Retirado de draft avançado do livro "Philosophical Semantics: Reintegrating Theoretical Philosophy" (CSP 2018)
Chapter IV
An Extravagant Reading
of Fregean Semantics
Wenn es eine Aufgabe der Philosophie
ist, die Herrschaft des Wortes über den menschlichen Geist zu brechen, indem die
Täuschungen aufdeckt, die durch den Sprachgebrauch über die Beziehungen der Begriffe
oft fast unvermeidlich entstehen (…) so wird meine Begriffschrift, für diese Zwecke
weiter ausgebildet, den Philosophen ein brauchbares Werkzeug werden können.
[If it is a task
of philosophy to break the power of the word over the human spirit by laying bare
the misconceptions that through the use of language often almost unavoidably arise
… then my ideography, further developed for these purposes, can become a useful
tool for the philosopher.]
—Gottlob Frege
…might the time not have
come to reflect about the very foundations of analytic philosophy, and to see it
as one task of philosophy to break the power of the mathematical sign over the philosophical
mind?
—Edward Kanterian
The importance of Fregean semantics
for the philosophy of language derives from its unique blend of theoretical simplicity,
explanatory scope, and philosophical relevance. In this chapter, I want to revise
and reconstruct the essentials of Fregean semantics. I intend to make it clear that
his basic concept of sense can be paraphrased in terms of semantic-cognitive
rules and that his concept of existence can be reconstructed in terms of the
effective applicability of semantic-cognitive rules, leading to some unexpected
consequences regarding the explanation of the concepts of verification, fact, and
truth. With the identification of senses with rules, I intend to show the real link
between Wittgenstein’s semantics – that is, the way I understood his views in the
last chapter – and Frege’s semantics. This link was already noted by Michael Dummett,
though he still offered no proper pragmatic exploration. Anyway, my aim here is
not to produce a work of Fregean scholarship. It is instead to reconstruct Frege’s
semantic work with him, against him, and beyond him, in order to provide a more
rigorous framework for the rather vague semantic insights gained in the first
chapters.
As is general knowledge, Frege explains reference
(Bedeutung) using a semantic intermediary link which he called sense
(Sinn) (1891:14). The schema below shows how Frege deals with these two main
levels, (1) sense and (2) reference in the case of a predicative singular assertoric
sentence (Satz) of the form Fa:
singular term: a general term: F sentence: Fa
1. sense sense thought
2. reference concept (> object) truth-value
Although Fregean
semantics was a development of unparalleled importance for contemporary philosophy of
language, it is not free from well-known oddities. My intuitively natural reading
of its main semantic elements in terms of conceptual rules will also show how to
purge Frege’s semantics of its most
puzzling eccentricities.
1. Reference of the singular term
Let’s start with singular terms.
The reference of a singular term is, for Frege, the object itself, taken in an enlarged
sense. The reference of the name ‘Moon,’ according to him, is the Moon itself with
its craters. To designate the reference, he uses the German word ‘Bedeutung,’ whose
literal translation in English is ‘meaning.’ Most English translators have chosen
words like ‘reference,’ ‘denotation,’ and ‘nominatum,’ in this way making clear what Frege
really had in mind. There are also other terms, like ‘semantic value,’ ‘semantic
role’ and ‘truth-value potential.’ These terms underline the contributions of the
references of a sentence’s components to the truth-value of the sentence as a whole.
Although the literal translation of ‘Bedeutung’ as ‘meaning’ remains the correct
one, for the sake of clarity I will use the word ‘reference.’[1]
There is also an interpreter’s discussion of
the reason why Frege would have chosen the unexpected word ‘Bedeutung’ for the reference of a nominal
term. A widespread interpretation is that one of the meanings of ‘Bedeutung’ (as
well as of ‘meaning’ or ‘signification’) is relevance or importance,
since reference is what matters most for truth (Tugendhat 1992: 231). While this
may be the case, it seems clear to me that the strongest reason, at least with regard
to the reference of natural language terms, is that by introducing the term ‘Bedeutung’
Frege substantivated the verb ‘bedeuten.’
In this way, the word no longer expresses the act of pointing at (deuten) or of designating (bezeichnen), but
rather what is pointed at (die Bedeutung), what is designated (das Bezeichnete), that is, the reference
itself.[2] These derivations could be diagrammed
as follows:
Bedeutet... → deutet... bezeichnet... → was gedeutet, bezeichnet wird/
(means) (indicate... designates) (what is denoted, designated)
↓
die Bedeutung
(meaning = reference)
This would have been the small
semantic twist with which Frege turned the word ‘Bedeutung’ into a technical term
– a twist that seems to betray some semantic-referentialist influence.
2. Sense of the singular
term
Now we come to what Frege understands
as the sense of a singular term. To introduce it, compare the following two sentences:
1. The morning star has a dense atmosphere of
CO2.
2. The evening star has a dense atmosphere of
CO2.
Sentences (1) and (2) concern to
the same thing regarding the planet Venus. But in spite of this, a person can know
the truth of (1) without knowing the truth of (2) and vice versa. Frege’s explanation
for this is that although the two singular terms ‘the morning star’ and ‘the evening
star’ refer to the same planet Venus, they convey different informative contents, that is, they have different
senses (Sinne).[3] The word ‘sense’ is defined
by Frege as an object’s way of being given (die Art des Gegebenseins des
Gegenstandes), which is usually translated as a mode of presentation.
The senses of the singular terms ‘the morning star’ and ‘the evening star’ are different,
because ‘the morning star’ presents Venus as the brightest celestial body usually
seen just before sunrise, while ‘the evening star’ presents the same planet Venus
as the brightest celestial body usually seen shortly after sunset…
Frege writes that words express their
senses (drücken ihre Sinnen aus), while senses determine
(bestimmen) their reference, since the mode of presentation should
show us how to find the reference. Even in cases where the reference does not exist,
this determination of reference through sense is given as a possibility, since even
in this case the words preserve their senses. This fact points to a flaw in Frege’s
idea that sense is the way an object presents itself to us, for in the case of empty
terms there is no object to be presented to us. This is why sense can be better
understood as the intended mode of presentation instead of as a mode of presentation
given by the object (Textor 2010: 134); sense is the way we intentionally present
an object or reference to ourselves, whether it exists or not. At any rate, for
Frege an expression can have a sense without a reference, but cannot have a reference
without its determination by means of a sense.
Frege extended his notion of sense to other
terms and to sentences. In the case of the senses of (declarative) sentences, he
calls it cognitive or (more literally)
epistemic value (Erkenntniswert). The last term is also appropriate.
The Fregean concept of sense has epistemological interest, for it constitutes the
proper informative content of the linguistic expression. It is what makes ‘the
evening star’ and other expressions informative. Or, using Dummett’s words, ‘sense
is what we understand when we understand
an expression’ (1990: 92). The philosophical importance of Fregean semantics is
largely due to the epistemological and ontological imports of the concept of sense
(this is what distinguishes it from a more exclusively linguistic semantics like
that of Ferdinand de Saussure.)
Frege is a Platonist about sense. For this
reason, he conceives senses as abstract entities which can only be analyzed in terms
of constituents that are also senses. A consequence of his Platonism of senses is
that it prevents him from analyzing senses in terms of other concepts. However,
it is just this task that naturally imposes itself. For it seems very plausible
to understand senses as semantic-cognitive criterial rules. We see here a
fundamental difference between Fregean semantics and the semantic considerations
of the later Wittgenstein, who regarded senses or meanings as depending on episodic
uses of expressions determined by rules. Dummett was perhaps the first to defend the idea that senses are rules as the
most natural reading of Frege’s use
of the term senses. As he wrote in his book on Frege’s philosophy of language:
The sense of a word consists in a rule which, taken together with the rules
constitutive of the senses of the other words, determines the condition for the
truth of a sentence in which the word occurs. (1981b: 194; my italics)
And concerning the singular sentences
in Frege, understanding with the term ‘criterion’ the condition of satisfaction
of a semantic rule, he wrote:
To know the sense of a proper name is to have a criterion
for recognizing, for any given object, whether or not it is the bearer (referent)
of that name; to know the sense of a predicate is to have a criterion for deciding,
for any given object, whether or not the predicate applies to that object; and to
know the sense of a relational expression is to have a criterion for deciding, given
any two objects taken in a particular order, whether or not the relation it stands
for holds between the first object and the second. (1981b: 229)[4]
The identification between senses
and rules proves particularly compelling when we take numerical expressions as examples.
Consider the following expressions:
1 + 1,
6/3,
(7 + 3) – 8,
(874 – 870)/2
5 – 3
All these numerical expressions
have the same reference: the number 2. But their senses or modes of presentation
are in each case different. At the same time, they are expressions of procedures,
methods, semantic-cognitive rules or, in most cases, combinations of such rules
by means of which we reach the identification of the same number 2 as a result (See Runggaldier 1985: 91 f.).
By treating senses as semantic-cognitive rules
and these rules in the primary case as shared conventions, we contrast them with what Frege called colorations
and illuminations (Färbungen
and Beleuchtungen), which are feelings
often associated with image representations
(Vorstellungen) and sensory-perceptions
(Anschauungen), as such all belonging
to an intrinsically subjective level (Frege 1892: 31). These ‘colorations’
and ‘illuminations’ are names for what we would more often call expressive meanings, that is, sensory-emotional states that
we normally and customarily associate with expressions. Thus, for example, the words
‘love,’ ‘dog’ and ‘hell’ in the sentence ‘Love is a dog from hell’ (Bukowski) contrastively
associate words linked with strong specific emotions in order to create a weird
epigrammatic effect.
As Frege realized, the kind of appeal or lack
of appeal that the colorations associated with words have for different persons
depends correspondingly on similarities and differences in their human natures.
Because of this, they do not require conventions to be communicated, as in the case
of senses. This is why some people are emotionally moved by a certain poem, while
others are not. Consequently, it is very difficult to translate poetry, which depends
so much on colorations acquired by expressions in a particular language and form
of life. Hence, colorations are not results of conventional rules; they are rather
regularities originating from shared aspects
of human nature within a historically developed cultural context. If my understanding
of Wittgenstein’s argument against private language is correct, then his attempt
to explain phenomenological language as a simple replacement of public behavioral
criteria like uttering ‘ouch!’ under conditions that would cause pain with a sentence
like ‘I feel pain’ is insufficient (1984d, sec. 244). It is an attempt to assimilate
the referential meaning of the phenomenal language to its expressive meaning (I
suppose that both can be legitimated).
If in opposition to Frege we accept the view
that sense is usually only something with the form of a rule (etwas Regelartiges), namely, a convention or a combination of conventions,
we can easily solve the problem of the communicability of senses that has long
tormented philosophers like him. This is because the reason can easily be found
for the objectivity (interpersonal accessibility) of senses, as well as for their
consequent communicability. This reason is that Fregean senses are epistemic
unities easily reducible to conventional semantic-cognitive rules or associations
of them, and such conventions
are interpersonally established and agreed upon in a pre-reflexive manner. Indeed,
accepting the conclusions reached through our discussion of Wittgenstein’s views,
senses typically result either from the direct application of interpersonally established
semantic conventions or, more importantly, from associations or combinations of
these conventions.
Accepting that the sense of a singular term
is the same thing as a rule understood as a conventional or conventionally grounded
procedure that plays a decisive role in the identification of the object, it is
easy to go further and accept that this rule can be typically expressed by means
of definite descriptions. Hence, the sense or mode of presentation expressed by
the singular term ‘the morning star’ is a conventional rule that can be understood
as requiring as a criterial condition for the cognitive identification of the morning
star that we see as the brightest celestial
body not too far from the Sun just before or after the Sun rises. Concisely stated,
this rule can be expressed by the definite description ‘the brightest celestial
body that is seen close to where the Sun is about to rise.’ Without assuming that definite
descriptions are expressions of rules, Frege also approached this in a note on the
name ‘Aristotle’ (Frege 1892: 28). For him the proper name ‘Aristotle’ abbreviates
a cluster of modes of presentation of the object that can be expressed by descriptions,
which may include (i) ‘the disciple of Plato,’ (ii) ‘the teacher of Alexander the
Great,’ and (iii) ‘a person born in Stagira.’ If this is the case, then (i), (ii)
and (iii) express different senses, different rules that in one way or another help
us to determine the reference of the proper name ‘Aristotle’ (Cf. also Frege 1918-19: 63).[5]
Of course, there is a controversy about this
issue, which arose from Kripke’s arguments against descriptivist views of proper
names like Frege’s. However, it seems
to me out of question that Kripke’s arguments are successfully countered by the
kind of meta-descriptivist bundle theory suggested in the Appendix to Chapter I
of the present book.[6]
3. Reference of a predicative
expression
Frege
has something to say about the reference of a predicative expression, which he calls
a concept (Begriff) and which may include relations. This is odd because
it seems natural to call a concept something like the sense of a conceptual
expression – the mode of presentation of its designata – while the reference itself should be called a property
(e.g., a red patch) or some combination
of properties (e.g., a bird’s colorful feathers).
