by a new condition, which can be called a condition of sufficiency. This condition can be stated as follows:

 

Condition of sufficiency: it must be required that the sum of the satisfactions of each of the two fundamental description-rules should be sufficient, in accordance with the given circumstances.

 

A question that remains is about the exact measure of what we should understand as sufficient. The most plausible answer is that there is no exact measure. After all, empirical language is inevitably vague, and our criteria for applying words do not define their extensional boundaries in a perfectly precise way. There are always ambiguous cases, where we cannot decide if our criteria apply. Important is that, despite this vagueness of our natural language, we are in general – actually, in nearly all cases – quite capable of publicly referring to objects without ambiguities. Therefore, the vagueness of natural language – which supposedly reflects the vagueness of the objective divisions of reality that we intend to categorize – should not be seen as an imperfection of our language. It is at the least a fact to be admitted. The right amount of linguistic vagueness is capable of modulating discourse in the most satisfactory way, opposing pointless and often undesirable insistence on precision. This vagueness only seems troublesome when, in the philosophical effort to scrutinize the limits of our concepts, we consider unusual limiting cases, as we are presently doing.

   Another important point is that in counterfactual situations Aristotle would cease to be our Aristotle if there were competitors who also satisfied the disjunctive rule in equal measure. So, imagine a possible world where it would not be unusual, but in fact quite natural, for people to have two heads. Imagine then that in 384 BC, Nicomachus, the physician at Philip’s court, had a son who was born with two identical heads, both baptized with the name ‘Aristotle.’ Suppose that the two-headed Aristotle journeyed to Athens to study with Plato, and further, by working together, these two heads wrote the entire Aristotelian opus. Although it is possible to say that this world had two “Aristotles” with parallel spatiotemporal careers (given that the two persons were permanently joined to the same body), from a more rigorous perspective it is also possible to argue that this world had no Aristotle in the usually given sense of the name, because a proper name is, in its most usual sense, a singular term that by definition can only be applied to a single object able to be distinguished from all others. It is largely a matter of convention whether in that world the two identical heads account for two Aristotles or only one.

   Such consideration leads us to a new condition to be added, which is that a proper name can have only one and the same reference. Consequently, it seems that we need to admit for the application of the meta-referential rule itself the condition of uniqueness:

 

Condition of uniqueness: it is the condition that in the considered domain, only a single and the same object of reference satisfies the disjunctive rule.

 

 The main case where the uniqueness condition is no longer satisfied is one where the localizing rule is satisfied by one object, while the characterizing rule is satisfied by another. This would be the case in a possible world W1 where there existed (a) a Greek Aristotle, son of Nicomachus, who was born in Stagira in 384 BC, but who contracted brain fever upon arriving in Athens and was so severely handicapped that he could do no work in philosophy in the years before his death in Chalkis in 322 BC, and (b) a philosopher named Aristotle, who wrote an identical Latin version of the Politics in Rome about three centuries later. In these circumstances, we could no longer have a way to decide who the real Aristotle was, whether the Greek or the Roman, because our two fundamental identification rules conflict with each other. The immediate and reasonable alternative is to abandon the assumption that our Aristotle existed in such a world, since the condition of the object’s uniqueness is not satisfied. (In criterial logic, 1 + 1 = 0.)

   By adding the conditions of sufficiency and uniqueness to the disjunctive rule, we achieve what could be called a meta-identifying rule, namely, a rule that will show us in a more precise and adequate way than does the disjunctive rule, under what conditions proper names are typically applicable to their references. This rule will tell us the adequate combinations of the fundamental description-rules that need to be satisfied by any proper name to allow us to say that it refers to its bearer. Here is how this rule can be formulated:

 

MIRp:

A proper name “N” refers properly (self-sufficiently) to an object x belonging to a class G of objects

iff

(i-a) x satisfies a localizing description-rule L of “N”

 and/or

(i-b) x satisfies a characterizing description-rule C of “N”

 And

      (ii) the satisfaction of L and/or C of “N” by x is overall (on the whole) sufficient and

      (iii) univocal

 (under the tacit assumption of an expected satisfaction ‘Ns’’ cluster of descriptions, and an unknown C-condition.)

 

I call the rule resulting from the application of the meta-identifying rule MIRp to the fundamental description-rules of a given proper name the identifying or definitional rule of that proper name – which is something equivalent to what Ernst Tugendhat hypothetically would call the Identifikationsregel of that singular term (1983: 235). (This identification rule may also be regarded, I think without a real difference, as a simple instantiation of MIRp in which the variables, “N”, G, L, and C, are replaced by constants, insofar as we consider MIRp a general form of the identification rules).

   Let us also remember that the condition (ii), of sufficiency, is to be applied “as a whole,” that is, to the sum of the satisfactions of each of them taken together. This allows us to rescue the intuition that the rule can be applied (and is therefore applicable) even when in isolation each single fundamental description-rule is considered to be unqualifiedly satisfied. The rule will apply if the sum of the satisfactions of each fundamental description-rule is considered by the privileged namer – tacitly reflecting the evaluation of the linguistic community – sufficient for its application.

   Finally, once we apply an identification rule that instantiates MIRp, we are necessarily led to the hypothetical conclusion that a C-condition is satisfied. One could here ask if MIRp could not be derogated in its application if we discover that the C-condition isn’t satisfied… But how could this discovery be made, except by descriptive means? We will see, in the next chapter, that when resulting elements of a causal record begin to have explanatory value, they are integrated into the disjunctive rule itself, gaining explanatory power.

   Let’s now look at a case where the MIRp is applied to the specific bundle of descriptions associated with the name Aristotle. By doing this we formulate what Tugendhat could call the identification rule for the proper name ‘Aristotle’, which I will abbreviate as IRp for ‘Aristotle.’ Here it is:

 

IRp-“Aristotle”:

The proper name “Aristotle” refers properly to an object x belonging to the class of human beings

iff

(i-a) x satisfies the localizing description-rule of having been born in Stagira in 322 BC, lived much of his life in Athens, and died in Chalkis in 322 BC (...)

 and/or

(i-b) x satisfies the characterizing description-rule of having been the philosopher who developed the great ideas that form the Aristotelian opus (...)

 And

(ii) the satisfaction of the localizing description-rule and/or of the characterizing description-rule for x is overall sufficient and

             (iii) Univocal.[12]

 

As I have already noted, the name Aristotle is also placed in quotation marks here in order to indicate that as a specific sensible mark it is not an indispensable component: another sign could possibly be agreed on to meet the same conditions.

   It is also important not to forget that the meta-identifying rules we are considering are meant to be applied by ideal types of speakers, who I call the privileged users of the proper name. As we will see, not all speakers know the identification rule and, in many cases, they are only oriented by some group of more or less relevant descriptions. As we will see later, we very frequently use proper names “referentially” in a weaker sense of the word, without having fulfilled this ideal. It will be at this point that the auxiliary descriptions will show their full importance in the cluster of descriptions associated with a proper name; but this is not the focus of the present discussion; so, for now I will ignore the role of descriptions belonging to group C.

   Finally, there is an ontological point that reinforces and is reinforced by the proposal made in the last chapter that a trope ontology may furnish the true key to the identification of individuals. Indeed, different combinations of tropes can be totally congruent with the demands made by identification rules derived from MIRp. An identification rule will tell us which combinations of definite descriptions and what amounts of them will be necessary to justify the application of a proper name, allowing us to say that it refers to its bearer. But in doing this, the rule will also show which combinations of tropes or t-properties must be found in the world in order to allow us to judge and say that the identifying rule is satisfied or applicable. Concerning examples with the proper name ‘Aristotle’, the tropical criteria can vary as much as:

 

a.     One (only) Aristotle from 10th century Damascus, who satisfies the tropes of having written the Organon, the Metaphysics, and the Nicomachean Ethics, and of having chosen ‘Aristotle’ as a pen name.

b.     One (only) Aristotle who was born in Stagira in 384 BC, the only son of the court physician, who contracted brain fever while traveling to Athens, dying in Assos in 322, but who satisfies most of the tropical properties concerning his spatiotemporal career.

c.     One (only) Aristotle born in Stagira in 384 BC who satisfies the tropes of first becoming a doctor like his father, joining Alexander’s army, and succumbing to dehydration and starvation while returning from the military campaigns in the East.

 

The important philosophical point is that now we do not need any “individuating essence” (here understood as a necessary and sufficient individuating tropical property) common to these three Aristotles that can be found in the world. The old idea of an objectively shared identifying essence of the object, which is impossible to be satisfied, is here replaced by the demand of an objectively grounded essence inscribed in the identification rule of its identifying linguistic unity. The identification rule gives us ways to unify those very different combinations of tropes found in the world that confirm the applicability of a proper name, allowing us to identify these three Aristotle as one person existing in different possible worlds. In other words: we agree that there is no objective property individualizing a referent like Aristotle. However, we have found a way of formulating the identifying rule for a proper name like ‘Aristotle’ that makes it possible to unify very different (clusters of) tropical properties by means of which the same referent can be presented to us. If there is here an essence, it is givenby the rule; it is a nominal, not a real one. As we will see later (Chap. V), the lack of unifying criterial essences can also occur with general terms. The problem of essence finds in this way a non-compromising solution.

 

5. Solving Theseus’ paradox

The MIRp already allows us to give the best answer to the famous puzzle of Theseus’ ship, so often cited in philosophical handbooks. Let us suppose that Theseus’ ship was named the ‘Calibdus.’[13] In the course of the years, Theseus gradually replaced the worn-out planks of his ship until eventually they were all replaced. However, it was decided to refurbish the old planks, which had been saved and kept in storage, repair them, and use them to build another ship identical to the first. Suppose that someone then asks, “Which of the two ships is the true Calibdus?” Paradoxically, we do not know for sure how to answer. A too hasty answer could be that both are Theseus’ Calibdus. That would be logically unacceptable, because a singular term cannot refer to more than one object of reference. Most people will tend to say that Theseus’ real ship is the one on which he sailed for all those years; but there will still be uncertainty: after all, the second ship is the only one that is made of the same planks as the one that was initially built! The problem is not irrelevant, because, as someone once noted, if the two ships were to collide head on and start sinking, Theseus, who, like every good captain was honor-bound to go down with his ship, would have had to decide whether to stay on the old ship or jump onto the new one.

   What we have considered so far makes possible a better answer to this old puzzle. The reason for the uncertainty is our realization that the question of which of the two ships is the true Calibdus has become unanswerable due to a criterial conflict between the two fundamental description-rules for that name. The first ship satisfies a localizing rule, which tells us that Theseus’ ship is the one built in a specific place and time, having then enjoyed a long space-time career under the command of Theseus. The second rule, satisfied by the second ship, belongs to the characterizing dimension. It tells us that Theseus’ ship is the one built from certain specifically given material… This conflict is understandably the reason for the uncertainty.

   At this point, someone can rightly object that the characterizing rule is much more complex. It not only concerns the same material, but also includes functional and structural characteristics that were preserved by both ships. Consequently, it seems that the first ship must be the Calibdus captained by Theseus, as it more completely satisfies the fundamental description-rules. That is why this is usually the first idea that comes to mind. Nevertheless, we can balance this intuitive difference by increasing the speed of replacing the old planks with new ones to shorten the ship’s space-time career until the replacement of all parts is complete. Imagine that the entire series of plank replacements took place in just two months. In that case, we’d start having doubts. What if the replacement took just one week? Calibdus is launched and soon afterwards, with Theseus supervising the work, the replacement of planks begins with the immediate construction of another ship… Then we begin to think that at the end of the week Theseus is not the captain of the Calibdus anymore! Imagine now that the construction of Theseus’ Ship is completed, but that it is not yet launched. Hours after it is ready, workers begin to build a second identical ship, next to the Calibdus. When both ships are completely built, the first one is baptized with the name ‘Calibdus’, while the second remains unnamed. Then workers begin to substitute the planks of Calibdus with planks from the second ship and vice-versa. After two days all planks of each ship have been removed and replaced by planks of the other. Which ship is now the true Calibdus? The answer seems obvious to us: the second ship is now the real Calibdus, because all that has happened is that both ships, so to speak, have exchanged places. Here the identity of the Calibdus’ original material is what warrants our intuition. It seems that the identification rule derived from the application of MIRp can give us the final explanation for the puzzle of Theseus’ Ship, since in this case the second ship better satisfies the identification rule for Calibdus.

   Finally, MIRp also allows us to give a straightforward answer to the oldest and simplest version of the puzzle. In this version, the question is whether the Calibdus would still be the same ship after having all its planks replaced.[14] The obvious answer is that since the Calibdus must be a single ship, and since it continues to satisfy the localizing and most of the characterizing rule, it does indeed remain the same ship.

   But let us return to the initial story of the Calibdus having sailed for a certain time under the command of Theseus. Because the same proper name cannot name more than one object, the strategy of renaming ships turns out to be a convenient way to avoid misunderstandings. We can give different names to the ships, assuming the existence of two ships: the Calibdus-1, which fully satisfies the localizing rule and much of the characterizing rule, and the Calibdus-2, which although not satisfying the localizing rule, completely satisfies the characterizing rule, which among other things requires the preservation of the same material of the ship ever since it was initially built. Similarly, in the previous example, we can propose the existence of two Aristotles in the possible world W1: Aristotle-1, who lived in ancient Greece and satisfies only the localizing rule, and Aristotle-2, who is the author only of a large part of the Aristotelian opus, and satisfies at least part of the characterizing rule, without satisfying the localizing rule. It would be a mistake, however, to see this as an answer to the same problem. It is simply a new move in the name game, a proposal for new conventions, for new reference terms, to be used in place of failed terms.