A traditional philosopher like Kant understood
the concept as immediately related to a schema,
which, as I understand him, is a rule
able to lead to the formation of a manifold variety of sensory patterns that are
satisfied by those things to which the concept applies (Cf. Kant 1988, B 180). Although Kant’s text on schematism is terminologically
impenetrable, it is easy to paraphrase his intuition using the terminology we have
developed based on Wittgenstein by saying that a concept is a semantic-cognitive
rule or procedure that requires the satisfaction of criteria by particularized properties
(p-properties) or tropes, which is also consonant with Dummett’s and
Tugendhat’s analyses of singular statements. Consequently, we have good reasons
to suspect that a concept should be the sense of a predicative expression, its mode
of presentation, and not its reference, as in Frege’s strange use of the term.
To be fair to Frege, he also says that when
an object falls under a concept, the concept may be called a property (Eigenschaft) of the object (1892: 201), seemingly acknowledging that
‘property’ is the right term for the reference of a predicative expression. However,
for him the criterion of identity for two concepts is the sameness of their value-range
(Wertverlauf), what includes their extension, which means that predicative expressions
with different senses but the same extension must refer to the same concept (2001:
31). So, for instance, ‘…animal with a kidney’ and ‘…animal with a heart’ should
be predicative expressions referring to the same concept since they have the same
extension. But it is intuitively obvious that kidneys and hearts are very different
concepts.
In addition to belonging to the realm of reference,
Frege also sees his concepts as functions.
The mathematical concept of function can be defined as a rule that has as its input arguments and as its output values
(for example: ‘3 + x = y’ is a
function by means of which when we give as input the number 2 as the argument for
x, we get as an output the number 5 as the value of y). For Frege, a concept is a function whose argument is the object
that ‘falls under it’ (fällt unter etwas) or does not and whose
value is a truth-value, which can be alternatively two abstract objects: ‘The True’
(das Wahre) when the object falls under the given concept and ‘The False’
(das Falsche) when it does
not. For
example, the concept designated by the conceptual term ‘...is a satellite of the
earth’ has the value true for the object Moon and the value false for the object
Jupiter.
Nevertheless, for Frege, concepts cannot be
objects, either collections of objects, nor extensions (2001: 26). The reason is
that objects, collections of objects and extensions are complete (vollständig)
entities. That is, they do not require anything
to complete them. A concept, by contrast, as a function, is seen by Frege as necessarily
open: he calls it an incomplete (unvollständig) or unsaturated
(ungesättigt) entity, needing to be completed by those arguments represented
by the objects falling under the concept. In contrast, objects referred to by proper
names are complete (vollständig), saturated (gesättigt) or independent
(unabhängig).
One could add that the saturated-unsaturated
distinction can be found on three distinct levels: linguistic, semantic and referential.
For instance: the predicate ‘…is a horse’ could be called an unsaturated linguistic
expression (the unsaturatedness is shown by the gap ‘…’), expressing a supposedly
unsaturated sense, which refers to an unsaturated concept (property) as the ultimate
unsaturated ground. This unsaturated concept, for its part, becomes saturated when some object falls
under it, for instance, the object named ‘Bucephalus’ referred to by the predicative
sentence ‘Bucephalus is a horse.’
With metaphors like those of ‘unsaturation’
and ‘incompleteness,’ Frege hoped to open the way to the solution of the problem
of the logical distinction between the subject and predicate of a sentence. After
all, the subject (the singular term) would refer to the saturated object, which
would complete the unsaturated concept referred to by the predicate (general term).
Unsaturated predicative expressions and saturated
singular terms combine to form saturated singular sentences like ‘Bucephalus is
a horse,’ which being complete must also be the name of an object, which for Frege
is the truth-value of the sentence. This seems to be confirmed by the possibility
we have of nominalizing sentences in the form of definite descriptions, since the
latter are also singular terms (1879: § 3). Thus, the sentence ‘Bucephalus is a
horse’ can be transformed in the description ‘the horse named Bucephalus,’ which
appears in the sentence as ‘The horse named Bucephalus was black.’ The problem with
this argument is that the same can also be done with general terms: ‘…is a horse’
can be nominalized as ‘the horse,’ as found in sentences like ‘The horse is an herbivorous animal.’ Hence, this argument
isn’t persuasive. Anyway, we can accept that assertoric sentences are like
proper names in the sense that they do not require completion as unities of
meaning.
4. Ontological level
Discussing the unsaturated nature
of the references of predicative expressions leads us to the question of the ontological
nature of what Frege meant by a concept. If a concept is an unsaturated entity,
what kind of entity is it? If it is an abstract entity, it seems that we should
also have concepts as referred-to abstract entities of empty predicates, like ‘…is
a yeti,’ which seems to be an ontologically abusive
admission.
Anyway, it is by now clear that Frege uses
the word ‘concept’ as a technical term that contrasts too strongly with the word’s
ordinary use. For our ordinary language intuition, there is surely an empty concept
expressed by the predicate ‘…is a yeti,’ but this concept should be called empty
because it is nothing but the sense of a predicate that has no reference at all!
It is no wonder that Frege has nothing to say about the sense of predicative expressions,
since he has beforehand emptied them by absorbing the semantic level into the ontological
one.
My final conclusion is that it is better to
drop the Fregean technical notion of a ‘concept.’ This is a problematic remnant
of ontological realism that does nothing to explain predication. Instead, I will
understand the word ‘concept’ here in an intuitive way as the sense of the predicative expression: its
mode of presentation of something. It is counter-intuitive to assume that ‘...is a yeti’ must have any reference;
but this predicate clearly has a sense intuitively expressing what we ordinarily
understand by a concept, namely, that of the abominable snowman of the Himalayas.
Thus, it seems that the best way to give a legitimate role to the word ‘concept’
is to see it as the sense of a predicative expression understood as its cognitive
meaning, that is, its ascription rule.
5. Referring to particularized
properties: trope theory
But if we drop Frege’s technical
notion of concept, what is the reference of a predicative expression? I think that
nowadays the most reasonable answer to this question consists in an appeal to
the pure ontology of tropes proposed in the Appendix of Chapter III of this book,
since it not only promises a parsimonial solution for ontological problems, but
produces less difficulties than the traditional doctrines. Thus, I propose to replace
Frege’s reference of predicative expressions with what we now call a trope, which I characterize simply as
any spatiotemporally individualizable
property, notwithstanding its degree of vagueness.
There are many examples of tropes that are
genetically primary and directly accessible to experience: the white color I see
when I look at newly fallen snow on a sunny day, and which is there in my visual
field, the smooth surface of this couch, the rectangular shape of my computer screen,
its hardness or my headache. All these are tropes – spatiotemporally particularized
properties or simply p-properties – that may range from simple objective or subjective
qualities to complex ones, and from homogeneous
or heterogeneous complex tropes, like the music I listen to in the former case and the personality
of a human being or a country’s political system or a social upheaval in that
country in the latter, since all these things are in a less specific way also spatiotemporally
localizable. Also very indirectly experienceable things like physical forces could
be derivatively constructed from perceived tropes, since they are spatiotemporally
localizable, and it is not inconceivable that even space and time, together
with formal properties could eventually be reducible to tropes, as I tried to
show in the Appendix of Chapter III.
Moreover, it is easy to suggest a particularistic
construction of universals built on the basis of particularized properties or tropes.
In my view, a universal can be disjunctively defined as:
Any chosen trope model
T* or any other trope strictly
similar[7] to T*.
I suggest this assuming
that the trope we take as the model T* is at our discretion and may vary
according to the epistemic subject and even concerning the same epistemic subject
on different occasions.[8] In this case, tropes T1, T2…
Tn are identified as instantiations of the universal only because they are strictly
similar (qualitatively identical) to an arbitrarily chosen trope model T*. An additional point
is that usually the trope-model needs to be intermediated by memory: we (usually)
don’t bring with us physical patterns to compare things with, but have a memory
of them. The memory-trope cannot be the primary trope we intend to consider, since
it must stand for the experienced one.
A material object could be constructed as a
cluster of tropes. It can in principle be understood as a cluster of tropes displaying
at least compresence, that is, it must
consist of a co-located and co-temporal cluster of tightly connected varied tropes.
Moreover, there are some general characterizing property-tropes like unity, displaceability,
volume, solidity, resistance to pressure – scientifically explained in a
broader way as inertial mass – that typically comprise material objects.
I usually avoid using the word ‘property’ instead
of ‘trope,’ not because it isn’t the best one, but because the philosophical tradition
has too often hypostasized this word as referring to some scarcely intelligible
non-empirical entity, vitiating our philosophical language. This tradition has stubbornly
ignored the fact that in ordinary language the word ‘property’ has always been used
to refer to simple or complex, homogeneous or heterogeneous tropes. Anyway, I intend
to use the word trope exactly as the word ‘property’ is ordinarily used. Thus, I
explicitly include among the tropes complex tropes made up of different kinds of
tropes, these complex tropes possibly being designated by composite predicates like
‘…a black horse of the best Thessalonian strain’ in the sentence ‘Bucephalus was
a black horse of the best Thessalonian Strain.’ This does not make this complex
trope (complex property) a singular material object, mainly because, as we will
see later, a singular material object, taken as an individual, is seen as able
to exist independently if compared with the trope to which it is tied (in a different
possible world Alexander’s beloved horse, Bucephalus, could still exist even if
he were just a tired old nag).
According to the understanding of the reference
of predicative terms that I am proposing, a predicative
expression like ‘... is white’ in the sentence ‘The moon is white’ does not
refer to any Fregean concept. It primarily ascribes, denotes, designates
(or refers to) a particularized property, namely, a trope, which is the
whiteness of the Moon as normally seen by observers on the Earth. Secondarily but
distinctively, however, the predicate ‘…is white’ also alludes to (or connotes) the fact that this trope exemplifies the
universal property of whiteness, here understood in the already explained particularist
way as this same model trope that is being considered, or any other trope that is
like it. Summarizing, a predicative expression has mainly a twofold function:
(A) An ascriptive
function: that of ascribing or denoting the trope (property) belonging to
the object referred to by the subject term,
(B) An allusive
function: that of alluding to or connoting the denoted trope or any other
tropes that would be strictly similar to the model-trope that could be considered
by the speaker as designated by the predicative expression, building what might
be called the universal, here understood
in an ontologically unobjectionable particularist way.
The allusive function is subsidiary
to the ascriptive function: to identify a trope you do not necessarily need to grasp
its role as an instance of a universal.[9] Better said, as particularized
properties tropes have not only ontological, but also epistemic priority if compared
with their role in the identification of universals.
Furthermore – opposing the overwhelming influence
of the logicist tradition – we have, as a still more subsidiary element: (C) the
extension. Although relevant, differently
from (A) and (B), extension isn’t primarily associated with predication. Extension
doesn’t even need to be implicitly considered in the act of predication! However,
it can be derived from the application of the allusive function of the predicate
plus additional information, allowing us to infer or even find: (C1) an extension
of tropes as the set of tropes strictly similar to the trope in question and (C2)
an extension of objects as a set of objects having tropes strictly similar to the
trope in question. However, in both cases the extension is a further element that
is usually an only vaguely inferred set.[10] As a rule, you do not need
to take it into consideration to use a predicate ascriptively.
6. Difficulty with
the concept of unsaturation
The main objection to the idea of incompleteness or unsaturation is that it
fails to serve its main purpose, which is that of distinguishing a predicative expression from a nominative
or singular term. Between the object referred to by the subject and the property
designated by the predicate, there seems to be an important functional asymmetry:
the nominative term always refers to its object and cannot properly take the place
of a predicate; on the other hand, it seems that we can easily turn a predicate
into a subject by means of nominalization.[11] For instance, ‘Socrates’ in
the statement ‘Socrates is wise’ always refers to its object and cannot properly
take the place of a predicate, while ‘… is wise’ can be nominalized as ‘wisdom’
in a statement like ‘Wisdom is a virtue.’ To make the point more convincing, consider
the following sentences:
1. <A man who lived in Antiquity> was called
Socrates.
2. <Wisdom> is a property of Socrates.
3. <Xantippe’s husband> is Socrates.
4. <There> is Socrates!
In these sentences, the name ‘Socrates’
at least seems to occupy a predicative position. However, this name clearly continues
to be used logically as a proper name, since the true logical form of these sentences
can be easily expressed, respectively by:
1. <Socrates>
was a man who lived in Antiquity.
2. <Socrates>
has the property of being wise.
3. <Socrates>
is the husband of <Xantippe>.
4. <Socrates> is in < that place>![12]
One cannot effectively transform
a singular term as such into a predicate, while predicates seem to be easily transformed
by nominalization into singular terms. However, we can show that the nominalized
predicate is, in fact, a disguised universal predication: the sentence ‘Wisdom is
a virtue,’ for instance, could be analyzed as, ‘For any x, if x has
wisdom then x is virtuous.’ However, the asymmetry returns at this deeper
level, since we cannot analyze a proper nominal term (like ‘Socrates’) in the same
way. The asymmetry suggests that subjects and predicates play different logical
roles in sentences, which requires explanation. The question is: can the Fregean
distinction between saturation and unsaturation really do anything to explain the
difference?
At first glance, the answer is in the negative.
Frege’s distinction does not explain the difference between subject and predicate
in a logical sense, because it is also possible to suggest that a singular term
and, therefore, its sense and reference, is unsaturated or incomplete! After all,
what is the difference between:
[Bucephalus, Silver,
Black Beauty, Fury… Pegasus] …is a horse.
And
Bucephalus is... [black,
strong, restless, swift… of the best Thessalonian strain]?
In the first case, the concept
‘…is a horse’ is a function that according to Frege may have as an argument any
object and as a value a resulting truth-value, which for the object Bucephalus is ‘The True’ and for the object
Alexander is ‘The False.’ However, it makes just as much sense to apply the same reasoning
to the second case. One can suggest that the nominal expression ‘Bucephalus is…’
refers to an object that is a function that may have as its argument any property designated by any predicative expression.
If it is the property white, it has as a value ‘The False,’ and if
it is the property black, it has ‘The
True’ as its value, since we know
that Bucephalus
was a black horse. The undesirable conclusion is that in a singular predicative
sentence both the general and the singular terms can be viewed as unsaturated in
the sense of denoting functions that can be supplemented by a myriad of arguments
able to bring in ‘The True’ or ‘The False’ as the resulting values!
7. Unsaturation as
ontological dependence
Notwithstanding, I think that the
metaphor of unsaturation is not exhausted so easily. In chemistry, a carbon compound
is said to be unsaturated when it contains carbon-carbon bonds that can be broken
by the addition of hydrogen atoms, which make it a saturated compound. The hydrogen
atoms aren’t said to be unsaturated. Isn’t there a hint in the metaphor of an answer
that was not sufficiently explored by Frege?
In what follows, I hope to offer a reading
of the reference of a predicative expression in terms of tropes that enables us
to make a useful paraphrase of the Fregean distinction between saturation and unsaturation.
This paraphrase is inspired by the Aristotelian independence definition of the individual as primary substance:
All the other things are either said of the primary substances as
subjects or in them as subjects. For example, animal is predicated of man and
therefore also of the individual man; for were it predicated of none of the
individual men it would not be predicated of man at all… Thus, all the other
things are either said of the primary substances as subjects or in them as
subjects. So, if the primary substances did not exit it would be impossible for
any of the other things to exist. (1984, vol. 1, Categories, sec. 5)
That
is, some
things can exist apart, and some cannot, and the former are substances.
I am not here worried in questioning if there
are substances, what they are and if they are ultimately able to exist apart. However,
applied to individuals or material objects understood as (at least) clusters of
tropes displaying compresence, the independence definition suggests that the objects typified by material things exist
in a manner relatively independent of their tropes in the composition of facts
understood as tropical arrangements in the world.[13] Moreover, I hold that the individual referred to as a subject is
only independent relatively to its
predicated trope-properties, because the relation of existential independence/dependence
is here understood in a way restricted to the internal context of the fact represented
by the statement.
In other words, my suggestion is that the true dichotomy distinguishing subject from predicate
is between independence and dependence, terms only rarely used by
Frege. Thus, what distinguishes the designatum
of a predicative expression in the fundamental case of a predicative or relational
statement is that this reference is a trope (simple or complex, homogeneous or heterogeneous)
whose existence as part of the fact depends on a cluster of selected compresent
tropes constituting the individual referred to by the singular term, which is
independent relatively to that trope. It seems that this fragile distinction is
what that really distinguishes the references of logical subjects. Here are some
clear examples supporting this view:[14]
Mary’s smile depends
on Mary’s existence.
The car’s skidding depends
on the car’s existence.
The snubness of Socrates’
nose depends on Socrates’ existence.
Amundsen’s expedition
to the South Pole depended on the existence of both Amundsen and the South Pole.
These examples also make it
clear that we do not mean that the dependent tropes (like those of smile, skidding,
snubness, expedition to South Pole…) could not exist independently of other individuals
as clusters of compresent tropes, but that they could not exist as they are independently
of the individual or individuals belonging to the fact represented by the respective
statements. – Qualitatively identical tropes of smile, skidding, snubness… could
obviously exist in the dependence of other
individuals.
Concerning singular statements,
my suggestion can be summarized as follows:
In the constitution of a fact represented by a true singular (predicative
or relational) statement, the trope ascribed by the predicative expression only
exists in the dependence on the existence of the compresent trope-cluster
constitutive of the object(s) referred to by the nominal term(s).
Hence, it is important to see that
the considered existential tropical dependence is relative to the fact it is a
constituent (Cf. section 23).
In trying to explore this view in more detail,
we can begin by remembering Peter Simons’ nuclear trope theory of material objects.
According to this theory, individuals are in the standard case formed by an essential
nucleus or core of mutually founding tropes,
which is necessarily surrounded by a looser cluster of accidental peripheral tropes,
so that these peripheral tropes require the nucleus of essential tropes for their
existence (See Appendix to Chapter III, sec. 3). To this we should add, as already
noted for the relevant case of material objects, that belonging to the nucleus are
typically tropes like those of hardness, form, volume and resistance to pressure
or solidity, a trope that in physics was better elaborated under the label of inertial mass, all of them related by the dependent trope of compresence.
Unfortunately, the issue is not so simple.
As we saw in the Appendix of Chapter I, the identification rule of a proper name requires
for its application sufficient and predominant satisfaction of at least one inclusive
disjunction of the two fundamental description-rules belonging to it, which are
the localizing and the characterizing rules (Cf. Appendix to Chapter I). This identification rule, as we also saw,
can be satisfied by an indeterminate range of independent criterial configurations,
in other words, tropes or configurations of tropes.
This means that what Simons understood as a necessary nucleus of mutually
founding tropes may change regarding one only individual in different
counter-factual situations.
Already considered examples are the Aristotle born 500 years later in Rome in one
possible world and the Aristotle who in another possible world was born with cerebral paralysis in
Stagira in 283 BC, son of Nicomachus… and was unable because of his disorder
to write any philosophy. Hence, the nucleus
of mutually founding tropes may be different within limits established by the identification
rule. Consequently, in the case of objects referred to by proper names there is
no necessary condition in re – no unique real essence of the object – to be expected, but only a nominal essence
given by its proper identification rule, even if grounded on verified regularities.
Peripheral tropes, on their side, would be those referred to by our auxiliary descriptions
like (i) ‘the teacher of Alexander’ and (ii) ‘the founder of the Lyceum.’ And it
is clear that the tropes designated by relations like ‘…the teacher of…’ and ‘…the
founder of…’ are dependent on the existence of individuals like ‘Aristotle,’ ‘Alexander’
and the ‘Lyceum’ in order to exist as components of the facts represented by statements
(i) and (ii).
Searching for a simpler example, I will now
consider the singular term ‘this chair.’ I regard this phrase as an indexical name.
This indexical name has an identification rule made up of two interconnected fundamental description-rules: a
contextually dependent localizing description-rule establishing a spatiotemporal
location (by means of the demonstrative ‘this’ and some indicative gesture) and a characterizing description-rule (by
means of the sortal ‘chair’). This characterizing description-rule is simply the
definition of a chair as a non-vehicular seat with a backrest made for only one
person to sit on at a time. We can say that the complex criterion for the identification
of chairs added to the spatiotemporal location is what in this case forms the indispensable
nuclear structure of this designatum.
Symptoms of this chair, such as its having four legs and two armrests, or its being
made of wood, are peripheral combinations of tropes.
Moreover, if I say ‘This chair is green,’ the trope of green (in the described fact)
exists in dependence on the existence of a complex of compresent tropes that forms
this chair and would not exist without their existence.
These considerations allow us to better understand
the corresponding independence-dependence relation regarding the compresent core
of tropes of an object satisfying its identification rule and its contingent peripheral
tropes. Consider, for example, the singular predicative sentence ‘Bucephalus is
swift.’ The predicate ‘...is swift’ in this sentence applies to a contingent trope
that constitutes swiftness, whose existence
is here fully dependent on the existence of an object, Bucephalus, which is constituted
by some core of compresent tropes constitutive of a living material object. On the
other hand, the same distinction also applies to properties linked to individuals
that are not properly material objects. A rainbow, for instance, is an individual
(a cluster of compresent tropes), though not properly a material object. But consider
the dynamic fact described by the statement ‘That rainbow is fading away.’ The fading
away of a rainbow is a process-trope whose existence is dependent on the existence
of the rainbow in itself.
Consider now the true relational sentence ‘Bucephalus
belongs to Alexander.’ Regarding this fact, the contingent relational complex trope
of belonging to could not possibly be
found if Bucephalus and Alexander didn’t exist as independent individuals formed
by nuclei of compresent tropes. That is, the proper existence of the relation ‘…belongs
to…’ is here indebted to the existence of two more stable essential nuclei of mutually
founding tropes constituting the two objects Bucephalus and Alexander. These clusters
of compresent tropes referred to by the names ‘Bucephalus’ and ‘Alexander’ are concrete
psycho-physical individuals that certainly exist independently of the existence
of the relatively contingent complex combinations of tropes constituting the trope
of ‘…belongs to…’ since to have ownership we need the previous existence of individuals
having this particular relational property.
A problem arises when we have independent countable
things or sortals designated by predicative expressions. So, consider once more
our definition of a chair as a seat with a backrest made for only one person to
sit on at a time. Suppose now that I point to the chair and say, (i) ‘This chair
has two armrests.’ Since the tropical clusters constitutive of having two armrests
do not belong to the definition that makes explicit the nucleus, its existence as
something that the chair should be dependent on the chair’s existence. However,
the predicate ‘…has two armrests’ exists in the independence of the object
referred to by the subject ‘this chair,’ since they can be separated from the
chair, differently from its color or size. The solution to this problem is
simply to see the above logical analysis as incomplete. The right analysis must
take roughly the form: (ii) ‘<This chair> has <its first armrest
here> and <its second armrest there>, and they are two,’ pointing to
the armrests, where ‘x having y and z’ is the main property-trope, which is dependent on this chair and
its armrests.
A related problem arises when predicates denote
sortals belonging to definitional cores. Suppose I say, (i) ‘This chair has a backrest,’
where ‘…has a backrest’ is the predicative expression. The problem is not only
that having a backrest belongs intrinsically to the object referred to by the
singular term, but that the backrest exists independently of the chair. One can
saw the backrest and say things like ‘This backrest is green,’ using ‘this
backrest’ to refer to an individual. To this case, I suggest a similar
solution. A more complete analysis of the sentence (i) will be (ii) ‘<This
backrest> belongs (intrinsically) to <this chair>,’ where ‘x belongs
intrinsically to y’ means that it belongs definitionally to the sortal ‘chair’ used
to characterize the located individual y.
Very complex tropes (homogeneous or
heterogeneous, mixed or not) are also existentially dependent on the individuals
to which they are bounded. Consider some examples:
(1)
<Céline> had a strange personality.
(2)
<India> has a democratic system.
(3)
<The ancient Spartan State> was extremely
militarized.
(4)
<The Vienna Philharmonic Orchestra> played the 5th
Symphony.
(5)
<The Irish potato famine> was caused by <the late
blight>.
None of these tropes could
survive alone. They need to be attached to some localizable and characterizable
individual to which they belong.
Finally, what about formal names and sentences?
Consider the sentence ‘Three is an odd number.’ This sentence describes a mathematical
fact. Considering here ideas about what confers existence, we can think the number
three without thinking that it is also an odd number, or ‘the number two or any
multiple of two added to the number one,’ which is the definition of an odd number.
But there is no ‘being odd’ independent of a number. Hence, the existence of oddness
factually related to the existence of the number three is dependent on the number
three that we are taking into consideration.
Consider now the statement ‘Two is a natural
number.’ One could argue that to be a natural number belongs to the definition of
two as a kind of genus proximum, although
not essentially to the (here seen as incomplete) definition of two as its differentia. Maybe this differentia could be given by our already
suggested understanding of applied natural numbers as higher-order tropical properties
of actual or idealized counting belonging to an effectively applicable conceptual
rule (See sec. 4 of the Appendix of Chapter III). Repeating what I said there, consider
the statement ‘This hat has three corners.’ Here the applied number 3 indicates
that the possible conceptual rule identifying the corners of this hat not only has
the tropical meta-property of being applicable (attributing existence), but also
the tropical meta-property of being applicable three times in an additive way
(a counting process). Moreover, we can analytically express this conceptually dependent
higher-order trope of 3 by means of the set of applications {a, {a}, {{a}}} understood
as a spatiotemporally located higher-order numerical set-trope.
But how to represent the number 3 distinguishing
it as the universal object that is common to all conceptual identifications of three singular entities, the three-in-itself?