 

6. Meta-identification rule: final version

MIRp is already a very satisfactory rule, explaining most cases of a proper name’s application. However, it results from a still incomplete analysis. After all, it is not difficult to demonstrate that the condition of uniqueness is a derived condition and that MIRp does not account for counterexamples that depend on a prior stage of derivation. To prove this, I will examine two counterexamples.

   A first counterexample concerns the Twin-Earth fantasy. A Twin-Earth must be like ours, and everything on each planet exists and happens identically (or almost identically) to what exists and happens on the other. Thus, all that applies to one object on our Earth should apply to its Doppelgänger on the distant Twin-Earth. Nevertheless, even if we knew of a Twin-Earth somewhere in outer space, we would continue to have the very strong intuition that by pronouncing the name ‘Aristotle’ we are referring to our Aristotle and not to some other Aristotle on the Twin-Earth. However, if we consider our first formulation of the identification rule for Aristotle, it no longer seems applicable. After all, both the Aristotle of our Earth and that of the Twin-Earth sufficiently satisfy the disjunctive rule. After all, on the one hand, both seem to satisfy the rule of space-time localization, since both were born in 384 BC in Stagira, sons of the physician at Amyntas of Macedon’s court, etc. In addition, both Aristotles satisfy the characterizing rule: both wrote the Aristotelian opus down to the last comma. Hence, concerning the satisfaction of the disjunctive condition “(i-a) ˅ (i-b),” the two Aristoteles sufficiently satisfy the identification rule for the name ‘Aristotle.’ But if so, condition (iii) of uniqueness is no longer satisfied, resulting in the counter-intuitive conclusion that Aristotle did not exist. However, it is intuitively clear that he not only existed, but was also our Aristotle and not that of the distant Twin-Earth.

   Counterexamples with possible worlds can also be easily imagined. Let us say that in a possible world W2 in Stagira in 384 BC Nicomachus, the court doctor, became the father of twins, both baptized with the name ‘Aristotle.’ The first became a doctor like his father, joining Alexander’s army and succumbing to thirst and hunger while crossing the desert when he was returning from the East. The second went to Athens, where he learned philosophy from Plato and wrote all the Aristotelian opus. Since both sufficiently satisfy the localizing rule, both sufficiently satisfy the disjunctive condition “(i-a) ˅ (i-b)” required by the identification rule resulting from the application of MIRp to the cluster of descriptions associated with the name. However, also in this case the condition (iii) of uniqueness is no longer satisfied, leaving the identification rule for the name ‘Aristotle’ inapplicable and leading to the conclusion that Aristotle did not exist. However, such a result is also counterintuitive. Intuitively, we have no doubt that there is a single true Aristotle in W2 and that he is the second Aristotle and not the first. Only in a possible world W3, which only differs from W2 through the fact that the second Aristotle was not born, would we consider the first of them, the unfortunate physician, to be our Aristotle in potentia. Here the MIRp leads us to the puzzling conclusion that if we find an incomplete Aristotle, we are allowed to call him our Aristotle, but if we find two Aristotles, then we are not allowed to.[15]

   The question we should ask here is: what leads us in the first counterexample to choose the Aristotle of the Earth over the Aristotle of the Twin-Earth? And, in the second, what leads us to choose the Aristotle who wrote the Aristotelian opus instead of the one who became a doctor? There can be only one answer: a sufficient satisfaction of the disjunction of localizing and characterizing conditions by more than one object must be complemented, not by a condition of uniqueness, but by a condition that objects that are less able to satisfy the disjunction must be excluded from the competition for the right to satisfy the conditions for applying a proper name. The solution, therefore, is to replace the condition of uniqueness with what could be called a condition of predominance, which can be stated as follows:

 

Predominance condition: the condition that in the case where more than one object sufficiently satisfies the disjunctive condition of a proper name, the bearer of the proper name must be the object that most completely satisfies it.

 

Such an addition allows us to easily solve the two counterexamples above. For in the first, the Earth Aristotle satisfies the disjunctive rule added to the condition of sufficiency better than the Twin-Earth Aristotle, since the condition of localization implies that the right Aristotle should have been born in the Stagira on our Earth, lived in the Athens on our Earth… and died in the Chalkis on our Earth… a condition that the Aristotle from the distant Twin-Earth cannot satisfy. In the second counterexample, the Aristotle who wrote the Aristotelian opus also better satisfies a identification rule that replaces the condition of uniqueness with the condition of predominance, since he is the only one who satisfied the condition of characterization by having written the Aristotelian opus.

   Based on such considerations, I now want to suggest a last and improved formulation of the meta-identification rule, which incorporates into itself this last condition. Here it is, remembering that we are considering a rule only as used by privileged namers:

 

      MIRf:

A proper name “N” refers properly (self-sufficiently) to an object x belonging to a Class G

iff

(i-a) x satisfies N’s localizing description-rule L

and/or

(i-b) x satisfies N’s characterizing description-rule C,

(ii) x satisfies L and/or C to an overall sufficient extent, and

      (iii) x satisfies L and/or C more than any other object,

(Under the implicit assumption of a an expected satisfaction ‘Ns’’ cluster of descriptions, and an unknown C-condition.)

 

Here we replace the condition (iii), which was one of uniqueness, with the condition of predominance, which is prior to that of uniqueness, since it serves to guarantee it. The predominance condition is applied in such a way as to select the object that sufficiently satisfies the inclusive disjunction of the disjuncts more than any other object of the same class that also satisfies it, from which we obtain an unambiguous identification of the proper name’s reference.

   As in the previous case, when the MIRf is applied to the fundamental description-rules constituting any proper name (or, treating MIRf as the general form of the identification rules, when we consider the last ones as simply instantiations of MIRf’s formal variables), it produces an identifying or definitional rule for the proper name, to be applied by an ideal speaker. Here is how this identification rule can be summarized for the name ‘Aristotle’:

 

IRf-‘Aristotle’:

The proper name “Aristotle” refers properly to an object x belonging to the class of human beings

iff

(i-a) x satisfies the localizing description-rule of being born in Stagira in 384 BC, having lived much of his life in Athens… and died in Chalkis in 322 BC,

and/or

(i-b) x satisfies the characterizing description-rule that it was the philosopher who produced the relevant content of the Aristotelian opus.

(ii) x satisfies the disjunction (i-a) and/or (i-b) to a degree that is overall sufficient and

      (iii) x satisfies the disjunction (i-a) and/or (i-b) more than any other human being.

 

Detailing what we have noted above, the identification rule RIf-‘Aristotle’ resulting from the application of MIRf to Aristotle’s fundamental description-rules gives us a clear and intuitive answer to the problem of the Twin-Earth’s Aristotle. According to this answer, although both the Earth Aristotle and the Twin-Earth Aristotle satisfy the disjunctive rule sufficiently, the Aristotle of our Earth is the only one who truly satisfies the condition of spatio-temporal localization. After all, as philosophers have plausibly noted, there is only one space, and we are talking about our own region of this space. Since only the first Aristotle exists in our spatio-temporal region, and the localizing description-rule is made to be applied to our spatio-temporal region of a single space that includes both Earths – and not to the analogous spatio-temporal region located on the distant Twin-Earth – our first Aristotle is the only one who really satisfies the localizing condition. Thus, our Earth Aristotle satisfies the disjunctive condition “(i-a) ˅ (i-b)” more completely than the Twin-Earth Aristotle. In doing so, he fulfills the predominance condition of the identification rule for Aristotle resulting from the application of MIRf to the fundamental description-rules associated with that name, which is in full agreement with our intuition that we are referring to our Earth Aristotle.

   The application of RIf-‘Aristotle’ also solves the problem of the twin Aristotles who sufficiently satisfy the disjunctive condition (i) in W2. Only in his childhood does the first (who marched to India with Alexander) satisfy the localizing rule, satisfying this rule sufficiently, but he never satisfies the characterizing rule. The second (who went to Athens and wrote the Aristotelian opus) not only completely satisfies the localization rule, but also completely satisfies the characterizing rule. For this reason, due to the great predominance in the satisfaction of the disjunctive rule, we choose the latter Aristotle as the true one, which also conforms to our intuitions. In a world W3, where the second Aristotle never existed, but only the first, we will tend to identify the former as our Aristotle, even if he was unfortunately prevented from accomplishing the great intellectual deeds we attribute to him.

   Returning to MIRf,, there remains one question to be answered. Imagine that other names for the same object, with their own identification rules, were competing with the identification rule we are considering. Thus, if various clusters of descriptions associated with the various proper names N1... Nn have their MIRfs satisfied by the same object, that is, if different identification rules are satisfied by the same referent, it seems that a condition should be proposed so that we can decide which of the proper names truly refers to that object. Would it not be necessary to have a predominance condition requiring that to be referred to by a name, an object should satisfy the disjunctive identification rule for the name in question more than any other identification rule that also refers to it?

   Fortunately, it does not seem that in the case of proper names this additional condition needs to be introduced, because any new and different criterion or cluster of criteria for the identification of an object will only be added to the old ones, even if this also means the addition of a new aspect that had previously been overlooked or unknown. These criterial tropes typically concern characterizing description-rules, since concerning the localizing description-rules we cannot have two different spatio-temporally localizing descriptions for the same object. A confirming example of two apparent identification rules that are added for the same object was that of Father Marcial Maciel presented in the previous chapter. This famous imposter used the alias ‘Raúl Rivas’ while courting Senõrita Gutiérrez, deceiving her with the fraudulent claim to be an Esso employee and CIA agent. These and other descriptions of Raúl Rivas should be added to the descriptions belonging to the cluster associated with the proper name ‘Marcial Maciel’, which is the most inclusive.

   An adverse example, but still in accordance with what we said, is the following. Suppose it is discovered, as has long (and implausibly) been speculated, that Francis Bacon was the true author of Shakespeare’s works, and that there was no Shakespeare who independently satisfied the characterizing condition attributed to him by us of having written the complete Shakespearean opus. So considered, it seems that the rules of identification for Bacon and Shakespeare should compete. However, this does not have to be so. We do not really find ourselves forced to choose between Bacon being Bacon and Bacon being Shakespeare. In this case, we will extend the attributes of Bacon to encompass the characterizing attributes of Shakespeare, saying that in addition to being a scientist, philosopher, and diplomat, Bacon also anonymously wrote the poems and plays attributed to Shakespeare.

   However, what about the Shakespeare born in Stratford-upon-Avon in 1564, who married Anne Hathaway? That must now be another person, another referent, for whose identification there must be another identification rule. The important thing to be noticed is something that no one denies, namely, that for the case in question, the weightiest element is by far the satisfaction of the characterizing description-rule, besides the fact that Bacon lived in London at that same time, thus partially satisfying the localizing condition. Thus, in our imaginary example, Bacon better satisfies the identification rule for the proper name ‘Shakespeare’ than does the Shakespeare born in Stratford-upon-Avon. Several utterances could sum up this identity dispute: not only “Bacon was the real Shakespeare” and “The person baptized as Shakespeare was not the person we call Shakespeare,” but also, say, “Bacon was the great playwright; Shakespeare was just a fellow thespian and theatrical director”.

 

7. Proper name’s semantic geography

Let us now look at the question of a proper name’s meaning or, to avoid ambiguities, of the semantic content that can be attributed to it. To arrive at an answer, it helps to recall the argument presented in the introductory chapter suggesting that any meaning – here restricted to the semantic-cognitive meaning corresponding to the Fregean sense (Sinn) of a singular term – is plausibly clarified in terms of rules or combinations of rules that enable the effective application of expressions.[16] The reason seems simple to me. Rules are the originating source of what we call meaning, since rules are meaningful per se. Following a rule is the same as giving meaning to something. If “&%” seems less significant than “à$,” it is because we are used to regarding an arrow as the expression of a rule indicating a direction, and the dollar sign as a rule indicating value. Where there is a rule, there is a meaning of some kind, even if usually not of the kind that may interest us here, as in the case of syntactical rules. More specifically, assuming Wittgenstein’s dictum that “meaning is what the explanation of meaning explains” (1984b Sec. 560), it seems clear that when we talk about the meaning of a linguistic expression, we are usually considering more properly the rules that we rely on in explaining what we mean by the expression. Furthermore, a meta-descriptive neodescriptivist theory of proper names, being a theory of semantic rules expressed by replacing descriptions, is no more or less than a theory of the referential or cognitive criterial meanings of proper names, since these description-rules explain the referential meanings of the names. Moreover, from the ontological viewpoint assumed in the last chapter, these rules can be nothing but repeatable tropes of a psychological nature. Meanings promise to lose their mystifying character when seen from this perspective.