Here, if we wish to avoid speaking of a Russellian abstract set of all sets of the
same kind, we can still construct the number 3 as a located model of tropical numerable
trope-set {a, {a}, {{a}}} or any other
strictly (equinumerous) located trope-set:
Number 3 in itself (Df.) = a chosen higher-order located numerical set-trope of counting
{a, {a}, {{a}}}* used as a model or any other higher-order strictly similar located numerical set-trope.
This definition still allows the
predicate ‘…is a natural number’ to be ascribed to the whole definiens as an internal dependent addition
(a genus) and the predicate ‘…is an odd
number’ as an external dependent addition. In any case, even the name of a so-called
abstract object, such as ‘the number three in itself’ cannot be moved to the predicate
position here, insofar as it refers to something held as independent, being identifiable
(existing) independently of its non-definitional predicates like ‘…is an odd number.’
Understanding
unsaturatedness as relative existential dependence suggests, therefore, that the tropes denoted by the
predicate have an inevitable tie of dependence
when considered in relation to
the relevant individual within the fact referred to by the singular sentence.
This gives us a better understanding of the asymmetrical tie between subject
and predicate.
Summarizing
the argument, my point is that the independence/dependence distinction gives
a sufficiently reasonable ontological ground (I guess the only one) to explain the
logical distinction between the references of subject and predicate in singular
predicative and relational sentences. The nominal term cannot be moved to the predicate
position because it refers to a core of compresent tropes that exists in relative
independence of the less central tropes in and outside of the core, these less central
tropes being able to be designated by predicative expressions.
In my view, the proposed analysis also sheds
light on the so-called problem
of the unity of proposition. What really differentiates subject from predicate regarding
the fact represented by the statement is the corresponding independence/dependence
of their references. Moreover, what assures the unity of the thought-content expressed
by the sentence is simply the existential dependence/independence in the factual
unity (for instance, in the fact that Bucephalus is swift). And it is clear that
these ties of dependence/independence will be more evident when the difference in
relevance between the elements in question regarding the identity of the individuals is greater, and weaker when this difference
is smaller, justifying occasional uncertainties.
Finally, one could object that what really
distinguishes the predicate from the subject in singular statements is simply that
the subject is a singular term that identifies one particular object and distinguishes it from all others, while the
predicate is a general term able to be applied
to more than one object… It is this possible one-to-many relation that is at
the base of the subject-predicate distinction!
Nonetheless, although this is true
regarding a formal definition of singular and general terms, I believe that
what gives a reason for this distinction is the relation of
independence/dependence between subject and predicate. What defines an
individual is that because of the uniqueness of its existence it can be
referred to by a nominal term by satisfying its condition of sufficiency. And
what defines a property-trope is its existential dependence on some individual
(object). The individual is by definition non-repeatable. On the other hand,
the property-trope is repeatable, insofar as qualitatively the same
property-trope can be, by its lack of existential dependence, tied to many
individuals. But this is so as a consequence of the fact that the existence of
the property-trope must always be dependent on the existence of individuals,
disregarding what individuals. In the end, it is the difference in nature
between individuals (objects) and property-tropes (attributes) that is
responsible for the one-to-many relation.
8. Sense of a predicative term
The independence/dependence relationship
originating on the ontological level of reference is reflected on the semantic and
linguistic levels. It is first reflected on the semantic-epistemic level of Fregean
senses. We see this in the fact that the identification rule of the nominal term
– its sense – is applied to its object independently of the ascription of tropes
to the same object by the ascription rule
– the sense – of the predicative expression, while the ascription rule of the predicative
expression – its sense – depends on the prior application of the identification
rule of the object referred to by the nominal term. Finally, on the level of linguistic
signs, the same relation of independence/dependence is what makes the singular predicative
sentence take its usual subject-predicate form.
Our view of tropes as the designata of predicative expressions allows us to make some additions not present in Frege’s original semantic distinctions. The first is the suggestion that
different predicative expressions with the same designata may be able to have different senses, paralleling the case
of nominal terms like definite descriptions. Consider the following two sentences:
1. Mont Blanc is white.
2. Mont Blanc reflects
all wavelengths of the visible spectrum.
The reference of the predicative
expressions of sentences (1) and (2) – the trope or compositions of tropes that
constitute the whiteness of Mont Blanc – remains the same, while the senses
of the predicative expressions are different: a person may know that Mont Blanc
is white without knowing that its surface reflects all wavelengths of the visible
spectrum and vice versa. This means that there are differences in concepts as modes
of presentation or ascription rules of the predicative
expressions of sentences (1) and (2), although they have the same designatum.
Another consequence of our understanding of
predicative expressions as basically referring to tropes by means of their semantic-cognitive
conceptual rules contradicts the Fregean expectation that the same sense cannot
have more than one reference, which favors the potential for multi-referentiality
inherent to predication. Consider the following sentences:
1. The South Pole is white.
2. Mont Blanc is white.
The predicate ‘...is white’ in
sentences (1) and (2) obviously has the same sense in both, as in each case it expresses
qualitatively identical ascription rules. But the tropes of whiteness (of reflecting
the combined wavelengths of the visible spectrum) of the South Pole are located
at the South Pole itself, while the tropes of whiteness of Mont Blanc are
located in its eternal snows. The same can be found in the application of relational
predicates. This is explained by the fact that the different objects referred to
by different singular terms have numerically different tropical configurations that
satisfy qualitatively identical ascription rules of the same predicative expression.
9. Dependence of the
predicative sense
As we have already noted, in the
context of a singular predicative sentence, the identification rule of the singular
term applies to the object as some core of compresent tropes, which seen as a
whole exists independently in relation to its more or less dependent partial or
peripheral tropes. Consequently, the identification rule is also able to be applied
regardless of the application of contingent ascription rules, which means that this
identification rule can be conceived as being applied in isolation. This explains
its independence and why one could call it complete or saturated. The ascription
rule, on its side, will be applied to a trope dependent on the core and consequently
depending for its real application on the earlier application of the identification
rule, lacking in this sense completeness. This is at most clear in the case of rules
for contingent properties, like the conceptual rule for the predicate ‘swift’ when
applied to Bucephalus.
The same may also hold for the fundamental
descriptions constitutive of the identification rule of the nominal term in the
sentential context. Since the tropes belonging to the object to which the identification
rule applies are ultimately dependent on the existence of this object as containing
a kernel of tropes, even the ascription rules of predicative expressions already
belonging to the identification rule of the object as part of this rule require prior application of the whole identification
rule to identify the object in order to become themselves applicable as part of
the identification (e.g. the statement ‘Aristotle was the author of the Metaphysics’).
Because of this, the application of the
predicate’s ascription rule is always dependent on the application of the identification
rule of the singular term.[15]
The general sense of a concept-word, which
(diverging from Frege) we identify with the concept or ascriptive rule expressed
by it, should then be a rule whose application to an object depends on the prior
application of another rule. Hence, the ascription rule of the predicative expression
is dependent, incomplete, unsaturated, in the sense that it demands the prior application
of the identification rule of the singular term in order to be applied. It is necessary
to identify, that is, in the empirical case to find some particular object in space
and time, in order to be able to characterize it by ascribing the predicative rule
to its appropriate trope. We must, for instance, first apply the rule that allows
us to spatiotemporally locate the horse called Bucephalus in order to apply to it
related tropes, and on that basis, the ascription rules of predicative terms. Thus,
due to the independence of the object Bucephalus, we apply the ascription rules
for the predicates ‘... is a horse,’ ‘... is black,’ ‘... is swift’… and also the
ascription rules of more complex predicative expressions like ‘…a horse that belonged
to the best Thessalonian breed’ to the tropical kernel constitutive of Bucephalus.
And we also need first to apply the identification rules for Bucephalus and Alexander
in order to be able to apply the relational predicate ‘…belongs to…’ In a
similar way, we need to apply the rule that allows us to mentally identify the number
3, in order to be able to apply to associated dependent tropes the ascription rules
of predicative expressions like ‘…is odd,’ ‘…is a prime number,’ though it is not
the case that the number 3 depends on these things in order to be identified as
such. In the same way, the relational ascription rule for ‘3 < 7’ is only applicable
in dependence on the independent application of the identification rules for the
numbers 3 and 7.
As I have very early noted (Ch. I, sec. 1),
it would be a naive objection to think that after all it is possible to say things
like ‘That is a horse’ or ‘There is a black thing,’ applying ascription rules of
predicates without identifying Bucephalus. The reason is that a fully detailed identification
of the reference as Bucephalus isn’t required at all. Indexicals such as ‘that’
and ‘there’ accompanied by some gesture of pointing are already able to identify
some spatiotemporally localizable spot which exists independently of further predication,
being therefore in a technical sense an object or individual. As we already saw,
this relative independency of the indexical identification rule can be made explicit
when the indexical is followed by a term designating countable things, that is,
a sortal, such as ‘that object,’ ‘that
animal,’ since we localize with the demonstrative and characterize with the
sortal. Therefore, not only does the trope designated by the predicate depend upon
the previous existence of the object and its identification, but, as a consequence,
also the effective applicability of the ascription rule of the predicate must be
dependent upon the prior application of the identification rule to the relatively
independent cluster of tropes. This is how the relation of semantic dependency –
on the level of sense – mirrors the relation of ontological dependency – on the
level of reference – solving the riddle of unsaturation.
10. The concept horse
paradox
We can continue to make major revisions
of Frege’s views in order to overcome difficulties arising from his semantic views,
like the so-called concept horse paradox. Based on his view of a concept as the
unsaturated reference of a predicate, Frege was led to the strange conclusion that
one cannot name a concept. For him the sentence:
1. The concept horse is not a concept,
is true. After all, ‘the concept horse’ appears here as a singular term
– a definite description – and as such it must refer to something saturated, that
is, an object and not a concept. The paradoxical point is that the denial of the
true sentence (1), which is:
2. The concept horse is a concept,
must for Frege be false! Nonetheless, (2) clearly sounds like
an obviously true analytic sentence.
From our perspective, the first thing to do
is to treat nominalization as what it really is: an abbreviated way to speak about
quantified concepts. What (1) really means is:
3.
For any
x, if x is a concept horse, then x
isn’t a concept,
which is obviously false. Regarding sentence (2) it really means:
4.
For any
x, if x is a concept horse, then x
is a concept,
which is obviously true. Using H to replace ‘… is a concept horse,’ which is
the ascription rule able to designate the property-trope of horseness, and replacing
‘…is a concept’ with C, which is the ascription rule able to designate any property-trope
in an undifferentiated way, we can formalize (3) as (5): (x) (Hx → ~Cx), which is false, and (4) as (6): (x) (Hx
→ Cx), which is true.
What is the lesson of this analysis? If ‘the
concept horse’ does not really work as a definite description – as a singular term
– but rather as a hidden universal predication, Frege was wrong in maintaining that
it cannot be a concept only because it now works as a definite description. Frege’s
‘paradox’ results from an incomplete analysis of sentences like (1) and (2) and
the true analyzed sentences are the corresponding harmless universal conditionals
(3) and (4), the first being contradictorily false and the second tautologically
true. If we agree that rightly analyzed ‘the concept horse’ expresses a universal
predication and no real singular term, the whole paradox dissolves. It turns out to originate from the naïve mistake
of thinking that if you put a predicate in the position of a subject, transforming
it into a definite description, you necessarily transform it into a real singular
term (See Appendix to this chapter).
11. Existence as a
property of concepts
At this point, we can turn to Frege’s
treatment of the concept of existence. Deepening an idea already present in Kant’s
philosophy, he suggested that existence is a property (Eigenschaft) of a
concept, namely, the property that at least one object would fall under it (Frege
1884, sec. 53). A similar idea was later advocated by Bertrand Russell in the suggestion
that existence is the property of a propositional function of being true for at
least one instance (1994: 232-3, 250-54.).
Here I will not try to interpret the details
of Frege’s often obscure remarks. Using more current terminology, I will follow
an explanation taken from John Searle, who with his usual clarity brings us unmistakably
to the point (2008: 176). Consider the sentence ‘Horses exist.’ This sentence can
be analyzed as:
There is at least one ... such
that (... is a horse).
As Searle notes, this sentence
contains two components. One is expressed by the predicate ‘…is a horse,’ symbolically
Hx (where we use x instead of ‘…’
and H replaces ‘is a horse’). The other component is the predication of existence
expressed by the open sentence ‘there is at least one ... such that ...’ This predication
can be symbolically expressed as Ǝx(...) (where Ǝx replaces ‘there is at least one … such that…,’ and the last ‘...’
is the gap to be filled by some concept applied to something, now in the
most proper ususal sense of the word concept, which in this case is the concept
horse symbolized as Hx. The result is
that the whole sentence ‘Horses exist’ can be symbolized as Ǝx(Hx).
This also means that the predication of existence Ǝx(...) is a metapredication
expressing a higher-order concept, a concept of a concept, a metaconcept under which
other concepts can fall – in this case (Hx). Thus, Ǝx(Hx) instantiates
the general form Ǝx(Fx), which usually expresses a second-order concept – the concept of existence – applied
to some first-order concept. In a Fregean way of speaking, what this second-order
concept does is to say of the first-order concept that at least one object falls
under it, which also means that the first-order concept is satisfied or fulfilled
by being applicable to at least one thing. So understood, existence is something
objective, since this satisfaction is independent of our cognitively grasping it
as the applicability (and not mere occasional
application) of a concept.
12. Existence as a
property of conceptual rules
These last ways of speaking are
more interesting to me because they could be paraphrased in accordance with my identification
of concepts with senses of predicates, more precisely, with conceptual, semantic-cognitive
ascription rules. This identification shows that existence can be a property of
these conceptual rules, namely, their property of being able to be satisfied, fulfilled,
or simply applicable. For instance, when
I say ‘Horses exist,’ I mean that the conceptual rule expressed by the predicate
‘…is a horse’ is definitely applicable.
More precisely, I mean that this conceptual or ascriptive rule is, if it is
given, effectively applicable in a domain
of external objects. I add the adverb ‘effectively’ or ‘definitely’ to make
it clear that I do not use the word ‘applicable’ in a merely subjunctive sense,
as referring to something that may be
applied, but as referring to something that is
effectively (definitely,
warrantedly) applicable,
which is continuously the case during some period of time (the period
in which the object is said to exist). Moreover, the own ascription rule must
be seen as a possibility, not as an
actuality, since things exist in the independence of their semantic-conceptual
characterizing’s rule existence. Furthermore, the existence or effective applicability
of a semantic-cognitive rule is always considered with regard to a certain domain of entities (a ‘universe of discourse’).
The most fundamental domain is that of the real
empirical world, be it the external (physical) world (Carnap’s thing-world) or
the internal (psychological) world. The statement ‘Horses exist’ applies in the
first domain. The statement ‘Headaches exist’ applies in the second domain. Indeed,
what is normally meant by the predication of existence isn’t the applicability of
a possibly given ascription rule of a general term as a mere possibility entertained
only in our imagination, but also an effective applicability of the rule within
some empirically given domain of entities. Furthermore, this effective applicability
is usually within what we might call its most
proper domain of entities, which in the case of horses is a domain of external,
physical objects, and in the case of headaches is a domain of internal, psychological
states. I consider this point here because there are subsidiary cases, like that
of the Valkyries,[16] whose most proper domain is
mythical – that of Norse mythology.
As one could guess from the last example, there
are other higher-order domains and sub-domains of entities within which we can predicate
existence, even if only in a subsidiary sense. One can say, for instance, that Valkyries’
horses exist in the fictional domain of Wagner’s opera The Valkyrie in the sense that the ascription rules for these fictional
horses are effectively applicable in the fictional domain described in the libretto. There are also cases like the probable
existence of life in other galaxies, which can be in principle verified. Thus, there are imaginary mythological domains, fictional domains in the arts, and domains of imaginable but also plausible entities.
Moreover, there are domains of so-called abstract entities and their various sub-domains,
like the domain of mathematical entities, of logical entities… It is simply a linguistic
fact that we can apply the word ‘existence’ in any of these domains. What I intend
to show in the following is that there is a unifying justification for this.
According to the view I am supporting, to say
that horses, rocks, trees and chairs exist is to confer effective applicability
to the ascription rules of the respective concept-words ‘horse,’ ‘rock,’ ‘tree’
and ‘chair’ in the fundamental domain of material objects belonging to the objectively
real external world. To say that thoughts, joys and pains exist is to ascribe effective
applicability to the ascription rules expressed by the concept-words ‘thought,’
‘joy’ and ‘pain’ in the subjectively real mental domain of entities. And to say
that ‘totalitarianism,’ ‘corruption’ and ‘exploitation’ exist is to affirm the effective
applicability of the ascription rules of these concept-words within the psycho-physical
domain of social entities. The domain of entities to which such concept-words apply
is usually assumed to be respectively physical, psychological and social. As a general
rule, to say that an entity exists is to say that its conceptual rule is effectively
applicable in the already conventionally established most proper domain of application.
Thus, to give examples, the most proper domain of application of the conceptual
word ‘horse’ is the real external world, while the most proper domain of application
of ‘Valkyrie’ is a fictional one. That is, it is normally assumed that the attribution
of existence is made in its most proper domain. But this assumption isn’t necessary
(when I say that there are horses in Wagner’s opera The Valkyrie, the concept horse isn’t being applied in its most proper
domain).
As already noted, a concept – understood as
the semantic-cognitive ascription rule of a predicative expression – is able to
generate dependent, subjective criterial configurations. Thus, to say that a concept-word
is effectively applicable is to say that dependent criterial configurations generated
by its ascription rule are able to be fulfilled by corresponding independent, objective
criterial configurations. These objective criterial configurations (external or
not) can be seen as configurations of tropes usually belonging to more complex tropical
arrangements called facts – another point against Frege that I will explain and
justify in some detail later.
The parallel between the concept of existence
in Frege and the more detailed concept of existence derived from my reconstruction
of concepts as senses of predicates understood as ascription rules is straightforward:
Concept of existence (Frege) =
A second-order concept
that demands for its satisfaction that a first-order concept has at least one object
that falls under it.
Concept of existence
(reconstructed) =
A conceivable higher-order
semantic-cognitive conceptual rule that has a criterion for its (effective) application
that a possibly given lower-order conceptual (or ascriptive) semantic-cognitive
rule is effectively applicable to at least one entity, this entity being a trope
or a configuration of tropes, usually in what is conventionally viewed as its most
proper domain.
In my judgment, the advantage of
this last form of analysis is epistemological: we are better able to scrutinize
the nature of our existence-assignments, as will be shown by the answers to objections.
13. Two naive objections
There are two naïve objections
to the proposed formulation of the
higher-order view of existence, which
offer revealing answers. The first is that the concept of a rule’s effective applicability would be an anthropomorphic one,
while things are said to exist in full independence of cognitive Beings.
However, this objection only arises if we confuse
the concept of effective applicability (within a certain domain) with
the concept of effective application.
The application of a semantic-cognitive rule is an act or a series of acts that
are essentially mental, though often also inevitably sensorimotor, resulting in
judgments. The application of the conceptual rule for the identification of the
planet Venus, for instance, really demands the existence of cognitive Beings able
to perform the application. Our judgment that the Moon circles the Earth depends
on the experience of the application of a verifiability rule for the existence of
this fact by ourselves or by someone who testifies to its application. On the other
hand, the concept of effective applicability of a possible rule is not anthropomorphic.
Even if there were no cognitive Beings able to apply the identification rule for
the concept Venus, this planet would continue to exist, since if the ascription
rule for the identification of Venus existed, it would still be effectively applicable
to this object in its proper domain. The rule would still be applicable, even if
no one had ever applied or even conceived it! The rule would be effectively applicable
in a universe without any cognitive being able to conceive it, since all that is
required is that if the rule existed,
it would be effectively applicable. Thus, there is no doubt that the concept of
effective applicability, as I understand it, isn’t anthropomorphic.
This answer makes it easier to refute a second
naïve objection. This objection could easily be made by proponents of the idea that
existence is a property of things instead of concepts. According to it, if existence
is a property of conceptual rules, then it has nothing to do with the objects that
fall under these concepts: existence seems to be something floating above things
that are said to exist. However,
this seems odd, since intuitively we think that existence must in some way belong to entities that
we believe
exist!
The answer to this objection is that there
is no contradiction between being a higher-order property of an entity and belonging
to this entity. We make this clear by inverting the form of exposition. We can not
only say that some possible ascription rules have the property of being effectively
applicable to tropical properties belonging to a certain domain, but we can also
say that some tropical properties of a domain, the real ones, have the property
of having their own ascription rules effectively applicable to them, meaning by this that these entities exist
in their most proper domain. That is, when we say that kinds of objects such
as horses exist, we also mean that at least one of these conceivable countable kinds
of objects has the higher-order property or
trope of having its ascription rule effectively applicable to it. In other words,
we mean that at least one horse has the meta-property of existing in the actual external world as
part of it, and that this meta-property is also
a property of the kind of animal – even if of a second-order – since it is a
property-property at the level of the object’s ascription rule, belonging to
the object but not intrinsic to it.
In still other words, according to the higher-order
view of existence, the red trope of a couch in front of me exists only insofar
as this object (the couch) has the property of falling under the concept
of being red in the Fregean way of speaking. But in a more natural way, we can say
that the trope of redness of the indicated couch exists in the sense that the ascription
rule of the concept-word ‘red’ has the meta-property of being effectively applicable to the couch’s
trope of redness. Even in a world where this ascription rule does not instantiate,
for instance, a world without cognitive Beings to think and apply the rule, this
rule (understood as possibilia) would
remain effectively applicable, because we know that if this rule were conceived,
it would be effectively applicable. (Since the rule only instantiates in minds,
the rule is in this case only a possibility; but even if the rule actually does
not exist, the effective applicability of
the possible rule actually exists as a higher-order dispositional trope). However,
this also means that the couch’s trope of redness secondarily owns the meta-property of the effective applicability of its ascription
rule to it – it owns this property-property dispositionally. That is, since the
property of existence is the ascription rule’s property of being effectively applicable
to the trope of redness located on the surface of the couch, that property of the ascription rule is a meta-property of this trope of redness. It is so because,
through the ascription rule, this property belongs indirectly but dispositionally to the
trope of redness belonging to the real empirical world. Finally, the higher-order
property of existence or effective applicability of the rule must be where the rule
is, that is, it must be spatiotemporally located, being, therefore, a trope. Existence
doesn’t need to be an exception to our all-embracing trope ontology.
Considering that the meta-rule of existence
is a trope that also applies to the trope, even if in a subordinate way, one could
still ask: how would it be possible in the case of a possible world where there is no cognitive being able
to think this cognitive-semantic rule? The answer is: the property of having the
rule effectively applicable to it is a dispositional
and not an actual property. In a similar way as an object is only dispositionally
green at night when colors cannot be seen, the existence of an object will remain
as a disposition, independently of the existence of cognitive beings able to
identify existence by the application of conceptual rules.
Summarizing: it is a peculiar feature of the
concept of existence (and certainly of some other concepts) that, being owned by
a first-order concept effectively applicable to some entity, it must also be owned
by some entity belonging to the chosen domain of entities without being a proper
constituent of this entity.
14. Existence attributed
to objects
The idea that existence is a property
of concepts concerns not only what is meant by general terms, but also by singular
terms, since both kinds of terms express conceptual senses,
and their references can be said to exist. Since singular terms can be generally
divided into proper names, definite descriptions, and indexicals, I will briefly
consider each of them, beginning with definite descriptions.
Consider as an example the following definite
description: ‘the inventor of the Maieutic’. Applying the logical device to treat
some descriptions by replacing them with a predicate, we symbolize the predicate
‘the inventor of Maieutic’ with M, so that the statement ‘The inventor of the Maieutic
existed’ can be analyzed as:
Ǝx [Mx & (y) (My → y = x)].[17]
In this way, we are affirming the
existence of at least one and not more than one inventor of the Maieutic. This means
that the ascription rule that constitutes the concept (the sense) expressed by the
predicate ‘…is the inventor of the Maieutic’
has the property of being effectively applicable
to only one human being, namely, Socrates, reducing the domain of application
to only one member. This is the same as attributing existence to the inventor of
the Maieutic.[18]
Consider now the case of proper names. As we
have seen, they should also have senses in the form of identification rules. Considering
existence as the effective applicability of a possible semantic-conceptual rule
in a chosen domain, the existence of the object referred to by a proper name should
be established by the effective applicability of its possible identification rule,
primarily in a proper contextualized domain of the external world.
Although this issue cannot be properly addressed
without a deeper investigation of the nature of proper names, we can start by applying
the Fregean-Russellian formal device to the foregoing view. In order to do this,
we transform proper names into predicative expressions applied to only one particular,
showing then that the senses of names themselves can be reduced to the conceptual
senses of predicative terms. A first step in the attempt to arrive at this is to
transform the proper name into a predicate. Thus, ‘Socrates’ in ‘Socrates exists’
can be transformed into a predicate in the sentence ‘There is something that socratizes,’
or ‘Ǝx(x socratizes).’[19] Taken literally, this suggestion
is not only linguistically deplorable, but also formally
deficient, since it leaves open the possibility that there is more than one Socrates.
Nevertheless, I think that ‘Ǝx(x
socratizes)’ points in the right direction by suggesting that the existence of a
name’s bearer may be asserted by means of the conceptual senses of predicative terms.
After all, the verb ‘to socratize’ can be seen as a kind of abbreviation of the
predicative conceptual expressions included in the descriptions supposedly summarized
by the proper name ‘Socrates.’ This is a reasonable strategy, insofar as we take
seriously the bundle theory of proper names that was already fully present in one
way or another in the writings of Frege, Russell, and Wittgenstein, though it has
been made more explicit by P. F. Strawson and particularly John Searle. According
to this theory, the whole sense of a proper name is given by a cluster of definite
descriptions. Having this in mind, we might suggest that the attribution of
existence to Socrates in ‘Ǝx(x socratizes)’ could be seen as an abbreviation
of a set of predicative expressions like:
Ǝx {x is inventor of Maieutic, x
is mentor of Plato... x is Xantippe’s husband}.