   The acceptance of proper names’ meaningfulness contrasts sharply with the opinion of those who argue that proper names are meaningless. The reasons they offer are well-known: when asked the meaning of a proper name, we do not know what to say (Ziff 1960: 93-94). Moreover, as we have previously noted, proper names are generally not defined in dictionaries; and as the purpose of dictionaries is to clarify the meanings of words, this is an additional reason for rejecting the claim that proper names have meanings.[17]

   However, this thesis does not withstand closer scrutiny. Certainly, any proper name has meaning in the sense of having the lexical function of a proper name, which is the function of identifying some singular object as being its bearer. But it also has meaning in the most substantive sense of possessing semantic-cognitive content constituted by identifying rules. That a proper name should have meaning in this last sense is immediately clear when we consider sentences about identity between proper names. Repeating something basic, we can remember as an example Robert Louis Stevenson’s story of a man with two diametrically opposed personalities alternately competing for control of his psyche: Dr. Jekyll and Mr. Hyde. The statement “Dr. Jekyll is Mr. Hyde,” would be tautological and non-informative if the proper names ‘Jekyll’ and ‘Hyde’ were not intended to refer to rather contrasting things – if they did not have diverse characterizing semantic-cognitive contents, that is, different meanings. After all, although Dr. Jekyll and Mr. Hyde shared the same body, they differed in their guiding intentions and subsequent behaviors; while Dr. Jekyll was a good person, sometimes a bad side dominated his psyche, after he took a potion that gave control of his personality to the demonic Mr. Hyde. In other words: the localizing description-rule remains satisfied by the same human body, while the satisfaction of the characterizing description-rule alternates intermittently from Dr. Jekyll’s character traits to Mr. Hyde’s character traits, changing what we are emphazising in meaning. – Today we would tend to call it a problem of a split personality of the same (mind-body) person, so that “Dr. Jekyll = Mr. Hyde” means not only “Jekyll’s person = Hyde’s person,” but also “Jekyll’s character ≠ Hyde’s character”, that with the names ‘Jeckill’ and ‘Hyde’ we are eliciting two different characterizing rules, two cognitive contents alternatively applied to the same object of reference. The sentence “Dr. Jeckill is Mr. Hyde” says two things: (a) that there is an identity in the object that can be expressed using the identity sign: “Dr. Jeckill = Mr. Hyde”, since the whole identification rule for Jeckill-Hyde is the same. But it also says (b) that there is a difference in what Frege would call the mode of presentation, here constituted by the alternative employment of different characterizing rules, one for Jeckill’s character, the other for Hyde’s character. This semantic-cognitive difference can be made explicit when we say that both characters are different using a sentence like “Dr. Jekyll ≠ Mr. Hyde”. This point will be considered in more details in the nex chapter.

   Moreover, if we admit the Fregean understanding of semantic content, it explains itself as meaning (Sinn), which is informative content (informatives Gehalt). But if it is informative, then it becomes increasingly clear that in this aspect proper names should not be lacking, but, on the contrary, full of meaning, full of content. As Arthur Burks noted in his short but important paper on proper names:

 

That proper names have meaning is shown by the fact the people apply them consistently and use them to communicate. A person using a name correctly must have in mind some properties… which enable him in favorable circumstances to decide whether or not a given individual is the designatum of that name. (1951: 38)

 

After all, it seems that many of them are repositories of a diffuse mass of variously accessible informational content. Consider, for example, the immense amount of informational content that we can associate with the name of the emperor Napoleon or the philosopher Bertrand Russell. Russell’s excellent autobiography is full of informative content about himself, and all this information content comes to be at least implied by the proper name ‘Bertrand Russell’. From such a perspective, the issue is not so much that the proper name contains (or implies) less meaning, but rather too much. And so much so that the best place to look for the meanings of influential proper names is not in a dictionary, but rather in an encyclopedia. And in some cases, more than the encyclopedia, the place where we find the most detailed and complete content of meaning of a proper name is in a biography. Biographies such as Plutarch’s Parallel Lives, and autobiographies, such as Ingmar Bergman’s The Magic Lantern, are rich sources where we can find detailed expositions of the mass of informational contents associated with the regarded proper names – contents that in their essentials can easily be compressed and abridged into definite descriptions. In such works the rules of localization and characterization are not included in an abbreviated form, as we have done here, but rather in a much more detailed and complete form.

   There is also another reason why some think that proper names are meaningless. It is a fact that, when we casually use a proper name, all we often know about it are vague and variable aspects of its meaning, limited parts of its information content, whose domain generally varies from speaker to speaker, and even from occasion to occasion for the same speaker. The full content of many proper names, particularly scientific ones, is completely known only by a few privileged users, and often by no one of them in a complete way. When we contrast this situation with the permanent, distinct, and universally shared meaning of the simplest general terms (such as, say ‘red’ and ‘round’), we have the impression that because proper names do not mean anything specific for their users, they are not able to mean anything at all. Actually, proper names have so much meaning that they seem to have none.

   Having identified cognitive meanings with criterial rules and their combinations, let us now consider the question of the meanings of proper names from the already considered view of descriptive expressions. What would be the semantic value that really matters? A first rule to be excluded is the meta-identification rule itself, the MIRf: the distinctive semantic nucleus of a proper name cannot be constituted by it, as it is no more than a simple form shared by the identification rules of the most diverse proper names, while what matters most for the meaning of a term is what semantically distinguishes it from homonyms and other terms of the same kind. The meaning should also not be relevantly constituted by the auxiliary rules expressed in the descriptions of group C, since they are accidental in relation to the application of the name, although they are expected to contribute to some extent to its informative content and even to a great extent to its use in discourse. What remains are the fundamental rules of localization and/or characterization, expressed respectively by the descriptions of groups A and B in the clusters and entering into the identification rules of a proper name, singularizing both the name and its reference. Hence, these fundamental rules must be those which in a relevant way constitute the meaning of a proper name. If we ask ourselves, for example, which descriptions express the core of what should be meant by the name ‘Aristotle’, we tend to accept that it means the ancient Greek philosopher who studied with Plato in Athens and who developed ideas that profoundly influenced the course of Western philosophy; ideas presented in works such as Metaphysics, Ethics, Nicomachean Ethics, and the Organon. When all that a person is able to say of Aristotle is that he was ‘a famous Greek philosopher’, he is saying something that is already implied by the fundamental descriptions. Thus, the fundamental description-rules are those that express the indispensable informative content constituting the central nucleus of meaning of that proper name. If a person who watched a film about Alexander learned that he had been taught by a philosopher called ‘Aristotle’, and then tells us he was ‘the teacher of Alexander’, we decide he is referring to Aristotle, because we associate this definite description with fundamental localizing and characterizing descriptions we know, even if in most cases only in a vague way.

   Apart from the central semantic nucleus, we can see that there is certainly a halo of secondary meanings, generally expressed by auxiliary description-rules. Thus, it seems that the metaphorical auxiliary description ‘the master of those who know’, formulated by Dante to connote Aristotle, also contributes to the mass of informative content that constitutes the full significance of this proper name. In the same way, better known accidental descriptions, such as ‘Plato’s greatest disciple’, ‘the tutor of Alexander’, ‘the founder of the Lyceum’... do so as well and even better in parasitical uses since those who know them are already able to give some clearly convergent meaning to the name Aristotle. Not all auxiliary rules, however, contribute to enriching the informative content of proper names. Ignored accidental description-rules, such as ‘Achaeon’s grandson’, certainly do not contribute in a relevant way. Even parasitical uses are here very improbable. And by their circumstantial nature, adventitious description-rules, such as ‘the philosopher mentioned by the teacher in the classroom’, contribute nothing to the permanent informative content of the proper name, and therefore will never be found in encyclopedias or biographies. Nevertheless, it can be said that adventitious description-rules still express an occasional sense which is intended by a name when a user employs it, and a borrowed or parasitical reference when it is correctly understood by his hearers.[18]

   To avoid confusion, it is always indispensable to distinguish between the complete or full meaning and the intended meaning of a proper name. Let’s start with the intended meaning. This is the variable content that different people and even the same person at different times has in mind when employing a proper name. It is what Frege, Strawson, and Searle usually had in mind and what Russell called the “description in our minds”. (1980: 30) We can say that it consists in what is, if not consciously, at least unconsciously intended by a speaker when he thinks or utters a name, considering that the intention does not need to be consciously elaborated. I say that this meaning is at least fully intended, because what is intended in terms of description-rules – which can be both fundamental and auxiliary – does not need to be reflexively considered at the time of the name’s application, although it determines the meaning-in-use of the name by the speaker and can in principle be made conscious. Moreover, it is common for us to know very little of the meanings of many proper names we use, so that the intended meaning rarely coincides with the complete meaning. Who knows, for example, the complete meaning of the name ‘string theory’? Even specialists do not know the full range of theoretical alternatives attached to the concept of string theory.

   As for the complete meaning, it is constituted primarily by what we can call the proper or essential meaning: the set formed by localizing and characterizing description-rules – the semantic core. Secondarily it is also formed by what we might call auxiliary meaning: the one constituted by auxiliary rules – the semantic halo. Furthermore, it is important to note that the borders are blurred between descriptions that belong to the semantic core and those that belong to the semantic halo. Ask yourself, for instance, if the definite description ‘the greatest of Plato’s disciples’ belongs to the characterizing or the auxiliary descriptions of the bundle we associate with the name ‘Aristotle’.

   The following scheme summarizes the distinctions made above with respect to the meaning of a proper name:

 

                                                                                              Proper meaning

                                               Full meaning                         (semantic core)

                                               (possibly only known

Cognitive                                 by privileged namers)          Auxiliary meaning

meaning                                                                                (semantic halo)

(= informative

content or the                         Intentional meaning of the proper name                      

Fregean senses                       (identified with the meaning given by the

of the proper                            proper name’s user when it is applied)

name)

 

With this picture in mind, it becomes easy to clarify the semantic role of the auxiliary rules expressed by group C descriptions. Clearly, a person who knows only one auxiliary description-rule does not yet have sufficient knowledge of the proper name’s meaning. But auxiliary description-rules such as ‘the iron marshal,’ ‘Plato’s greatest disciple,’ or even ‘the philosopher quoted by the professor,’ may already suffice to enable the speaker to insert a proper name into speech in a communicatively effective manner, achieving referential success in a derived sense of the word. Moreover, if a speaker inserts this unqualified allusion to the referential term into public discourse, it is important that he is aware of his unqualified knowledge of its meaning. After all, this person is only able to rationally insert a proper name in discourse, if he is using it with the intention of referring in a weak or unqualified sense, even though he is part of a linguistic community that in its linguistic division of labor ultimately has links with interpreters capable of completing the meaning and reference of the proper name. That is: in such a community, assuming the right context, other people understand to whom the speaker is intending to refer, or at least this intention is socially comprehensible. This unqualified reference, understood as the assumption that a complete reference can in principle be socially rescued, is based, as we will see, on an improved form of reference borrowing already anticipated in Strawson’s concept of reference borrowing and, more decisively, in Searle’s concept of parasitic reference.

 

8. Ordinary proper names

You may now wonder whether MIRf would apply to the proper names of ordinary people, whose contents of meaning can be found in neither encyclopedias nor biographies. The answer is that there is no essential difference in relation to the above considered cases; the real difference usually lies only in the greater spread or dispersal of the characterizing description-rules, which can more often be only aspectually known by the contact with many different pragmatically moved speakers. To understand this, imagine an elderly man remembering a woman he once knew named Bärbel Hildish. If asked who Bärbel was, he could perhaps say that she was (i) “the nice lady who helped me several times when I went to ask about rooms in the Student Dormitories at the University of Bielefeld, and who had fascinatingly exotic facial features” (adventitious description). The man who had formerly been her husband, Felix Schneider, might remember something very different. Perhaps he would say that she was (ii) “the woman who was my wife for sixteen years and who had two children with me” (part of the characterizing description-rule). The children, for their part, could perhaps agree that (iii) “our mother was a cheerful person with great human understanding” (widely known accidental description). Her father, Tobias Hildish, might recall that she was (iv) “a very playful child” (little known accidental description). The last ones emphazise emotional motivations.

   Descriptions like these are often aspectual, even if this is the way we frequently know people. But let’s say someone wants a more detailed and precise characterization of who Frau Bärbel Hildish was, for example, a civil servant. In this case, one will use a document like a passport, drivers license, or other official ID, which will typically specify place and date of birth, including a photo and a fingerprint. These descriptions are less aspectual and more concerned with fundamental elements.

   Let’s now say that Frau Hildish were involved in a lawsuit.[19] In this case, a history of the addresses where she lived could be required, in addition to personal details, her level of education, professional history, police records, and of course photos, fingerprints, etc. Let’s just say, finally, that someone in her family decides to write a biography of Frau Hildish. In this case, all the above elements will certainly be drawn upon. The conclusion we reach is that, although aspectual knowledge plays a more important role in the legal case, as there is no major reason for very many people to remember common names, this knowledge exists in connection with the fundamental description-rule for identifying Frau Hildish. This constitutes the localizing description-rule summarized as follows:

 

The person who was born on 12.3.1926 in Berlin, whose parents were Tobias and Frida Hildish, spent her youth in Stuttgart and later lived in Bielefeld, where she died on 26.4.2018.

 

Followed by the characterizing description-rule summarized as follows:

 

The woman who was married to Herr Felix Schneider, with whom she lived for sixteen years, having two children. After their separation, she worked in the Student Administration of the University of Bielefeld, later was a diligent manager of the same, and looked very much as shown in photos.

 

The descriptions one initially knows are either auxiliary or, to a greater or lesser extent, components of the localization and characterization rules of Frau Hildish. Here the question arises: few know in detail the localization and characterization rules; how then is it possible that many people are able to refer to Frau Hildish with as little information to go on as the descriptions of (i) to (iv)? The obvious answer is that this is achieved by means of enhanced reference borrowing, also called parasitic reference. Details of this answer will be addressed in the next section.