Of course, this is still inadequate,
since it not only demands that all predicates must be satisfied, but leaves open
the possibility that these predicates could be applied to more than one object.
However, this fault can easily be remedied by means of the formal device that allows
us to establish a minimum of at least one effectively applicable definite description:
Ǝx {x
and no other person invented the Maieutic, or x and no other person was the
mentor of Plato or… or x and no other person was the husband of Xanthippe}.
Symbolizing the predicates ‘…is
the inventor of the Maieutic’ as P1, ‘…is Plato’s mentor’ as P2,
and ‘…is the husband of Xanthippe’ as Pn, the above sentence can still
be symbolically formulated as follows:
Ǝx [(P1x
& (y1) (P1y1 → (y1 = x)) ˅ (P2x
& (y2) (P2y2 → (y2 = x)) ˅... ˅
(Pnx & (yn) (Pnyn → (yn
= x))]
Here the supposed meaning of a
proper name is disjunctively translated into the conceptual-senses of predicative
expressions such as P1, P2… Pn, which according
to our analysis are nothing but ascription rules expressed by predicates that we
expect to be really applicable to one and the same thing. So analyzed, the attribution
of existence to the object referred to by a proper name is made by saying that its
sense, its identification rule, definitely applies in the assumed context. As this
rule for the identification of a name was here analyzed in terms of a disjunctive
set of rules for the application of predicates that must be applied to the same
individual, we can easily explain existence as follows: The existence of the bearer
of a proper name is the same as the effective applicability of at least one conceptual
rule of a predicative expression to precisely one individual.
Of course, here it could be objected that such
a descriptivist attempt to explain the meaning of a proper name is doomed to failure.
This must be so, not only because the applied formal device is limited, but also
because it amounts to some version of the bundle theory of proper names with its
well-known difficulties, already persuasively
pointed out by Saul Kripke, Keith Donnellan, and others...
However, such a conclusion would be too hasty,
and there are at least three reasons to oppose it. The first is that, contrary to
a current bias, Kripke’s and Donnellan’s objections have
not discredit the most comprehensively developed versions of descriptivist theories,
and some criticism has already been answered with considerable success by John.
R. Searle (1983, Ch. 9). A second reason is that Kripke’s alternative solution,
the causal-historical view, could never be developed beyond a rough sketch.[20] These first two points lead
us to the conclusion that bundle theory hasn’t yet been definitely refuted.[21] Indeed, perhaps it just needs
a stronger defense.
15. The existence
of objects and its identification rules
The third and really conclusive
reason that I can oppose to the anti-descriptivist
view is that the above presented formal analysis is still a crude simplification
when seen from the viewpoint of the new version of the bundle theory of proper names
I have exposed in the Appendix to Chapter I. This version has, as I believe I have demonstrated, a much greater explanatory power
than any previous theory, answering in a more nuanced way the most diverse counter-examples.
Briefly repeating what I said there, my view
is the following. The traditional bundle theory of proper names defended by Frege,
Russell, Wittgenstein, P. F. Strawson, John Searle
and others has a severe limitation that has been overlooked: the bundles
have no internal order. The theory does
not tell us which descriptions or combinations of descriptions are more or less important or even why
some seem to be very important for the application of a name, while others are obviously
irrelevant for it. Definite descriptions are nothing but expressions of rules that
should help us to connect a proper name with its reference. I called them description-rules.
Regarding all this, my question was whether we cannot find the general form of a
rule that we all implicitly know, which if applied to any bundle of descriptions
associated with a proper name enables us to recognize the most relevant ones and
decide in what ways the satisfaction
of these descriptions makes this proper name applicable to some referent.
When searching for the general form of a rule,
the first thing to do is to classify the descriptions. There is a sensible, ordinary-language
method to use in order to begin with: check how encyclopedias treat well-known proper
names. We can thereby easily distinguish fundamental
from merely auxiliary descriptions, which
are accidental. In doing this we see that proper names are first and foremost attached
to two fundamental forms of description, which I call localizing and characterizing
description-rules. Here is how we can define them:
(A)Localizing
description-rule: This is the description that gives the spatiotemporal location and career of the object referred to by the proper name.
(B) Characterizing description-rule: This is the description
that gives the characteristics of the object that we consider the most relevant
to be referred to by the proper name – which gives us the reasons to use the name.
Consider, for instance, the name
‘Adolf Hitler.’ Here is what is said about its bearer in the first paragraph of
a Wikipedia article:
Adolf Hitler (20 April
1889 – 30 April 1945) was born in Braunan an Inn, Austria. Later he was a German
politician and leader of the Nazi Party. He was Chancellor of Germany from 1933
to 1945 and Führer of Nazi Germany from 1934 to 1945. As effective dictator of Nazi
Germany, Hitler was at the center of World War II in Europe and the Holocaust.
It is usual in encyclopedias that
the first thing we find is an abbreviation of the localizing description-rule, followed
by an abbreviation of the characterizing description-rule, stating the reason why
we remember the name. What follows in the Wikipedia
article (as in many others) are more or less relevant details and explanations.
We find a variety of definite and indefinite descriptions that are more or less
irrelevant: accidental, auxiliary descriptions. Examples of them are that Hitler
was ‘the lover of Eva Braun,’ ‘the son of Alois Hitler and Klara Pölzi’[22], ‘the person called “Adolf
Hitler”,’[23]
‘the boy who was sent by his father Alois to the Realschule in Linz in September 1900.’ All this information given by
encyclopedias will also be found in a more extended form in biographies.
You find a similar pattern if you search in
encyclopedias for other proper names like ‘New York,’ ‘USA,’ ‘Eiffel Tower,’ ‘Niagara
Falls,’ or ‘Milky Way.’ Of course,
there are also the proper names of ordinary persons who are not famous enough to
mention in encyclopedias. But the basic mechanism of reference remains the same.
It is not difficult to see that the relevant information is given by their localizing
descriptions and by the usually much more scattered characterizing descriptions.
So, in most cases, if you wish to know who Sam is, you can probably get relevant
information from his identity card, drivers license, employment record, police record
(if any), school reports, club records… and most of all from details given by him, by his family and
friends about his personality, character, education, interests, abilities, relationships,
accomplishments, faults, etc., which are linked together by just one spatiotemporal
career.
Now, my suggestion is that, although a conjunction
of the localizing and the characterizing descriptions isn’t required in any possible
world, as Kripke has clearly shown (1980: 62), an inclusive disjunction of the
two fundamental description-rules must in some degree be satisfied to enable a proper
name to refer to its object in any possible world. John Searle perceived this point
many years ago when he wrote:
…if none of the identifying descriptions believed to
be true of some object proved to be true of some independently located object, then
that object couldn’t be identical to the bearer of the name. (1969: 169)
Indeed, if we discovered records
of a man named Adolf Hitler who was born in Gusental and lived in Austria from 1634
to 1689, worked as a shoemaker and had no political interests, we could safely conclude
that he wasn’t our Adolf since he does not satisfy any of the disjunction.
Moreover, two other complementary conditions
should be added. First, a condition of sufficiency
that must be satisfied: the disjunction of these two fundamental descriptions
must be at least sufficiently satisfied in order to enable a proper name to refer
to its object in any possible world. So, you can imagine a possible world where
there was no World War II but where Adolf Hitler was born on 20 April 1889 in Braunan
an Inn as the son of Alois and Klara Hitler. However,
he had the same career as Adolf Hitler up to the point where he was not rejected
but rather accepted by the Vienna Academy of Fine Arts in 1907, becoming a rich
landscape painter who lived a long uneventful life. In this case, we are inclined
to say that this person is our Hitler
in this counter-factual situation, although
he satisfies only the localizing description-rule, and even this only partially.
But he already satisfies the
inclusive disjunction sufficiently.
The second important condition is that of predominance, demanding that a possible
bearer of a proper name should satisfy fundamental descriptions in a more complete
manner than any other competitor in a possible world, since by definition the bearer
of a proper name cannot be more than just one specified object. Thus, suppose that
in a very similar possible world there were twins Adolf and Rudolf Hitler, both
born on… 20 April 1889… but only Rudolf went to Berlin, served in World War I and
later headed the Nazi Party, starting World War II and the Holocaust, while Adolf
became a farmer in his native Austria. We would choose Rudolf as the true Hitler,
despite his different name, since Rudolf satisfies the disjunction of conditions
belonging to the identification rule for our Adolf in a much stronger way than the
name of his twin brother presented by the auxiliary description ‘the person called
“Adolf Hitler”.’ This shows once more the low relevance of auxiliary descriptions.
Finally, it is important to add that the object
of reference belongs to the nearest
relevant class ‘C’ that does not mix with the contents made explicit in the localizing
condition (here, not being a politician, but being a human being).
Bringing all this together, we are able to
propose the following general form of any identification rule for proper
names, a form that must be satisfied by any bundle of descriptions associated by
the linguistic community with a given proper name:
General form of the identification rule for proper names:
A proper name called
‘N’ has a bearer
iff
it is something that
belongs to the nearest relevant class of referents C, so that more than any other entity of the kind C
it sufficiently satisfies at least the
conditions set by:
(A) its localizing description-rule,
and/or
(B) its characterizing
description-rule.
(Auxiliary descriptions
can be added as helpful symptoms for the identification[24]).
Now we can apply this form to any
well-known bundle of descriptions that we associate with a proper name in order
to have its identification rule. When
we link the general rule form with the bundle of descriptions associated with the
proper name ‘Adolf Hitler,’ we get the following identification rule for this person:
The proper
name ‘Adolf Hitler’ has a bearer
iff
the bearer is something that belongs to the
class of human beings, so that sufficiently
and more than any other human being he satisfies the following inclusive
disjunction of conditions:
(A)being born on 20 April 1889 in Braunan an Inn…
living the last part of his life in Germany… dying on 30 April 1945 in Berlin, and/or
(B) being the leader of the Nazi Party… dictator
of Nazi Germany from 1934 to 1945… the person most responsible for World War II
and the Holocaust.
(He would very probably also satisfy helpful
auxiliary descriptions like being ‘the lover of Eva Braun,’ ‘the person called “Adolf
Hitler”,’ etc.)
This summarized identification
rule gives us the core meaning of the
proper name ‘Adolf Hitler.’ If we try to imagine an Adolf Hitler who does not minimally
satisfy the fundamental localizing and/or characterizing conditions, we see that
this is impossible. This was the case of the Adolf Hitler born in Gusental in 1634,
who was a peaceful shoemaker and had nothing to do with politics. Surely, he could
not be the person in a political socio-historical context whom we always mean by
the name ‘Adolf Hitler,’ but someone else with the same name.
This example
also outlines the lack of relevance of auxiliary descriptions. Suppose that
the Adolf Hitler born in Gusental in 1634 satisfies many of the best-known auxiliary
descriptions: he was the lover of an Eva Braun, he was the son of an Alois Hitler
and a Klara Pölzi, the person
called ‘Adolf Hitler,’ the boy who was sent by his father Alois to the Realschule in Linz… The feeling elicited
by these strange discoveries would be of deep puzzlement, not persuasion. For his
Eva Braun could not be the well-known Eva Braun who also committed suicide in the
Bunker… and even that his parents had
the same name as those of the infamous Adolf Hitler would be merely a remarkable
coincidence… (He could not, it is true, satisfy the description ‘the author of Mein Kampf ’; however, more than an auxiliary
description, this is already part of the full characterizing description of our
Adolf Hitler.) Anyway, at no point will this change our belief that he is not the person we are trying to identify.
Since so understood the identification rule
simply defines which object among all others
owns the proper name by establishing the definitional criteria for identifying the proper name’s bearer in any possible world, it unavoidably also applies in any possible world where the name’s bearer exists, satisfying the fundamental
requirement of the Kripkean definition of a rigid
designator (1980: 48). The individually
taken definite descriptions belonging to the bundle, particularly the auxiliary
ones, on the other hand, being only loosely
associated with the identification rule, can refer to other objects in different
possible worlds and are therefore only accidental
or flaccid designators.[25]
Moreover, one can insert a name correctly in
a sufficiently vague discourse without knowing more than auxiliary and indefinite
descriptions, even when they are wrong, as Kripke realized. This is the case at
least insofar as these descriptions
are convergent (rightly classified), making
in this way what we should call a parasitical
reference, which can be helpful in several
ways. For instance, if someone already knows that Hitler was ‘some dictator’ or
erroneously thinks that he was ‘a military general,’ this person already classifies
him correctly as a man of power can already apply the name correctly in sufficiently
vague contexts and possibly be corrected and learn more about him.