 

9. A socio-linguistic division of cognitive labor

Against the MIRs and the consequent identification rules, one could still raise the following objection: We do not need to know the fundamental descriptions associated with a proper name in order to be able to use it in a sufficiently correct manner. Perhaps the only thing most people know about Aristotle today is that he satisfies the indefinite description ‘a great philosopher of ancient Greece’. A person who knows only this knows only some generalities implied by Aristotle’s localizing and characterizing descriptions. Even so, we would still say that this person is referring to Aristotle. Moreover, a person can be understood as referring to Aristotle, even associating this name with a single auxiliary description such as ‘Plato’s greatest follower’ after seeing a picture of Raphael’s famous fresco, The School of Athens, or ‘Alexander’s tutor’ after watching a film about Alexander’s life, or even with an adventitious auxiliary description such as ‘the philosopher about whom my uncle has spoken’. Furthermore, for a philosopher like Kripke, a person could even refer to Aristotle by associating him with an erroneous description, such as ‘a Greek general’ or ‘a medieval philosopher’. We have already said something as an answer to the problem. My intention now is to go into details.

   One way to give a complementary answer to the question of parasitic or borrowed reference consists in the appeal to what might be called a descriptivist-internalist understanding of the hypothesis of the division of labor in language. This division was originally proposed by Hilary Putnam for his non-descriptivist externalist view of the conceptual references of general terms. For him, many words are used by different people in different ways, each way containing its own greater or lesser pieces of information, which can be more or less specialized, so that they are all interrelated in the social network of our language. For him, words achieve their meanings not through psychological states, but in “the sociolinguistic state of the collective linguistic body” (1975: 229). Here he uses the pertinent metaphor of a steamship:

 

We may summarize this discussion by pointing out that there are two sorts of tools in the world: there are tools like a hammer or a screwdriver, which can be used by one person; and there are tools like a steamship which require the cooperative activity of a number of persons to use. Words have been thought of too much on the model of the first sort of tool. (1975: 229)

 

Essentially, different people use ships with different functions and purposes; most people use them as passengers who do nothing but ride on them to reach their destination. Others use them like crew members, having more active roles. They can work as pilots, serve in the engine room, perform on-board services... This variety of uses is surely a factor in the application of most general terms with scientific connotations, like ‘water’, ‘neoplasia’, ‘entropy’, ‘quark’, ‘string’, although, as it seems, not of more everyday terms like ‘stone’, ‘chair’, and ‘house’. Putnam was thinking of natural kind words. We will discuss his views in the right time. My question here, however, is: can we apply a similar understanding of a socio-linguistic division of labour to our cognitivist-descriptivist understanding of proper names?

   Putnam, committed to his semantic externalism, considers the linguistic division of labor as involving social groups and does not resort to cognitive-descriptive semantic aspects that psychologically understood should belong to their diversified component members. However, it is important to note that prima facie his externalist commitment is arbitrary, since it is even easier to imagine a division of semantic labor comprising diverse levels of descriptively expressible cognitive abilities that speakers, or even groups of speakers, need to have in order to warrant the most complete referential use of a word. After all, as A. D. Smith noted (1975: 70-73), allusions to something like the division of labor in language can be found in the writings of internalist philosophers preceding Putnam, beginning with John Locke himself, who was the classic advocate of a descriptivist semantics in which meanings are psychological ideas.[20] Moreover, Putnam’s arguments for his externalism of meaning are, as we will later see, more than controversial.[21]

   Having this in mind, my goal is to apply the above view to proper names, first classifying the divisions of language work into degrees of cognitive abilities in the application of the descriptively expressible semantic-cognitive contents that various speakers can associate with those terms. It seems clear that when we attribute reference to a name, we can have in mind different degrees of referential success. Three proheminent cases can be easily identified:

 

(A) that of a proper, self-contained, self-sufficient reference,

(B)  that of a parasitic or borrowed, unqualified reference.

(C)  that of an unhappy, failed reference.

 

Let us first consider the case (A) of the reference I call self-sufficient (proper referencing). We can understand it as the reference made by privileged users of a name, capable of offering identification of an object as a referent that exists in the world, guaranteed by the application of its proper name’s identification rule, that is, by the application of the proper name’s localizing and/other characterizing description-rules sufficiently and predominantly, at least in typical cases.

   There are many proper names, for example, those of our close relatives, whose identification rules we can self-sufficiently know, so that we are essentially privileged users. But there are other proper names whose relevant informative contents are known by only a few privileged users, such as, say, experts, historians, biographers, witnesses of their baptism… Consider, for example, the proper names ‘Kublai Khan’, ‘Battle of Salamis’, ‘Andromeda Galaxy’. A self-sufficient reference to the bearers of these names requires privileged users who can properly refer to their bearers, ideally being responsible for their institution and maintenance. Furthermore, among these privileged users/namers, we can find sub-specialized divisions of labor. The Battle of Salamis, for instance, will be seen differently by an historian, a military strategist, and a geographer, each knowing more about different special aspects of the event than others know.

   It often happens that when we attribute reference, we are considering unqualified reference. What a person has in mind is only an unqualified description-rule (B), which can be:

 

(B1) insufficient, in the sense of being schematic or accessory, or even

(B2) inappropriate, in the sense of being erroneous, although still convergent in the sense of being correctly classified – a reference whose character is derived.

 

As for insufficiency due to deficiency, it is customary to attribute this to people who know only generalities or auxiliary descriptions associated with a proper name. Thus, two persons can agree about the existence of ‘the great old Spanish painter called “Velázquez”’ without having seen his paintings and knowing nothing more about him; we do not deny that they can refer to Velásquez, although in an unqualified way, in sense B1. They are able to insert the name into discourse, and people who know something about Velázquez will usually agree that they are referring to the classic Spanish painter. However, in a more demanding sense, they do not know the painter about whom they are talking. The same can be said of people who only know that Aristotle is a figure in a famous fresco painted by Raphael, or who have seen him in a Hollywood movie, where he appeared as Alexander’s tutor. These persons are referring to the philosopher only in an extended sense of the word, in the sense that they are able to insert the name ‘Aristotle’ in undemanding conversational contexts, assuming that there are interpreters able to do something with the name, either because they are privileged namers or because they know as much as the speaker, but are confident that there are privileged namers who have sufficiently mastered the identification rule in order to be able to recognize in their use an attempt to identify the same person, the painter that privileged namers could actually refer to in a self-sufficient way. To this we must add that such a mechanism of reference borrowing works insofar as there is a common general context that is sufficiently determined to disambiguate the proper name (e.g., Aristotle is understood by hearers as the name of a thinker, and not as the name of a school or a Greek shipping magnate… Velázquez is understood by hearers as a great painter and not just a person living in a Spanish village). Through what I prefer to call an enhanced mechanism of reference borrowing, generalities regarding fundamental description-rules (e.g., the Greek philosopher Aristotle) and popular auxiliary descriptions (e.g., the greatest disciple of Plato) are recognized by others as part of the common general context. Satisfaction of B1 or B2 and of a common general context allows the sharing of a borrowed reference without directly appealing to privileged namers, though assuming their existence.[22]

   Insufficiency occurs in degrees. A degree of insufficiency that is somewhat lower than that of the examples above is given by Kripke’s example of a person who can associate a proper name only with an indefinite description, as in the case of a person who associates the proper name Feynman with the indefinite description of him as ‘a great physicist’. A description can, however, also be clearly inappropriate, though still worthy of the term ‘referential’ in our natural language. This is the case with Kripke’s example of an erroneous description such as ‘the inventor of the atomic bomb’ associated with the name Einstein (1980: 81-85). In most cases, these people make such associations with a full understanding of the grammar of proper names (implicitly knowing MIRf, and having sufficient background information to be aware of what they can – and especially of what they cannot – do with a proper name). In such cases we are still accustomed to say that the person was successful in referring, since the speaker, as well as his audience, normally knows that Einstein belonged to the class G of human beings, or that he was a scientist, or even that he was not the inventor of the atomic bomb. They know enough to correct the speaker, and all of them assume that the linguistic community contains privileged users. That is, there are people able to correct and complete the name’s reference because they have mastered its proper identification rule.

   Nevertheless, there are limits to the ability to refer using incorrect information about the possessor of a proper name. If someone uses the proper name ‘Aristotle’ in the erroneous belief that it names a prime number, if someone uses the name ‘Feynman’ thinking it is a brand of perfume, or if they use the proper name ‘Einstein’ thinking that it means a precious stone, he has a divergent understanding of those names – unqualified in the sense of being (C): failed. These are uses in which even class G (in these cases, of humans) is not recognized. Here the speaker will no longer be able to correctly insert the name into discourse in the sense that privileged namers can conclude that he is able to make the right gesture toward a fully referential use of these names. The speaker does not know what he is speaking about. He is not referring at all.

   Keeping in mind the derivative referential use of a name by a speaker without sufficient knowledge of its identification rule, we can propose a secondary, weaker, or parasitic sense of referential success. It concerns (B): unqualified references that are: (B1) insufficient or: (B2) inappropriate, but not: (C) failed. For the identification of the weakened, but the very common sense understanding of referential success belonging to class (B), the criterion is threefold:

 

    SUCCESS CRITERIA FOR UNQUALIFIED REFERENCES:

SCB-1. Convergence condition: we understand by a convergent use one where a person can at least correctly classify the referred object in the nearest relevant class G that together with the corresponding proper name makes its reference sufficiently recognizable for other speakers and, in the end, for privileged namers, who are assumed to exist (something equivalent to the knowledge of a genus proximum regarding conceptual terms).[23]

SCB-2. Condition of linguistic competence: knowledge of MIRf and of the mechanisms of reference borrowing on the speaker’s part. This enables a person to at least know that she does not know (e.g., if all I know about Aristotle is that he was Alexander’s preceptor, and I know MIRf, then I know that I am far from knowing enough about who Aristotle really was to believe I am able to properly identify him).

SCB-3. Condition of socio-contextual adequacy: there must be an adequate social context, where people who already know generalities about the proper name are already able to disambiguate it. (e.g., one can introduce the name ‘Aristotle’ referentially, linking it with the wrong description ‘a pupil of Socrates’ in a social context where he is already known to have been a Greek philosopher, but not in a context of children who only know Aristotle as the name of their school.)

 

In other words: A person is admittedly able to use a proper name in the extended senses of the word that are here classified as unqualified in an enhanced form of borrowed referential success, for which three main criteria must be satisfied. First, the uses must be convergent, falling within appropriate general classifications (satisfaction of SCB-1). This is so, simply because by inserting the name into discourse in a convergent manner, a person should already be able to employ the proper name in communication based on his expectations concerning the linguistic community. The spelling of proper names in convergent senses and adequate contexts already makes it possible for other users – assuming the ultimate support of privileged namers – to accept this insertion of the proper name into a discourse as successful, since in this way the path to a more complete reference is opened. Second, it is assumed that the person tacitly knows MIRf, the metalinguistic rule for the construction of proper names’ identification rules (satisfaction of SCB-2). Normally this makes the person aware that to use a proper name referentially in a self-sufficient way she would need to know more about it than she really knows. Third, the linguistic community where the name is inserted must be inclined to recognize contextual generalities about the name that enable its disambiguation (SCB-3): the community must know that the speaker is referring to a philosopher in the case of Aristotle, a world-famous historic building in the case of the Taj Mahal, etc. Without the satisfaction of these conditions, a proper name could not be suitably introduced into discourse in the form of an unqualified reference.

   Enhanced borrowed references are acts of referring that belong to our everyday communicative actions. The speaker performs his act of unqualified reference because he is counting on the support of a linguistic community able to recognize well-known generalities about the bearer and eventually complete his reference. It is only with the aid of better qualified speakers that it is cognitively possible to correct or complete the senses of the expressions he has in mind.

   Here it is worth remembering that although this process is social, it is obviously internal. The meaning of the proper name is internal, even though it is located especially in a speaker’s head, in other words, even though it is distributed differently in the heads of other speakers, including the very interpreters who are the privileged namers. Meaning is internal in all its moments, apart from its origins. – And here lies the original sin of externalism: the genetic fallacy of mistaking the usually external origins of meaning for the meaning itself.[24]

   Returning to our use of Putnam’s metaphor: a person is successful in referring according to the criteria of unqualified referential success, in contrast to a self-sufficient reference in a way comparable to that of a passenger who is taking a ship to go to a certain destination, even knowing that it is the crew that will sail and steer it. The case of the passenger is obviously different from that of a person who is successful in referring according to the true criteria of referential success, such as the captain of the vessel, who actually uses on-board controls to steer the ship to its destination. If we want to be demanding, we must admit that people who use a proper name without knowing its fundamental description-rules do not really know what they are saying when using the name. In fact, we only agree to say that they can insert a name into language referentially, because we rely on the existence of privileged namers who are actually able to identify its bearer. Finally, unqualified non-failed references form a spectrum ranging from knowledge of almost irrelevant descriptions (such as the overly vague ‘a philosopher,’ or the too little known ‘grandson of Achaeon’) to knowledge of important identifiers (such as ‘Plato’s greatest pupil’) or parts of fundamental descriptions (such as ‘the Greek philosopher who wrote the Metaphysics’).

   To emphasize the social dependence of unqualified references on self-sufficient references, we can imagine a situation in which, for some reason, all privileged namers disappear. Imagine that a catastrophe like a nuclear war occurs and that only a few almost illiterate people survive, reduced to a primitive state. Imagine that these survivors find a scrap of paper preserving some auxiliary descriptions concerning Aristotle, such as ‘the greatest disciple of Plato’. They would be able, I suppose, to recognize the word ‘Aristotle’ as the name of a person. However, they would not actually be able to refer to Aristotle, even in the sense of making an unqualified reference, simply because of the absence of any possible support given by a linguistic community, which must include speakers capable of filling gaps guaranteeing the reference and giving it a sense of what it originally was. Without privileged namers able to (together, at least) master the identification rule, there would be no possibility for the proper name’s effective referential use. It is as if the passengers remaining on board a ship were abandoned by its crew in mid-ocean, without having the slightest idea of how to navigate. They could never reach a port by their own efforts.

 

10. Why are proper names rigid designators?

A problem that has always haunted descriptivism is the prima facie impossibility of explaining why proper names are (obviously) rigid designators. After all, it seems clear that there is no identifying property that must satisfy some weighted definite description of a proper name’s cluster in all possible worlds. Searle tried to explain why:

 

[the name can be used as a rigid designator because] …we have a notion of the identity of an object which is separable from those particular intentional contents which are used to identify the object. (1983: 260; my italics)

 

This is the right insight but is not clearly expressed because of the lack of the right conceptual device, which is the form of the identification rules (MIRf). Now, what I want to show in this section is that another great advantage of the identification rules resulting from the application of MIRf to a proper name’s cluster is to explain in a clear and decisive way why proper names must be rigid designators even in the domain of a descriptivist theory.

   In order to give a meta-descriptive answer to the question, we need to begin by examining some semantic properties of the identification rules for proper names. One is that these rules can always be translated into the form of complex definite descriptions to be read as analytical-conceptual truths in the sense of definitions. We can make this clear by rewriting the identification rule of a proper name, which we can do simply by formulating it as a long definite description, which I call DD (definitional description, which can also be understood as an identification rule or IR expressed in a descriptive form). Here is the general form of DD:

 

DD (the formulation of MIRf as a definitional description):

The object that satisfies ((ii)) sufficiently as a whole, and ((iii)) more than any other the localizing condition ((i-a)) and/or the characterizing condition ((a-b)).

 

As you can see, the three conditions of the MIRf are contained in the DD form of definitional description. To make the function of a DD clear we can apply (or instantiate) DD to a proper name. If the proper name is ‘Aristotle’, the result is the following:

 

      DD-‘Aristotle’ =

The person who satisfies ((ii)) sufficiently as a whole and, ((iii)) more than any other, the condition ((i-a)) that he was born in Stagira in 384 BC, was the son of Philip’s court doctor, lived in Athens and died in Chalkis in 322 BC and/or the condition ((i-b)) that he was the author of the fundamental texts comprising the Aristotelian opus.

 

The essential point to be noted about a DD expressing the identification rule of a proper name is that it is a definitional description that is a tacitly accepted rigid designator. After all, it applies to the bearer of the name ‘Aristotle’ in any possible world where Aristotle can be said to exist and cannot be applied in any possible world where Aristotle cannot be said to exist. That is, we cannot conceive of a possible world where Aristotle exists and the identification rule provided by such a definitional description does not apply, since it is this same identification rule that defines who Aristotle can be for us.

   These considerations give us the most interesting clue to a new understanding of reference mechanisms that bridges the apparently insurmountable gap between Kripke’s insight and descriptivism. All we need to see is that the identification rules of proper names can be translated as rigid definitional descriptions, that is, that they are in fact, and intuitively, nothing but rigid definitional descriptions. This is important because it solves a central problem of descriptivism pointed out by Kripke, namely, the apparent impossibility of explaining how we can extract rigidity from a definitional description or a cluster of descriptions. This also means that from the ontological viewpoint we do not need any common essential property linking different possible worlds to warrant the rigidity of a proper name. It suffices to have a DD description-rule.

 

11. Blurred conceptual borders

We can now ask ourselves: could there be ambiguous cases, possible worlds where there is no way of knowing whether we can apply an identification rule? Could there be possible worlds where there is only, so to speak, “half” an Aristotle? The answer is: yes, but that does not matter at all! Vagueness is a pervasive characteristic of language and supposedly also of the world through the many ways it can be subdivided, and an adequate semantics of possible worlds also needs to cope with this fact. Certainly, there are possible worlds where Aristotle does not sufficiently exist, so that we cannot decide whether or not to apply his identification rule. In such worlds there is no way to attribute either existence or non-existence to Aristotle, and (assuming the plausible idea that vagueness arises from the very nature of things) where Aristotle neither exists nor does not exist. This does not mean that the name ‘Aristotle’ is not a rigid designator. It is rigid because outside the boundaries of indeterminacy the name can still be guaranteed to apply or not.

   There is an intuitively clear way to accommodate the concept of a rigid designator in such cases. For our purposes, it is sufficient to redefine such a concept as designating the property of a referential expression of applying in all possible worlds where the referred object definitely exists. Rigidity is, in other words, the property of the semantic-cognitive criterial rule of a referential term of “constituting” the existence of its referent in all possible worlds where this rule can reveal itself to be effectively applicable, that is, warranted and continuously applicable in a defined way without doubts about its applicability, which can occur only by means of direct or indirect verifiability procedures. For example: we can say that our Aristotle existed in our world simply because we have already applied the identification rule for the proper name Aristotle in a myriad of verifiability procedures, and therefore we know for sure that the identification rule for Aristotle (IRf-‘Aristotle’ or DD-‘Aristotle’) is effectively applicable.

   It would still be possible to object to this view by recalling the Sorites paradox. If there are frontiers of indeterminacy, where do they begin or end? If there is no clear limit to its extent, what justifies our saying that we have already reached a zone of clarity in the application of a concept, where the bearer of the name can be said to exist? The only answer we need to present here is that Sorites can be generated for virtually any vague term of our language without this fact making it practically inapplicable. Indeed, even if we are aware of Sorites, we do not fail to apply the word ‘bald’ to a totally bald head, nor the word ‘mountain’ to a mountain large enough so that it is impossible to confuse it with a hill. We do not need to solve the Sorites to apply our predicates. In a similar way, we do not need to make undecidable cases disappear to admit that the proper name ‘Aristotle’ might express a semantic core constituted by an identification rule which is a rigid designator.[25]

 

12. Rules’ changeability

We know that changes in an identification rule are clearly possible. This fact raises two questions: (a) How much can the identifying rule of a proper name change? (b) Can the change cancel the rigidity of a proper name?

   Before answering these questions, it is useful to consider a case of reference change due to the creation of a completely new rule. This is the case of the already considered example of Gareth Evan’s name ‘Madagascar’, now to be interpreted according to the metadescriptivist view. According to him, Madagascar was first identified as a region on the east coast of Africa. However, when Marco Polo visited the region, he mistakenly took Madagascar to be the great island near the east coast of Africa, which led to the formation of a completely new dominant identification rule for a new bearer of the proper name. Notice that the description ‘the region on the east coast of Africa with such and such characteristics’ elliptically shows the identification rule for the old reference of the proper name ‘Madagascar’, while the description ‘the great island with such and such properties near the east coast of Africa’ elliptically shows the identifying rule for the new reference of the same proper name. Accordingly, we have two homonymous proper names with different meanings and references. These two rules identify different objects in our world, but they are also rigid: they surely identify two different Madagascars in any possible world where their references exist.

   We can also imagine cases in which the differences are smaller but sufficient to sisawohl the candidat for a proper name’s bearer. The first is that of a conceivable world in which the person called Aristotle wrote nothing, while his smart students wrote all his works, including the Metaphysics and the Nicomachean Ethics; to make matters worse we find that he was not born in Stagira, but years later in Magna Graecia, dying in Athens. These unlikely discoveries would have to be accompanied by many other changes in history. Intuitively, we have no proper Aristotle. Corroborating our intuition, MIR-‘Aristotle’ will probably no longer apply. But it won’t make sense for us to say that MIR-‘Aristotle’ can be altered to identify this new Aristotle as being the same as our old Aristotle, who no longer exists. The flexible character of the rules for identifying proper names should not be confused with the possibility that they can be altered in a measure that intuitively would destroy their rigidity. Once its limits of flexibility are exceeded, the identified object will no longer be the same, since the identification rule will be considered the identifier of another object. We can summarize the point, adopting the maxim that:

 

the limits of alteration are the limit of rigidity.

 

Limits of applicability are blurred since the tolerance to change depends on a multiplicity of elements (remember the case of the 52nd regiment of Fot). But even this fact does not eliminate the rigidity of proper names, just as the sorites paradox does not eliminate what we see as heaps of sand. Therefore, the objection that the changeability of our rules of identification destroys rigidity is not convincing.

   The curious case of the impostor named ‘Arthur Orton’ may be of some help in clarifying the issue, showing how much can the vague limits of application of an identification rule can be stretched by the acceptance of changes. Born in England and having gone to sea at an early age, he was certainly identified through rules of localization and characterization by all who knew him. Years later, when he was in Australia, he read in a newspaper that an English woman, Lady Tichborne, was searching for her son Roger Tichborne, who had disappeared in a shipwreck in the Atlantic, and she refused to believe he had died. Back in England, despite his lack of resemblance to Roger Tichborne, Orton introduced himself as her son. Immediately “recognized” by the elderly lady, he lived in her son’s place at least until the death of Lady Tichborne three years later. After that, however, the ill-fated Orton was charged with fraud by relatives of Lady Tichborne (who never believed his claims), convicted, and sentenced to 14 years in jail. Note that the characterizing description by which we today know Orton is that of a great impostor. Orton was a person who falsely passed himself off as Lady Tichborne’s son by the very partial sharing of an identification rule with a high degree of vagueness in the localizing description and almost no characterizing description, though reinforced by the English lady’s desire to believe. That is: rules for identifying the same object that are so vague that they allow the identification of different objects in conceivable worlds, cannot be considered the same rules, and the identification rule of Arthur Orton is by far excessively different from the identification rule of Roger Tichborne, though it is no matter of certainty. Anyway, during the time of Orton’s life, mainly for ideological reasons, the point was publicly disputed. If this case shows anything, it is the difficulty of determining the limits of application of an identification rule when strong psychological and socio-ideological factors are involved.

   Now, since the identification rule is definitional regarding the bearer of a proper name’s reference, changes in the rule must be limited to the scope of what is intended to be defined. But how and to what extent? Well, we can consider three innocuous ways of change.

   The first way of change is that of changes in auxiliary description-rules belonging to a proper name’s cluster. They can be added or even subtracted without changing the applicability of the identification rule, since they do not really belong to it. To give an example: it does not really matter whether Proxenus of Artaneus was Aristotle’s guardian after the death of his father, or if Theophrastus really accompanied him to the lagoon on Lesbos Island… This is so because the auxiliary rules, while belonging to a proper name’s cluster, do not belong to the identification rule, and are consequently unable to suppress rigidity. Therefore, the possible worlds in which the identification rule applies remain the same.

   The second way of change is by increasing or decreasing the number of details concerning the fundamental localizing and/or characterizing conditions. This is very common. Regarding fundamental description-rules, the number of details relating to location and character usually increases with time, insofar as our knowledge of the bearer increases, though it can also possibly decrease if we discover mistaken attributions, for example, the discovery of water under the surface of Mars in one case, and the decision by astronomers that Pluto is not a real planet in the solar system in another. It makes no difference if a considerable increase in informational details occurs, since this normally does not change the reference or the possible worlds in which the name could apply.

   The third way of change concerns replacements within the identification rule. For example: we could discover that our Aristotle was in fact born in 392 BC and not in 384 BC. We could discover that he was not the true author of the Metaphysics and that this major work were actually written by his disciples soon after his death. Now, could small changes or not too big changes accepted as facts dissolve rigidity? Could such changes make a difference in terms of the possible worlds where Aristotle could exist? I think it is unlikely. If we consider a possible world where there were only one Aristotle, it would make no difference, since we would apply the somewhat changed identification covering both cases due to the rule’s vagueness. But consider possible worlds where there is more than one competitor for the bearer of the name ‘Aristotle’. Suppose there were a possible world – a conceivable world-circumstance – in which there were two identical bearers of the proper name ‘Aristotle’, one born in 392 BC and the other in 384 BC. In this case we would say that the distinction is too minimal to make a difference. We should better choose new proper names like ‘Aristotle-1’ and ‘Aristotle-2’ to dissolve the ambiguity and differentiate them. Now, if in a possible world we find two identical Aristotles, one who did not write the Metaphysics, and another who did write the Metaphysics, we would either reject the applicability of the identification rule, or we would say that we have made a small change in the semantic core and therefore in the reference of the proper name ‘Aristotle’. We cannot change an identification rule in a way that changes the possible conceivable world-circumstances in which a proper name already does or does not definitely apply, simply because the identification rule is what defines what should count as the bearer of the proper name in any conceivable world-circumstance (here expressions like ‘conceivable circumstance’ are better than the misleading ‘possible world’).

   A further example of change is that of a big replacement within the identification rule: suppose, for instance, we change Aristotle’s identification rule to say he was an Arab philosopher who lived in the 9th century and wrote a book in Latin called De Proprietatibus Elementorum. This person really existed in some possible world that happens to be our own. But he cannot compete with our Greek Aristotle. Here the changed rule is an identifying rule for an eponymous use of a person’s name, sharing with the original only the fact that the real author was also a man of science, one of many pseudo-Aristotles. Considering a cluster of descriptions belonging to a proper name, we have blurred boundaries between these descriptions and the fundamental descriptions, and between localizing and characterizing fundamental descriptions and, finally between the identification rules associated with the cluster and the identification rules of other identification rules associated with different clusters. Any attempt to counter the rigidity of identification rules by means of rule changeability will need to take this fact into consideration. Our answers to the questions presented at the beginning of this section are: (a) an identification rule can be changed insofar as it still identifies the same object in any possible world where this object exists; (b) if changing the identification rule cancels rigidity, it will also cancel the proper name’s function by changing its potential references in possible worlds. And the ultimate reason for these conclusions is that the identifying rule of a proper name is analytically definitional of what should count as its reference in any conceivable definite circumstance in which the reference can be said to exist (any possible world).[26] To think otherwise is to be deceived by what Wittgenstein once called the surface grammar (Oberflächiche Grammatik) of our language (1984: sec 664); the confusion is supported by an artificial term like ‘possible world’.