Now, the existence of an object referred to
by a proper name is the effective applicability of what can be called the identification rule of the proper name in
its (in most cases) proper contextual domain. We know that Hitler existed because
we know that his identification rule was effectively applied, hence applicable, in the political-historical context of Europe
in the first half of the twentieth century. Moreover, what allows us to say
that the bearer of the proper name ‘Hitler’ exists is that the property-tropes
that belong to this object satisfy an
identification rule that by this reason has the property of being effectively applicable
to it, a property that is actual if the rule is instantiated in some mind, but
that would be only potential if the rule were never instantiated in any mind (what
is almost impossible to imagine in the present case, but would be easily
imaginable concerning an object like a primitive animal living in a distant
planet.) This property of the potentially existing identification rule is a
higher-order property of the object, endowing it with existence in the real
world and not as something only conceivable.
16. Existence of spatiotemporal
locations: indexicals
Finally, there is the problem of
the application of the proposed analysis of existence to the reference of those
singular terms that change their reference according to the context: the indexicals.
I will consider them only very briefly. Take simple statements with indexicals as
(pointing) ‘There is a raven,’
‘Here is cold,’ ‘It rained yesterday,’ ‘I am tired,’ ‘I am here now’... The indexicals minimal
task is to indicate some spatiotemporal location relative to the speaker. Thus,
‘here’ points to the place where the speaker is, ‘now’ to the moment when the
speaker speaks, ‘yesterday’ to a period of time, the day before the day of the speaker’s
utterance… And regarding indexicals like ‘I,’ ‘she,’ ‘he,’ ‘they,’ there is
more to say than just this. Surely, these personal pronouns have more semantic content
than just a plain spatiotemporal
location, but this does not matter to us now.
Consider now the indexical statement ‘There is a raven,’ said when one found only
one raven there. How should we analyze it? Of course, we can transform ‘There’
in the definite description ‘the spatiotemporal location pointed to (or contextually
shown) by the speaker when he utters the word,’ which expresses a one-foot
localizing identification rule followed by the countable predicate, the sortal
‘…is a raven’ with its ascription rule. But in order to show our existential
commitment, we need more. We need to analyze the definite description replacing
the indicated spatiotemporal location by the predicate ‘…is in time t and place
p’ symbolized by L, replacing then the predicate ‘…is a raven’ with the symbol R.
With help of this we can symbolize ‘There is a raven’ as Ǝx [(Lx & Rx) & (y) ((Ly & Ry) → y
= x)], which means: ‘There is precisely
one x that is in L and is an R.’ Although the location L figures here as a predicate,
the condition of unity (any y = x) makes it a singularized spatiotemporal
location supposedly also analyzable in terms of tropes (See Appendix to Chapter III, sec. 3).
There is another common way to expose our
existential commitment in indexical statements. It is when we add to them a sortal
predicate, as in ‘that raven there’ in the sentence ‘That raven there is flying’
or ‘this chair’ in the sentence ‘This chair is comfortable.’ In these cases, we
consider the phrases ‘that raven there’ and ‘this chair’ as referring to only one
specific object, distinguishing it from all others. Hence, these phrases work as singular terms and must be analyzed as
expressing identification rules. Replacing ‘…is a raven there’ with R and ‘…is flying’
with F, we can also formalize it as the existential statement Ǝx
[Rx & (y) (Ry → y = x)
& Fx].
Indexical statements are important because
when we use them the language, so to speak, ‘touches’ the world, which makes indexicals
the indispensable roots of reference. Because of this, although the sense still
determines its reference, we can find here a double direction of fit. First, with
the help of our sensory cognitions, we create the identification rule for the indexical
that is for the first time used in a determinate context. Once formed, this identification
rule (a Fregean sense) determines the spatiotemporal location, often together with
the kind of object characterized by the sortal. Now, this new identification rule
can be so established that it can be reapplied (not only later, but immediately
thereafter), soon forgotten, or
maybe interpersonally conventionalized by association with a non-indexical singular
term of our language, normally a definite description. To this description,
others can be later joined, building that bundle of descriptions able to flexibilize
the referential work to many diverse circumstances which is typically abbreviated
as a proper name.
17. Advantages of the
higher-order view of existence
There are several advantages in
conceiving existence as a higher-order property, that is, as a higher-order trope.
One is that it gives a straightforward answer to what seems odd in the traditional
forms of the ontological proof of God’s existence. So, according to Descartes, once
we accept the definition of God (1) as the being with all perfections, and that
(2) existence is a perfection, we must
conclude (3) that God exists (1978, V: 65). But if existence is a (tropical) meta-property of objects and not a proper intrinsic first-order
tropical-property constitutive of them, differing in this way from perfections like
infinite goodness, omniscience, and omnipresence, which should be intrinsic properties
of God, the ontological proof is doomed to failure (Cf. Frege 1874, sec. 53).
However, the greatest advantage of conceiving
existence as a higher-order property is that we will not have
problems
with the denial of existence. Suppose
that existence were a first-order property of an object. In a sentence like ‘Vulcan does not exist,’ the negation
of existence should then be applied to the object
itself, and we would first have to identify the object in order to deny that it
has the property, the trope of existence. That is, if in order to identify an object, we first had to admit that it exists, we would be caught in a contradiction:
we would have to admit the existence of Vulcan in order to deny its existence.
According to our Fregean view, this contradictory
conclusion isn’t necessary, because all we do by denying the existence of Vulcan
is to assert that the ascription
rule that forms the concept of Vulcan doesn’t have the meta-property of being effectively
applicable in its proper contextualized domain of physical objects. Only to
illustrate the point, we could analyze the sentence ‘Vulcan does not exist’ as a
shorthand way of saying:
~Ǝx [(x is a small planet orbiting
the Sun between Mercury and
the Sun) & (y) (if y is a small planet orbiting the Sun between Mercury and the Sun, then
y = x)].[26]
What belongs to the scope of ‘~Ǝx’
are concepts constitutive of the identification rule, which in this illustration
consists of an ascription rule for a predicate that can be applied to only one and the same object. What ‘~Ǝx’ does is just
to deny that this identification
rule has the property of being effectively
applicable to the corresponding physical object, which is to deny that an object
existing only in our minds has the (meta-)property of also existing in reality.
18. Ubiquity of existence
The understanding of existence
as the effective applicability of (semantic-cognitive) conceptual rules allows us
to explain the almost unlimited extensions in the application of this concept. Why
given that existence is primarily attributed to properties and objects of the outside
world or of psychological states, are we also allowed to say that supposed entities
like hypothetical and fictional ones exist? Some believe that even contradictory objects exist. We
can even say that everything exists,
including all that can be conceived – at least as something that can be conceived.
And even of existence itself,
it can be said that it exists. Indeed, it seems that in one way or another everything exists. How can this be possible?
Concerning supposed entities, we need to distinguish
at least two kinds: hypothetical entities
that experience hasn’t yet shown to exist or has shown not to exist, and imaginary (including fictional) entities.
Beginning with the first group, it is clear that we can find a sense in which they
exist. Although the planet Vulcan has been shown not to exist in the real external
world, its most proper domain, it surely has existed in the domain of the minds
of many astronomers in the past who searched for it, as a hypothetical object… and
it still exists in our minds, as a merely imaginary object.
For Frege,
this would be a problem. But this is no problem for our proposed view because our
identification rules can also have the existence-endowing property of being applicable,
at least partially, in imagination, that is, only in the dependent domain of conceivable
things that we consider as possible or even plausible candidates for existence in
the external world. If I imagine the hypothetical planet Vulcan orbiting the Sun,
I apply the identification rule for that proper name (even if in a vague, sketchy,
deficient way) to a merely conceivable state of affairs. Indeed, the French astronomer
Le Verrier, who first named the planet, even had a precise identification rule according
to which Vulcan should be a small planet orbiting close to the Sun at a distance
of 21 million km, which he mathematically calculated in order to explain by means
of Newtonian laws the perihelion precession of Mercury’s orbit. He applied this
rule in the domain of what is conceivable, which means that Vulcan ‘existed’ in
the restricted domain of the imagination of Le Verrier and other astronomers in his time, though not in its most
proper domain – that of a concrete object, a planet belonging to the external world.
Consider now the case of purely fictional entities.
Ivan is a character in Dostoyevsky’s philosophical novel The Brothers Karamazov. He never existed in the real world; but he can
be said to exist in the fictional world created in this novel, which is from the
start fictional. In this domain, Ivan is the son of Fyodor Pavlovich and has two
brothers, Dimitri and Alyosha. Ivan is a cerebral as much as a weak character, taking
refuge from the inevitable confrontations of life in contemplation and inaction
and creating resentful justifications for this; in the end, under the weight of
his own conflicts, he descends into madness. These and other elements form parts
of the rule for Ivan’s identification. We say that he exists in the story, insofar
as this rule is effectively applicable only to him within this proper fictional
domain. Differing from the case of hypotheses,
existence in a fictional world excludes from the start existence in the real world.
That Ivan said to Alyosha: ‘let the worms devour one another’ is true in its fictional
domain, as this statement is really made in the novel. But this utterance has no
existence in the domain of the real external world, where it would be a displaced
truth-bearer since the novel was not written to fit into it.
Saul Kripke gave examples of cases of fictional-fictional
characters like Gonzago (2013: 250), who is a personage in Shakespeare’s Hamlet
as a fictional character created by Hamlet in his play within a play ‘The Murder
of Gonzago.’ There is a hierarchy here. We may say that Gonzago exists in a third-order
domain of Hamlet’s play, requiring the effective applicability of a proper identification
rule in this same domain. This third-order domain is supported by the existence
of the plot of the fictional play Hamlet, forming a second-order domain. This play is in turn supported
by the identification of some writer and writings in the first-order domain of our
self-sustaining fundamental real empirical world.
As with other merely imaginary entities like
winged horses and unicorns, existence is here affirmed within a domain that is dependent, derivative or extended (Kripke 2013: 81), being supported
by the fundamental form of existence, which concerns the effective applicability
of cognitive rules in the domain of the real
external (physical) or internal (psychological) world. Existence in these forms
of usage is parasitic to the fundamental
sense, though retaining its basic features (also Searle 1969: 78-9). In traditional
philosophy, it was common to use the word ‘being’ instead of ‘existence’ for merely
conceived existence. But I suspect
that the
real intention was often to underline the importance of conceived entities, underplaying
or obstructing its derivative, parasitic character.
What about the attribution of existence to
contradictory imaginative conceptions like that of a round square? This case seems
really too hard to accept. We cannot combine the rule of identification of the square
with the rule of identification of a circle so
that both can identify one and the same thing, since they are from the start incompatible.
We cannot do this even in our imagination. Because of this impossibility, we must
recognize that in a literal sense a round square cannot reasonably exist: we cannot
have a contradictory combination of conceptual rules, because it cannot form a possibly
applicable rule combination. Since conceptual ascription rules are what constitute
their cognitive meanings, this conclusion agrees with our strongest intuition: contradictions
do not exist because they lack cognitive meaning.[27]
Finally, what about existence? Can we say that
existence itself exists? Surely, we know that existence exists in the sense that
we know that the concept-word ‘existence’ is effectively applicable to the property
of effective applicability of conceptual rules in the most diverse domains, telling
us that this property of effective applicability exists. This means that existence
exists in the sense that we can build a meta-meta-rule of existence, whose criterion
of application is the effective applicability of our metaconceptual rules made for
the attribution of existence as the property of effective applicability of lower-order
conceptual rules. Since there are meta-conceptual rules of existence which are effectively
applicable (since entities belonging to their varied domains exist), the meta-meta-rule
– which demands the effective applicability of meta-rules attributing effective
applicability to first-order conceptual rules – is also effectively applicable.
Consequently, it is safe to conclude that existence itself exists. Well, then, does
the existence of existence also exist? Surely: since the meta-meta-rule of existence
is effectively applicable to meta-rules of existence by saying that the latter are
effectively applicable to the first order conceptual rules, insofar as the latter
ones are effectively applicable, we can conclude that a meta-meta-meta-rule of existence
(affirming the existence of existence in itself) is also effectively applicable
to the meta-meta-rule of existence, making the latter consequently existent. Of
course, one can continue acknowledging the existence of the existence of existence
and so on, in an infinite regress, which is virtuous since it can always be stopped.
19. Answering some
final objections
According to many present theorists,
existence is a first-order predicate. A statement like ‘Horses exist’ should be
analyzed in a form similar to ‘Horses are animals.’ Since they have developed objections
against the traditional second-order view, I will answer at least some of them,
as they were formulated by Collin McGinn (2000b: 21-30). The answers can be helpful
in clarifying my own standpoint.
The first one is against Russell’s proposal
that to say something exists is to say that a propositional function – a property,
a concept – is true for at least one instance. Roughly stated, the objection is
that for one object to instantiate a property
this object must already exist, an admission that would make Russell’s view circular,
since it must already presuppose the existence of objects instantiating the property.