   Another way to state the same result arises when we consider the internal vagueness in the identification rule. Consider again the condition (iii) of the MDRf, that is, the predominance condition. It was stated as follows:

 

Predominance condition: the condition that in the case where more than one object sufficiently satisfies the disjunctive condition of a proper name, the bearer of the proper name must be the object that most completely satisfies it.

 

The point here is one of vagueness: the blurred borders between what counts as predominant or not. In the example of the Arab medieval philosopher who wrote De Proprietatibus Elementorum it is clear that in our world he is not the Aristotle of our identification rule, since he does not satisfy the predominance condition. But in the case of a conceivable world-circumstance in which we need to choose between an Aristotle who was born in 292 BC, and one born in 284 BC, or one who had and another who had not written the Metaphysics, ceteris paribus, there would be at least in the first case a practical ground for doubt. In any case, it seems to me that we are here reaching the limits of language, or, in better  words, the limits of our criterial linguistic tools to deal with proper names in our natural language.

 

13. Existence

A related point regards the attribution of existence to objects of reference in statements like “Aristotle exists”. I will consider here only a natural association between identification rules and the second-order view of existence traditionally defended by philosophers like Aquinas, Kant, Frege, and Russell.[27] According to this view, existence is not a property of things, but a property of concepts, which we could generally render as the property of being satisfied by at least one object.[28] Formally speaking, if we call the attribution of existence, and we call A the expression of the concept involved in the predicate ‘Aristotle’, we can say “Aristotle exists” or, which is the same, “There is only one x such that x is Aristotle”. Formally we can express this as “x [(Ax) & (y) (Ay → y = x)]”. Here we can clearly see that A applies to x, while applies to A, more precisely, we see that the concept expressed by A applies to something at the level of reference, while the concept of existence expressed by applies to the concept expressed by A and not to x. Now, if we accept that a concept is a criterial rule (a sense), we can replace A with the identification rule for Aristotle, and with the satisfaction of this rule, which is to us nothing but the property of applicability or effective applicability of the criterial rule. This means, namely, the effective (warranted, verifiable) applicability of the identification rule for the name ‘Aristotle’. Or, in other words, I am suggesting that the higher-order property of existence can be paraphrased as the meta-property of the effective (warranted, verifiable) applicability of conceptual rules in the considered domains.[29] I will try to make this clear by offering an example: suppose someone utters the indexical sentence: “The object on this table is a pencil”. Let us say that the ascription rule for the concept of pencil is: “a hard tube containing a sufficiently solid rod which can be used for writing or drawing”. If we claim that the pencil exists, we are saying that this rule is effectively, that is warrantably or verifiably applicable to the object on the table, even when we are not near that object, and even when we are not applying the rule. Moreover, the rule is effectively applicable, since it is warrantably, verifiably applicable, even in cases where we do not yet know of its effective applicability in the domain of the world around us (e.g., we do not know that the pencil exists). In a similar way, the existence of a proper name’s bearer, such as Aristotle, must be able to be identified by the effective applicability of the conceptual rule that we normally associate with the word ‘Aristotle’. Here, this is the identification rule (expressed by IR-‘Aristotle’ or the DD definite description) for this proper name. Thus, it is the effective applicability (the attribution of existence) of the identification rule, which establishes a referent as the bearer of the name in any possible world. With the above explanation, I am offering a more detailed analysis of the higher-order concept of existence that is somewhat equivocally analyzed by Frege as the second-order property of concepts of having at least one object falling under it (Frege 1961: 65). According to my analysis, the existence of the property designated by the ascription rule of a predicative expression is the higher-order t-property of this rule of being effectively or warrantably applicable, since the conceptual rule itself can be regarded as a first-order t-property in a world made up of tropes. Consider, as a further example, the statement Aristotle is white. This sentence can be formalized as x [Ax & (y) (Ay → y = x) & Wx], where ‘’ expresses the second-order predicate of existence, while the first-order predicates are expressed by ‘A’ = Aristotle and ‘W” = white. Now, according to our neo-Fregean understanding, A and W apply to x, while applies to the conceptual rules expressed by A and W. Considering the concepts expressed by A and W as first-order tropical rules, A is an identification rule effectively applied to (or satisfied by) a composition of concurrent t-properties (which is the same as the person of Aristotle), and W is an attribution rule applicable to (or satisfied by) a t-property (which is the Aristotelian whiteness). Furthermore, the second-order conceptual rule expressed by and meaning effective applicability applies to the rules expressed by A and W. It attributes to these first-order rules a second-order property of existence, which is nothing but the property of these first-order rules of being effectively applicable in a proper domain.

   Initially, the proposed view may seem puzzling, if we think of existence as a meta-property of effective applicability floating above the object supposedly constituted by its tropical properties. But we can easily get around the objection insofar as we paraphrase the above explanation more naturally as saying that the existence of an object is the meta-property of its identification rule of being effectively (warrantably, verifiably, continuously) applicable to it, while an object that does not possess this meta-property is not a real object, but merely a conceivable one. This way of speaking protects us from any accusations of anthropomorphism regarding existence: an object can have an identification rule effectively applicable to itself – thus not being a merely conceivable object – even if this rule has never been thought of or applied by any cognitive agent. Consequently, if we know that the identification rule for the name ‘Aristotle’ is effectively applicable in a possible world – that is, we have verified its applicability in a possible world that is our own – we know that Aristotle exists. In other words, the effective applicability of the identification rule is in some way “constitutive” of its object.

 

14. Why are definite descriptions accidental designators?

In this section, I present what I regard as an irrefutable demonstration of the greater explanatory power of the here presented theory of proper names’ referential function.

   We have already seen in Chapter II that a significant advantage of the causal-historical view is that it provides an explanation for the fact that definite descriptions are accidental designators, while proper names are rigid designators. In conformity with that view, it seems that proper names identify their bearers in any possible world where these bearers exist, by being connected more directly, even if mysteriously, with their references by means of baptism. Definite descriptions, on the other hand, can identify different objects in different possible worlds. They do so, it appears, by connecting with their references indirectly through what they mean (or, according to J. S. Mill, what they connotatively express). This Kripkian explanation remains to some extent unsatisfactory, as it must unavoidably resort to some mysterious “direct connection to the object”. This is supposedly acquired by proper names through the ceremony of baptism, even if often accomplished with the help of accidental descriptions.[30] In contrast, it is a great advantage of the meta-descriptive theory of proper names that it allows us to explain the difference in usage between definite descriptions and proper names simply by showing that what makes such descriptions accidental is their associations with proper names. To arrive at this explanation, however, we will need a detailed argument. We can start by asking: in what cases do definite descriptions become rigid designators? I do not wish to speak about the stipulation of rigidified descriptions referring to an object in the actual world, such as, e.g., ‘the actual last great philosopher of antiquity’, referring to the actual Aristotle even in worlds where he was not a philosopher (Cf. Searle 1983; Stanley 1997). What I want to consider is the case of perfectly normal assignable definite descriptions which are naturally interpreted as rigid designators simply because they are not associated with any proper name. They are not so rare. Here are some examples:

 

                              (A)

(i)               the square root of nine,

(ii)              the easternmost point in South America,

(iii)            the Rafflesia discovered by Dr. Joseph Arnold on 20 May 1818.

(iv)            the Third Cavalry Corps of the Grande Armée.[31]

(v)              the Last Glacial Period,

(vi)            the assassination of Austrian Archduke Ferdinand in Sarajevo in 1914.

 

By definite description (i) we mean not only the number 3, but also a method of reasoning or calculation which leads to this number. This description can be considered an obstinate designator, since its formal character makes it abstractly applicable in any possible world.[32]

  What really interests us here is not case (i), but that of descriptions from (ii) to (vi), whose content is empirical. Whether or not we regard them as rigid designators does not usually depend on how we interpret them. Consider case (ii). It is true that in our world the easternmost point of South America is located in the Northeast of Brazil near the city of João Pessoa, or so I’ve learnt as I was there. This geographical fact, however, can surely be considered irrelevant. For suppose that in another possible world Patagonia bends towards Africa, making it farther east than João Pessoa. In this case, description (ii) would apply to the same easternmost point, which would be located in Patagonia. It remains a rigid designator notwithstanding the difference in latitude and longitude and any other geographical specification, since these are not to be considered in cases where a point can change its spatial position. Worth noticing is that this reading of (ii) as a rigid designator is not a new and artificial stipulation but can be seen as a natural interpretation of the description’s content (ask yourself about the relocation of a Euclidian geometrical point).

   What I am trying to show becomes more plausible when we consider other cases of rigid descriptions that are obviously not associated with proper names. Consider (iii): The Rafflesia Arnoldi is regarded as the largest flower in the world. The first known specimen was discovered by Sir Stamford Raffles and Dr. Joseph Arnold on 19 May 1818 during an expedition to the Manna River in Sumatra. The description (iii) is rigid since it is true in any possible world where Dr. Arnold discovered that Rafflesia specimen on 19 May 1818 during an expedition to the Mana River in Sumatra. Hence, (iii) is a rigid designator. Indeed, if we try to treat it as an accidental designator, the question will arise: accidental with respect to what?

   Consider now (iv): if we have in mind only Napoleon’s Third Cavalry Corps of the Grande Armée, leaving aside the particular soldiers and horses that constituted it, its description is clearly seen as a rigid designator, applying to the same regiment in any possible world where that regiment can be said to exist. We should note that in this definite description the localizing description-rule (France, 1804-1815) and the characterizing description-rule (the third cavalry corps of Napoleon’s Grande Armée) are already clearly expressed.

   Now, consider descriptions (v) and (vi). They should also be interpreted as rigid designators. Description (v) can be understood as designating a state of affairs characterized by the Earth’s last cooling period. In our world, it lasted from 111,000 years ago until about 11,700 years ago, but in a counterfactual situation it could have occurred in a very different period, insofar as it could still be identified as the last glacial period. Description (v) is a rigid designator of a past state of affairs that we have located on our planet. Description (vi), finally, refers to an event explicitly containing its characterization as the assassination of Archduke Franz Ferdinand. In our world, he was tragically gunned down by Gavrilo Princip, but in another near possible world, he could have been stabbed, poisoned, strangled, etc. His death might not have ignited World War I in some possible worlds… But it is important to see that the description would not fail to satisfy the description of the assassination as a rigid definite description, applicable in all possible worlds where Archduke Ferdinand was assassinated.

   Now, if we apply rigidity tests to the above examples, we see that they also pass the test, since the corresponding statements are, as the test demands, false (see Chapter II, sec. 1). Thus, applying the test to A-(iii) we get “Something other than the Rafflesia discovered by Dr. Joseph Arnold on 20 May 1818 might have been the Rafflesia discovered by Dr. Joseph Arnold on 20 May 1818”, which is clearly false. Applying it to A-(vi) we get: “The assassination of Austrian Archduke Ferdinand in Sarajevo in 1914 might have been something other than what was in fact the assassination of Austrian Archduke Ferdinand in Sarajevo in 1914”. Surely not. The same results are reached by applying Hugues’ version of the rigidity test. Thus, applying it to A-(v) we get: “The last glacial period could have existed without being the last glacial period”. In any possible world, such statements would involve a logical contradiction, being therefore false, which demonstrates rigidity.

   We see now that there are definite descriptions naturally interpretable as rigid designators referring to (i) numbers, (ii) points, (iii) objects, (iv) groups, (v) states of affairs, (vi) processes, and even (vii) events. It is clear that these things are or can be considered as rigid designators. Are there features common to all these cases? The interesting point is that the answer is in the affirmative. There are two common features. The first feature is crucial and decisive for our whole argument: it is that there are no proper names corresponding to any of these descriptions.[33] That is why I call them autonomous descriptions. Below I show why this is a decisive feature: by nature, autonomous descriptions must be rigid. A second feature is a consequence of the first: these descriptions express fundamental rules of localization and/or characterization, and not auxiliary rules, as often found in the case of metaphorical or accidental descriptions used in association with proper names. This point is less important, because we may well invent a linguistically metaphorical or accidental description in place of the cases above, and it may also be rigidly interpreted as tacitly containing fundamental description-rules.

   As a contrast, let us now consider some examples of usual definite descriptions which clearly behave as accidental designators that can refer to different objects in different possible worlds. Here are some examples:

 

                 (B)

(i)               the Eagle of The Hague,

(ii)              the iron marshal,

(iii)            the founder of the Lyceum,

(iv)            the first Roman emperor,

(v)              the city of light.

(vi)            The third planet of the solar system.

 

In opposition to the examples given in list (A), the above definite descriptions are designators so typically accidental that a Kripkian philosopher would be pleased to use them as examples. Contrary to the previous descriptions, one cannot make them rigid, except by means of stipulation. Consider (i): it is usual to think of the description ‘the Eagle of The Hague’ as a laudatory metaphor for Rui Barbosa’s oratorical powers in his address to The Hague Peace Conference in 1907. But we can also conceive a possible world where the ship Rui Barbosa took to the congress at The Hague had sunk already at the beginning of its voyage, taking with it that outstanding orator, and that he was replaced by another excellent speaker, who was called by his devoted compatriots ‘the Eagle of The Hague’. The same goes for any other description in group B.

   The descriptions of group B do not pass the Kripkian tests of rigidity. Consider, for instance, the statement B-(v). Applying the test to (v), we get “The City of Light could have existed without having been the City of Light” (Hughes’ incremental test). This is a true statement, failing to pass the rigidity test that requires its falsity. For it is obvious that Paris, the City of Light, could have existed as a city without ever being called the City of Light!

   The next question is: what makes group B descriptions accidental, in contrast to the rigid descriptions of group A? The answer would not be that the descriptions of group B are only auxiliary, even if most of them are, because we could add to this list descriptions such as (vii) ‘the most famous soccer player in history’ and (viii) ‘the 45th president of the United States’. These are fundamental and yet accidental, since in some possible worlds Pelé might not have become the most famous soccer player, and someone other than Donald Trump could have become the 45th president of the United States. The real answer to the question is more profound. It is that the descriptions of group B, unlike those belonging to group A, are semantically associated, albeit loosely, with corresponding proper names, insofar as they belong to their clusters. These proper names are respectively (i) Rui Barbosa, (ii) Floriano Peixoto, (iii) Aristotle, (iv) Julius Caesar, (v) Paris, and (vi) Earth. Despite the strength of the association, established by the place of group B definite descriptions in the clusters and, in this way, also the conditions constituted by the identification rules of the corresponding proper names, these descriptions do not need to be satisfied by the same objects referred to by the corresponding proper names in all possible worlds where those objects exist. After all, it is certain that there are possible worlds where Rui Barbosa stopped undertaking diplomatic missions, where Floriano Peixoto was a candid adept of the monarchy, where Aristotle did not found a Lyceum, where Julius Caesar tenaciously defended the Republic, where Paris was destroyed in the fourteenth century, never becoming the City of Light, and (let us imagine) where a planet Vulcan really existed, Venus was the third planet from the Sun, and the Earth was consequently the fourth planet from the Sun. However, these proper names do not cease to apply to their respective objects in all these conceivable world-circumstances, since they are rigid designators, continuing to satisfy the respective identification rules that we have derived from MIRf.

   A consideration of this point would surely lead us to reject a Millian-Kripkian explanation of definite descriptions, according to which they would be accidental because they denote accidentally or flaccidly. According to Mill they denote indirectly, based on connotative properties, and not directly-rigidly, as is the case with proper names. Thus we see that a definite description is not, if taken alone, accidental, and it is called accidental with respect to the association we make between the definite description and some proper name. More precisely, it becomes accidental by being loose, contingent, and not necessarily associated with the proper name to whose cluster it belongs. This is a conclusion that is valid not only for auxiliary descriptions, but even for fundamental descriptions belonging to proper names, since the identification rule allows the possibility of dissociation between the application of a proper name and any isolated application of both kinds of description.

   We can further clarify this idea by saying that virtually any description belonging to the cluster of descriptions represented by a proper name has a contingent semantic association with the rest of the description-rules constituting the name’s informative content. This association is made because we consider such a definite description to be connected with, and often a contributor to, the identifying description-rule. The latter is considered whenever a proper name is applied in the fully referential act characteristic of a self-sufficient reference. That is, contrary to DD and the many combinations of descriptions belonging to its possible factual applications, descriptions of the cluster are accidental in the sense that they are not an indispensable aspect of a proper name’s self-sufficient reference. This being so, a definite description belonging to a cluster and the proper name with which it is associated only tend to refer to the same object, not necessarily doing so (e.g., the founder of the Lyceum, as well as the philosopher who died in Chalkis in 322 BC, tend to refer to the same object as does the name Aristotle).

   Of course, the sameness of the referent is something we assume to be the case; but we can easily imagine counterfactual situations where it does not exist. This is why the auxiliary description ‘Herphyllis’s lover’ applies to the reference of the name ‘Aristotle’, as far as we know, but it is not impossible to imagine, for instance, that the surviving texts constituting Aristotle’s heritage were incorrectly transcribed... In our world, the characterizing description of Aristotle is ‘the author of the Aristotelian opus’. But in another possible world, Aristotle could have died before reaching Athens and consequently never wrote the Aristotelian opus. This description – for speakers in that world – will lack the semantic association it has here with the semantic content of the proper name ‘Aristotle,’ even if it is a fundamental (but not indispensable) portion of our identification rule for that name. In other words:

 

Because of a possible disconnection between the reference of the proper name and the reference of definite descriptions that are in different degrees loosely associated with it, these descriptions become capable of designating another or perhaps none of the expected references in other possible worlds where the proper name associated with them continues to apply or even ceases to apply to the same reference. It is only for this trivial comparative reason that proper names are called rigid designators, and the associated definite descriptions not. Only the description DD, expressing the proper name’s identification rule, remains a rigid designator.

           

An example can be useful here. A description such as ‘the first Roman emperor’ expresses part of the description-rule defining the character of Julius Caesar (he was de facto the first Roman emperor). As the DD (or the MIRf-‘Julius Caesar’) for the identification of Julius Caesar is more complete, allowing us to identify the object much more specifically, we consider the description ‘the first Roman emperor’ to express a contingent, albeit important, property of Julius Caesar. It is contingent because according to its identification rule, expressed by DD, Caesar can be identified as such even if that description-rule could not be applied. That is the only reason why the description ‘the first Roman emperor’ is accidental, namely, because there could be counterfactual circumstances where he did not become the first Roman emperor. Thus, for instance, there could be conceivable world-circumstances where Pompey won the Battle of Pharsalus against Caesar and became the first Roman emperor, or even did not become one… or a possible world where Julius Caesar was a vigorous defender of the Republic and where this institution persisted until the end of the Empire.

   Of course, we could also stipulate that the proper name ‘Julius Caesar’ abbreviates the definite description ‘the first Roman emperor’. In this case, the description becomes a rigid designator, for it will designate the first Roman emperor in any possible world where he comes into existence. Such an artificial strategy can be applied to any other description associated with a proper name, if there is a reason for doing this. However, in the case of descriptions belonging to group A above, rigidity is a natural feature. Consider A-(iii): ‘the Third Cavalry Corps of the Grande Armée’. Because of the tacit conventions established by our specialized practice, this localizing and characterizing description will always apply to the same object in any possible world where that regiment can be found. The given explanation shows why this is the case. Since the descriptions of the A group are unassociated with the semantic content of any proper name to be related to them, they cannot refer to objects other than those referred to by them in any possible worlds where their objects of reference exist, which makes them rigid designators. We see, therefore, that quite unlike the implications of Kripke’s arguments, the relationship between a description/accidental designator and a proper name/rigid designator has nothing to do with a difference between the indirect (connotative in Mill’s sense) reference mechanism of the definite description and a mysterious direct-rigid reference mechanism of proper names resulting from some form of baptism. But this holds only for the relationship between a definite description and the proper name with which it is loosely associated.

   One point to be added is that in cases where a definite description is auxiliary regarding a proper name, the rule of connection to the referent is not qualified to identify it as the object referred to by the proper name associated with it. A definite description such as ‘the Eagle of The Hague,’ for example, is not capable, by its explicit content, of identifying Rui Barbosa independently of the identification rule usually associated with this proper name, because this honorific description does not have enough descriptive content to do so. Moreover, the speaker who applies the description ‘the Eagle of The Hague’ usually also has in mind at least part of the localizing and the characterizing description-rules for Rui Barbosa when using it, though not necessarily associating these rules with the definite description (suppose he was mistaken about the association, as often occurs). Moreover, in differently conceivable world-circumstances, an auxiliary description such as ‘the Eagle of The Hague’ can more easily become contingent; it can easily be associated with another proper name, say, Joaquim Nabuco, belonging then to the semantic halo of this last name.

   Now we also clearly know why the descriptions of group (B) do not resist the rigidity test. It is because we are able to unwittingly associate one of their occurrences with the proper name and not the others within the rigidity test’s statement. Applying the test to B-(i) we get “Something other than the Eagle of The Hague [Rui Barbosa] might have been the Eagle of The Hague [e.g., Joaquim Nabuco].” (In fact, the distinction was first suggested by the Baron of Rio Branco for Joaquim Nabuco.); applying the test to B-(iii) we get “The founder of the Lyceum [?] might have been other than the founder of the Lyceum [Aristotle]”. These two statements are also true, since the first occurrences of the descriptions in them can be detached from the proper names with which they are weakly associated. And B-(vi) “The second planet of the solar system [?] could have existed without having been the second planet of the solar system [Venus]” is also true, for instance, if the second planet were replaced by a rogue planet in the 3rd century AD without any visual confirmation. It is the weak association that we make with the proper name and the possibility of disassociation that leads us to regard these statements as non-contradictory and consequently true, failing to pass the rigidity test.

   Finally, we can add a very clarifying explanation of the loose semantic association between description and name by using the Wittgensteinian distinction between primary criteria and symptoms or secondary criteria already explained in the present book (Chapter I, section 4). Repeating what we saw there, criteria are regarded by Wittgenstein as defining properties (1958: 24; 2001: 28)[34]. Once identified as given, they constitute conditions that for us guarantee the applicability of a conceptual term. Symptoms or secondary criteria, in contrast, are properties that once accepted as given make the applicability of the conceptual term only more or less probable. For instance: plasmodium falciparum in a patient’s blood can serve as a criterion of malaria, while intermittent fever is only a symptom.[35] A criterial rule necessitates (for us) the satisfaction of criteria for its application, for which reason the term ‘criterion’ is ambiguous: it means both what the criterial rule requires for its application and what satisfies this requirement – an ambiguity that extends to symptoms or secondary criteria.

   Now, the identification rule of a proper name is its proper criterial rule. We see that the changing t-properties or t-property bundles required for the effective applicability of the identification rule of a proper name are valid as criteria guaranteeing the name’s applicability. The tropical properties required by definite description-rules belonging to the bundle of descriptions associated with a proper name are only probabilizing symptoms for the application of the name, since they only make that application probable. These considerations allow us to predict that the dependency a definite description has on the semantic context of the corresponding proper name should diminish in proportion to its irrelevance for the identification of the object. This makes most descriptions in the bundle weaker but helpful symptoms, probabilizing the application of the identification rule. It is easier to consider separately accidental and generally unknown definite descriptions like ‘Alexander’s tutor’ or ‘Achaeon’s grandson’ or ‘Herphyllis’s lover’ as symptoms of the referent of the name ‘Aristotle’, since they play a secondary role in determining the reference of the name ‘Aristotle’. But it will be less easy, although still possible, to do the same in the case of fundamental descriptions such as ‘the author of the Metaphysics’ and ‘the Greek philosopher born in Stagira in 384 BC’. And if the definite description contains in the right way all that is essential for the content of the proper name to which it is subordinate, it will inevitably become rigid. This is only the case with DD-rules. Thus, the DD-‘Aristotle’ is the descriptive formulation of the identification rule for the name ‘Aristotle’, which, as we have seen, is a rigid designator: the primary criterion.

   If an accidental designator is derived from the contrast of a description with the associated proper name, we can ask ourselves if it could also occur as a contrast between one proper name and another. This should be the case for two proper names of the same object, when one of them contingently includes in its cluster all the descriptions belonging to the other. Indeed, this happens, especially in the case of nicknames. Consider the case of a young schoolboy, call him Bud, who because he has trouble figuring things out, was for some time nicknamed by mean-spirited schoolmates ‘Anvil-head’, or for short, ‘the Anvil.’ There are possible worlds where Bud was not an inept pupil or had no malevolent schoolmates, or where his friend John was the actual recipient of that nickname. In these worlds, the nickname ‘Anvil’ either does not apply or identifies someone other than Bud. The nickname ‘Anvil-head’ is – if considered in contrast to most common proper names – an accidental designator, an accidental proper name, which is only a symptom of the person who bears Bud’s name.

   The above explanation for the difference between the semantic behavior of proper names and that of definite descriptions is much more clarifying than the obscure causal-referentialist theory. The latter suggests that through an act of baptism a proper name comes to refer by possessing some secret and inscrutable intimacy with its object. The former explanation is more powerful, since it justifies exceptional cases. According to it, the rigidity of the proper name ceases to be suggested as something arising from a mysterious property of the baptized object in abstraction from its cognition and without the resource of properties. Instead, rigidity arises from the identification rule as its t-property of being applicable in any conceivable world-circumstance where criterial configurations generated by it are satisfied by criterial t-properties belonging to the bundle of compresent t-properties constitutive of the referred object.[36]

   This is the way the concept of rigid designator loses its mysterious aura. It is deflated, since in the end any singular term (and, in fact, any general term) is a rigid designator, namely, a term applicable in any conceivable world-circumstance (possible world) where it can be applied effectively to an object (in which its object of reference exists not only as something conceived but also as objectively given). A definite description only refers, either because it is detached from the proper name and consequently seen as rigid, or because it is regarded as belonging to the cluster of descriptions of a proper name in the application of the identification rule of that name.

 

16. Autonomous definite descriptions

Finally, there is the question of how to analyze autonomous definite descriptions. The most plausible hypothesis is that, to work independently of proper names, these descriptions need to have their own identification rules constructed upon fundamental conditions, which are their localizing and characterizing description-rules. In fact, the same MDRf we apply to the clusters of descriptions of a proper name should be applied to an autonomous definite description, insofar as, being a singular term working independently of any proper name, it needs to be a rigid designator and, in this way, able to identify an individual. The difference regarding proper names is not just that in the case of autonomous definite descriptions the rule is in some way made explicit through symbolic forms as their connotations or meanings. The difference is that the identification rule is usually less complex.

   Consider first the definite description ‘the Last Glacial Period.’ Because it is autonomous, the fundamental descriptions belonging to the identification rule contain a localizing and a characterizing description. The first one is the following:

 

Localizing description-rule: the last glacial period occurred on the planet Earth[37] and lasted so long that there has been no other ice age from its end until the present day.

 

Although it occurred during the Pleistocene period, from approximately 115,000 to ~11,700 years before our time, and although it was preceded by several other similar glacial periods, it could have occurred in some other longer or shorter period, ending before or after. But there is also a rule of characterization for the last glacial period, even if it is redundant. Here is how we can summarize it:

 

Characterizing description-rule: a long period of decrease in the temperature of the Earth’s surface and atmosphere, resulting in the expansion of continental and polar ice sheets, as well as glaciers and alpine snowfields.

 

Because the autonomous description ‘the last glacial period’ functions as a proper name, its application requires enough of the complexity needed by an identification rule, which is not needed by auxiliary descriptions used in place of names, as is the case with ‘the City of Light’ parasitically used (Someone can know nothing more of the City of Light than that it must be a beautiful city, taking the description literally).

   Now we can present a complete example of an identification rule of an autonomous definite description. Consider the description: ‘the 52nd Regiment of Foot’. It has the following (summarized) localizing description-rule:

 

The 52nd Regiment of Foot existed from 1757 to 1881 and was stationed in Oxfordshire; it saw active duty particularly during the American War of Independence, the Anglo-Mysore wars in India, and the Napoleonic Wars.

 

 The characterizing description-rule for the 52nd Regiment of Foot can be summarized as follows:

 

The 52nd Regiment of Foot was a highly regarded regiment whose troops were recruited chiefly from Oxfordshire, consisting of one or two battalions of light infantry, each comprising approximately 1,000 men.

 

The whole identification rule of this autonomous definite description will be the following:

 

RIF-‘the 52nd regiment of foot’:

The autonomous definite description ‘the 52nd regiment of foot’ refers properly to an object x belonging to the class of military units,

iff

(i-a) x satisfies the localizing description-rule of having existed from 1757 to 1881, and ws stationed in Oxfordshire; it saw active duty particularly during the American War of Independence, the Anglo-Mysore wars in India and the Napoleonic Wars,

 and/or

(i-b) x satisfies the characterizing description-rule of having been a highly regarded regiment whose troops were recruited chiefly from Oxfordshire, consisting of one or two battalions of light infantry, each comprising approximately 1,000 men,

(ii) x satisfies the disjunction (i-a) and/or (i-b) to a degree that is overall sufficient, and

      (iii) x satisfies the disjunction (i-a) and/or (i-b) better than any other military unit.

 

It also seems clear that in other possible worlds the 52nd regiment of foot could consist of troops not recruited in Oxfordshire, but, say, in Cambridgeshire (still in England), and existing from 1726 to 1832… nevertheless satisfying sufficiently and more than any other regiment important characteristics such as serving during the American War of Independence and Anglo-Mysore wars, and made up of one or two battalions of light infantry comprising approximately 1,000 men... This would be sufficient for the identification of the 52nd regiment of foot in that near possible world, even if it were regrettably non-Oxfordian.

   But then, what is the difference between the identification rule of autonomous descriptions and that of proper names? Regarding fundamental descriptions, the difference often lies in the complexity of the rule. But the main difference concerns the auxiliary definite descriptions, which are so helpful to the work of inserting a proper name into discourse. It is not that they cannot exist. The 52nd regiment of foot was associated with the following auxiliary laudatory definite description: ‘a regiment never surpassed in arms since arms were first borne by men’. The use of this auxiliary description can be sufficient to insert the description convergently into discourse. The same surely applies to many other autonomous definite descriptions.

   The contrast is here with definite descriptions strongly associated with proper names like the auxiliary descriptions ‘the City of Light’ with Paris, or ‘the tutor of Alexander’ with Aristotle. We can also contrast them with definite descriptions that express the fundamental description-rules, like ‘the Stagirite’ or ‘the author of the Nicomachian Ethics, the Metaphysics, and the Organon’. In these cases, the descriptions are viewed as appended to the identification rules of the respective proper names, which emphasizes the descriptions’ explicit meanings and eschews their possible autonomy. As such, auxiliary descriptions are seen only as helpful though unnecessary complements to the identification rules of their associated proper names. Finally, we can always artificially abstract definite descriptions from the proper names they are associated with, analyzing them as autonomous. One could speculate as to whether or not this was what philosophers were trying to achieve when they proposed we could rigidify descriptions by indexing them to the actual world.

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 



[1] See Bencivenga 1987.

[2] I use the term cognitive to include tacit non-conscious cognitions. One does not need to be able to explain the descriptions one has in mind by applying a proper name.

[3] The term ‘causal descriptivism’ was coined by David Lewis in his 1984 article to designate mixed theories of proper names. See also Kroon 1987. 

[4] Russell 2010: 460.

[5] His words also serve as a warning against some formalist overconfidences: “Our common stock of words embodies all the distinctions men have found worth drawing, and the connections they have found worth marking, in the lifetime of many generations: these surely are likely to be more numerous, more sound, since they have stood up to the long test of the survival of the fittest… we are looking again, not merely at words, but also at realities we use the words to talk about: we are using a sharpened awareness of words to sharpen our perception of reality… Certainly then, ordinary language is not the last word: in principle, it can be everywhere supplemented and improved upon and superseded. Only remember, it is the first word” (1979: 182-185; for objections to the limits of this method, see Grice 1989, part I.)

[6] The fact that spatiotemporal localizing rules have a privileged role has not gone completely unnoticed. Paul Ziff, for example, argued that localizing descriptions or localizing implications form a central part of the proper name’s reference mechanism (1960). (Cf. also Tugendhat 1976: Ch. 21-25)

[7] I chose Wikipedia because of its ease of access; but any other encyclopedia will highlight these kinds of data, often in a similar order.

[8] It is important to see how much different is “the bearer of the name ‘N’”, as we understand it here, from the non-homonimist sense that proper names receive in most of the so-called metalinguistic theories of proper names, in which proper names are usually treated as referential context-sensitive terms (see Gray: 2018). For instance, the name ‘John Smith’ will have as referents as many bearers as there are individuals with this name in the world, varying its identification with the context. Notwithstanding the fact that the word, the ‘proper name’, can also gain that sense, the sense I am investigating in this book is that of an individual constant, having as its referent an individual. This is also what we usually mean with the term proper name.

[9] The main reason why the philosophy of language is distinguished from linguistics is not as much the breadth of its scope, which goes beyond a particular language, but the presence of epistemological and ontological imports. It is in this sense that Frege’s semantics, as much as the present discussion, are philosophical, unlike, for example, Saussure’s linguistics (2016).

[10] I suppose here that the person knows nothing about who Achaeon was and about when and where he lived, for this already implies that he associates the name with descriptions such as a Macedonian philosopher from the 3rd century BC.

[11] God could also be understood to have no location, because he is said to be simultaneously everywhere. But this is a problematic case, because either His existence is unverifiable, or His nature distorted. On the other hand, there is another concept well expressed by Baudelaire as he wrote, “Dieu est le seul être qui, pour régner, n’ait même pas besoin d'exister.” [God is the only being that to reign does not even need to exist.] (1867, 75-76).

[12] The tacit assumptions of the existence of auxiliary descriptions and a supposed ultimate causal relation – not properly belonging to the rule by means of which the referent is identified – will by reasons of economy not be repeated.

[13] It could also be called ‘Theseus’ ship’ since a definite description without an associated proper name (which I will call autonomous) should express an identification rule like that of Calibdus.

[14] This is the version originally proposed in Plutarch’s Theseus.

[15] It should be noted that the Kripkian theory of baptism would also find it difficult to explain our preference for the second Aristotle in W2. This theory would not be able to distinguish the true Aristotle, for it would not have at its disposal enough descriptive resources to privilege it; it couldn’t explain why the real Aristotle happens to be the first one in W3.

[16]  The cognitive, epistemic, or informative meaning (Sinn or Erkenntniswert) of a word is much more than the literal meaning, and according to the adopted ontology, it should be taken as constituted by internal tropes (like psychological criterial conditions) able to be equally repeated in the same or in different minds.

[17] It should be noted that there are specialized dictionaries or lexicons for proper names, such as those that explain the etymological meanings of peoples’ proper names and even provide generic information about their best-known bearers. An etymological meaning, however, is precisely what we are not searching for, since it might belong to a proper name’s sensible mark, independently of what it can refer to regarding each circumstantially different bearer.

[18] It is not always so transient, as is attested to by the well-known scathing remark of a London critic about James Joyce and his almost illiterate wife: “I was introduced to a sick old man accompanied by a cow.” (O’Brien, 2011)

[19] For an impressive example of a biography being fully scrutinized in a court trial, see the documentary The Staircase, about a writer named Michael Peterson, who apparently tried for murdering his wife in 2001.

[20] According to Smith, this appeal to a division of linguistic labor can be found in writings of philosophers like John Locke and C. S. Peirce. A closer look shows that Locke was emphasizing the frequent inadequacies in our ability to reflect on the different aspects of our ideas using words. He thought that ideas corresponding to words can be inadequate and faulty in different minds, distant from the patterns or archetypes they should refer to (II, 31, 4-5). For him, ideas that are collections of simpler ideas can be attached to names in ways that are distant from those who use the names in their most proper signification (II.32.12), and confused complex ideas are bound to render the use of words uncertain (II.29.7). Thus, many do not use such words in their precise sense, which often defeats real communication (III.10.22). Children often learn imperfect notions of our complex ideas, and as adults sometimes remain ignorant of aspects, so that, although they master our grammar, they may still use certain words improperly… (III.11.24).

[21] See Appendix of the present book, sec. 7

 

[22] This also occurs frequently when we hear scientific expressions like ‘quantum entanglement’ or ‘string theory’. The little that most of us know of physics allows us at least to share a similar locus in our cognitive networks.

[23] I am detailing something that John Searle already noticed this point as he considered the transference of relevant information from speaker to hearer in order to secure reference: “…the type of thing named by the name – whether it is a mountain or a man or a mouse or whatever – is generally associated with the name even in the parasitic cases; and if the speaker is wildly mistaken about this we are disinclined to say that he has really succeeded in referring”. (1983: 249)

[24] Cf. Appendix, sec. 6 to 9 for criticism of Putnam’s externalism and an examination and analysis of the meanings of general terms’.

[25] Notice that a similar problem could be found with causal-historical views: there could be a half-Aristotle unjustifiably baptized or labeled, etc.

[26] The existence of a pervasive, unproblematic, and inevitable vagueness in natural language was insistently pointed out by the later Wittgenstein (1984b: sec. 72-108). Although the admission of vagueness in a proper name’s reference mechanisms seems to offend some logical instincts, it is unavoidable. In a similar case, inescapable vagueness can be found in scientific fields, for instance, in the statistical mechanics, or, more famously, in the uncertainty in our observations of subatomic events in quantum mechanics, making probabilism the only way to access microphysical events.

[27] Although today there is a wide range of literature opposed to the higher-order view of existence, I still consider first-order views unnecessary and their conclusion that one cannot deny existence self-destructive. For a detailed discussion, see Costa 2018, pp. 213-217.

[28] Frege regarded a concept as an incomplete abstract object on the level of reference of a predicative expression. This view left him unable to say anything about the corresponding sense of the predicative expression, which intuitively should be its expressed concept. I prefer to locate the term concept on the level of sense or meaning, placing referred particularized properties or tropes on the level of reference. (Frege 1891, Cf. also Searle 2008, p. 186.)

[29] I take this terminology from my reconstruction of J. S. Mill’s definition of matter as “the permanent or warranted possibility of sensations”. What I call ‘effective applicability’ is the property of the rule of having its applicability warranted by some form of direct or indirect verification within an assumed domain of entities. For details, see Costa 2018, pp. 204-233.

[30] This is the only way I can interpret Kripke’s supernaturalistic explanation of how we identify individuals, as presented on pages 52-53 of his Naming and Necessity.

[31] An uppercase first letter is an indicator that a definite description is being used as a proper name.

[32] To be sure, the claim that they are applicable in all possible worlds seems to be nothing more than a manner of speaking, since if something is abstractly applied, it is not being effectively applied in a possible world – assuming we understand a possible world as any conceivable world-circumstance. To understand this better, consider again the description ‘the square root of nine’: then imagine yourself in a counterfactual situation doing the same abstract math in your head; this does not need to have anything to do with the world-circumstance we are conceiving.

[33] A difficulty is that too many descriptions can be associated with proper names. Thus, using Google Search I now see that the easternmost point of South America can also be called by the name ‘Cabo Branco’, a place I once visited in João Pessoa. However, it is not difficult to find more adequate examples. Thus, we can replace (ii) by (ii’) ‘the easternmost point of Iceland’, to counter the objection.

[34] The precise interpretation is controversial; here I give my own (Costa 1990: 147-167; Cf. Baker 1974).

[35] Wittgenstein suggests that the confusion between criteria and symptoms is a source of philosophical confusion (1958: I). To illustrate: the face and body of a person are symptoms of her identity, though at first view seeming to be criteria.

[36] Remember that according to Donald Williams’s trope theory, the whole world, including anything usually called “abstract” (things like rules or even the applicability of rules…) must be constituted by tropes. For my attempt to explain natural numbers in terms of tropes, see Appendix II.

[37]  Notice that the Earth can be a different planet in a differently conceivable world circumstance (possible world).

Nenhum comentário:

Postar um comentário