For instance, if ‘Mars is a planet’ is true, it presupposes the existence of the
planet Mars to instantiate the property expressed by ‘…is a planet’ in order to
make the sentence true. Summarizing, there must already be existent objects in order
to instantiate the properties ascribed to them by our conceptual words.
This objection works insofar as one holds a
Kripkean view of objects bearing proper names, since for him they cannot be defined
by their own properties (1980: 52). Once we have analyzed an object as a widely
accessible cluster of tropes displaying compresence, the objection appears to us
in a different form. Since not only the ascriptive rules of predicative expressions,
but also the identification rules of nominal terms are for us conceptual rules,
our position should be generally stated as saying that existence is the effective
applicability of any semantic-cognitive rules in some chosen domain or context.
However, since these rules also apply to objects as compresent clusters of tropes,
this means we cannot conceive any object as being given – that is, as existing –
without simultaneously conceiving its
identification rule as effectively applicable to it. Thus, for instance, the existence
of a concrete object like the planet Mars is nothing but the effective applicability
of its identification rule in its proper astronomical context. This means that we
cannot separate the existence of the object in its proper context from the effective
applicability of its identification rule in the same context, since this is what
warrants the object’s existence. Now, if we assume that the attribution of truth
to a singular predicative statement results from the applicability of the identification
rule added to the applicability of the ascription rule, the attribution of properties
and the admission of the object’s existence are conceptually correlative and cognitively simultaneous. Moreover, as
the truth follows from the combined application of the first two rules, it is wrong
to insist that the attribution
of truth requires the attribution of any property prior to the attribution of existence
to the trope-property and the object as a cluster of trope-properties. The conclusion
is that the flaw in McGinn’s objection lies in the assumption that we can separate
the instantiation of a property by an object from the attribution of existence to
this same object.
Now to the second of McGinn’s objections: uninstantiated
properties are said to exist. But in order to exist, an uninstantiated property must fall under a higher-order
property attributing its existence. This higher-order property must also exist,
which means it must fall under a still higher-order property and so on infinitely.
Consequently, the attribution of existence as a higher-order property is impossible,
because it requires an infinite regress of properties to allow the attribution of
existence.
My answer is that I agree (partially) with
the diagnosis, but not with the prognosis. The effective applicability of a semantic-cognitive
(conceptual) rule in its most proper domain not only endows its reference with existence,
but is in itself a second-order property or trope that can also be said to exist.
And furthermore, a semantic-cognitive
rule that is only imaginatively applicable not only endows its reference with existence
in an imaginary domain, but can also
be said
to exist. The trope-property of existence exists, which means that we can say that
the second-order property of effective applicability of a conceptual rule can be
the object of a third-order rule predicating its effective applicability, and so
on indefinitely. This, of course, leads to an infinite regress. However, it is a
virtuous infinite regress, since the applicability
of a conceptual rule such as existence is already
warranted by the application to it of a higher-order rule, and we don’t need to
bother with all the unlimited further applicabilities of applicabilities or existences
of existences that the first existence-endowing rule can generate. The mark of a
virtuous regress is that we may stop it without
loss when we feel that we do not need further steps to what we intend to explain,
and this is the case here (See Appendix of Chapter III, sec. 2).
The third objection is that there are statements
ascribing existence to particulars, such as ‘Venus exists,’ that resist the traditional
paraphrase. We have already answered this objection in our treatment of proper names
as conceptual identification rules.
But there are other objections. Consider the
statement ‘Something exists.’ Although this is a true statement, McGinn believes
that it is not paraphrasable in terms of the higher-order view, since there is no
property to be instantiated here, and if we try to translate into the standard form
we get the gibberish ‘Ǝx(…x).’
The answer to this objection is too easy. What
‘Something exists’ means is that there is at least one trope or tropical construction
out of tropes that exists without a further determination on our side. That is,
we can say that there is some semantic-conceptual rule that is applicable to some
domain of entities, even if this rule remains unspecified. This possibility
is even shown by our logical symbolism on an elementary level, since we can symbolize
an undetermined property such as, say, F. In this way we can translate
‘Something exists’ symbolically as Ǝx(Fx). But there is nothing wrong with Ǝx(Fx). Paralleling existential universalization, we
can reach this result by considering singular existential statements like ‘Venus
exists.’ So, calling Venus V, if it is true that ‘Ǝx(Vx)’ this implies that some property
exists or ‘Ǝx(Fx), namely, that some
conceptual rule is effectively applicable. This assumption of cognitively undetermined
properties is harmless.
McGuinn reminds us that there are also more
complicated statements that seem to resist a higher-order understanding of existence,
like:
1.
Some cities are purely imaginary.
2.
Some of the things you are talking about do not exist.
3.
There are things that do not exist…
Nonetheless,
we can easily explain the predication of existence in such statements, insofar as
we do not confuse the domains of application of the semantic-cognitive rules involved.
Thus, statement (1) means that some cities
that exist in the imaginary domain exist only in this domain. Hence, the effective
applicability of rules allowing us to identify the imaginary cities of Chloe and
Valdrada in the contextual domain of the book The Invisible Cities is sufficient
for the attribution of existence to them in that purely fictional context. Statement
(2) means that some things you are talking about exist only in imaginary domains,
but not in the external world, that is, there are identification rules that are
effectively applicable only in the unreal domain of one’s own discourse. For instance,
the identification rule of the name ‘Vulcan’ in the statement ‘Vulcan is red’ is
only applicable in the speaker’s (or hearer’s) imagination. Finally, statement (3)
means that there is at least one thing that exists only in the mind but not in external
reality. Indeed, it seems obvious that the identification rule for some objects
and therefore for at least one of them, though effectively applicable
in an imaginary, only conceivable domain, isn’t effectively applicable in the domain
of external reality.
The last of McGinn’s objections is that according
to the higher-order view, nothing can exist without falling under some property
or other, which rules out the existence of a thing that has no properties – a ‘bare
existent.’ However, our empiricist commitment makes us see this not as a weakness,
but rather as a further anti-metaphysical advantage of our understanding of the
higher-order view.
20. Reference again:
a metaphysical excurse (Mill)
It is instructive to consider what
happens when we compare the famous phenomenalist view of J. S. Mill, according to
which ‘matter’ or ‘substance’ is nothing but ‘permanent possibilities of sensation’
with our view of existence in terms of the effective applicability of conceptual
rules. The results will be no less speculative than Mill’s phenomenalism, but they
may be telling.
Mill’s great epistemological question was:
If all that is experientially given to us are sensory phenomena, how can we justify
our belief in the existence of an external world, an objective world constituted
by substance or matter? – An external world that can exist even when there is no
observer at all to perceive it?
Mill’s answer to the question was a development
of Berkeley’s unofficial view, according to which things that we know to exist when
we are not perceiving must be nothing more than things that we are certain we would
perceive under suitable circumstances.[28] As Berkeley wrote:
Existere is percipi or percipere… The horse is in
the stable, the books are in the study as before. (1707-8, Notebok A, 429)
The table I write on, I say, exists, that is, I see
and feel it; and if I were out of my study I should say it existed – meaning thereby
that if I was in my study I might perceive it, or that some other spirit actually
does perceive it. (1710, I, sec 3)
According to this view, esse
is not only percipi, but also percipi possi. In a more explicit manner,
what Mill suggests is that:
Matter or substance is not made up of actual sensations,
but of groups of permanent (or guaranteed or certified) possibilities
of sensation.
Mill justifies his identification
of matter or substance with permanent possibilities of sensation in the following
way. First, these possibilities of sensation are conditional certainties: they
are not mere epistemic possibilities, but firm conditional expectations that are
in direct or indirect ways based on experience. They are permanent in the sense that, once suitable circumstances are given,
they would always be experienced insofar as they are said to exist. And they are
guaranteed or certified in the sense that we have good reasons – observational or
not – to have a firm expectation that under suitable circumstances they will be
experienced again and again. This does not mean that the groups of permanent possibilities
of sensations would depend for their existence on our past experience of them, because
if that were so, they could not exist without us as subjects of knowledge, and we
would fall like Berkeley into some radical form of idealism (Berkeley 1710, 1713).
This was not Mill’s intention. As he explains:
We mean [by permanent possibilities of sensation]…
something which exists when we are not thinking of it; which existed before we have
ever thought of it, and would exist if we were annihilated; and further that things
exist that we never saw, touched or otherwise perceived, and things which never
have been perceived by man. (1979, X: 178-177)
Thus, it is clear that Mill wished
to avoid idealism: the permanent possibilities of sensations would exist even if
cognitive beings able to perceive them never existed.
These permanent possibilities are for Mill
objective, differing from our actual constantly
changing sensations, which are subjective. They are objective because they are grounded,
he thinks, in our common public world, which makes us able to interpersonally agree
on their existence. For him, even if different persons cannot have access to the
same sensations, they can have access to the
same possibilities of sensation. As he writes:
The permanent possibilities are common to us and to our fellow creatures,
the actual sensations are not… The world of possible sensations succeeding one another
according to laws is as much in other beings as it is in me; it has therefore an
existence outside me; it is an external world. (1979, X: 181-2, my italics)
This is in summary Mill’s view
on the nature of matter – a view that always seemed to me as much deeply suggestive
as contentious.
I think there is a serious confusion in Mill’s
view, which can be made clear when we compare his insights with those of Berkeley.
According to the non-official Berkeleyan view, the external world is constituted
by sensations whose experience is continually
(permanently) possible for us, even if we are not there to experience them. But
if this is so, the material objects constituting the external world cannot be reduced
to simple ‘groups of permanent possibilities of sensation,’ for possibilities
as such, permanent or not, cannot be qualitatively distinguished one from the other
in the same way as one material object can be distinguished from another. Material objects can be qualitatively very different
from each other, they are multiple and varied, while possibilities are always the
same, namely, mere possibilities. Consequently, possibilities (of sensations),
permanent or not, cannot be the same as material things. Keeping this in mind, the
only feasible way to express the Berkeleyan insight in Mill’s terminology seems
to me to use it in the characterization of material objects, as follows:
Material objects (or substances) are nothing but multiple and varied groups
of sensations whose effective experience is permanently (or guaranteed or certified
to be) possible.
This would meet the requirement
of multiplicity and diversity proper to material objects and their presentations
because each material object would be constituted by innumerable groups of sensations that under suitable circumstances could always be possibly distinctly
experienced. But if the permanent possibility of sensations is not the material object, what is?
I believe it is a way to point to the external
existence of the material object. This
answer emerges when we consider Mill’s view in the light of my reconstruction of
Frege’s concept of existence, according to which existence is the effective applicability of a conceptual or semantic-cognitive rule. If this is
so, it seems that the permanent (guaranteed, certified) possibility of groups of
sensations could be approximated to the existence
of such groups of sensations and the last ones to material objects; these warranted
groups of sensations would be the same as the criterial configurations warranting
the applicability of the rule. Consider the expressions:
1. Permanent (guaranteed, certified) possibilities
of groups of sensations.
2. Effective experienceability of groups of sensations.
Expressions (1) and (2) say the
same thing in different words. Now, compare them to the following expressions of
existence in our reconstruction of Frege’s view:
3. Effective
applicability of a conceptual rule.
4. Effective
applicability of a conceptual rule to groups of given sensory-perceptual contents.
5. Effective
applicability of a conceptual rule to given (independent) criterial configurations
or tropes.
Although (4) is only a variation
of (3), it seems clear that when we interpret existence as (4) we are saying something
at least equivalent to (2): the effective experienceability of groups of sensations.
Since (2) is only a different way to say (1), the permanent (guaranteed, certified)
possibility can be approximated to existence. One could even suggest:
Existence is the effective
(permanent, guaranteed, certified) possibility
of groups of sensations.
The point in question is made clearer
when we consider the general structure of our conceptual rules of ascription and
identification. We already know that these rules have the form of semantic-criterial
rules that bring us to some usually pre-reflexively achieved semantic cognition,
given by the satisfaction of variable subjective criterial configurations (supposedly)
by means of their match with objective criterial configurations, which should be
nothing but configurations of external tropes. Now, when we interpret these variable
criterial configurations as being the same as Mill’s groups of sensations, as we
have reconstructed them, we can speak of existence as the effective, guaranteed,
certified, permanent possibilities of groups of sensations as consistent with the
effective applicability of a conceptual rule. Here an example can be helpful: In
order to be applied to a real located object, the conceptual rule for the concept
chair demands the satisfaction of criterial
configurations. These criterial configurations are established by the definition
of a chair as a seat with a backrest made for only one person to sit on at a time,
which we could decompose in terms of subjective sensory criterial configurations
that must be satisfied by matching objective criterial configurations or configurations
of given external tropes. But the criterial configurations (the dependent ones,
at least) could be reduced to groups of sensations whose experience is permanently
(guaranteed, certified as) possible.
Now, Mill’s insights can help us deepen our
reconstruction of the Fregean concept of existence. A material object exists only:
(i)
when its conceptual rule is effectively applicable, but
this effective applicability is only the case when
(ii) criteria for the application
of its identification rule can be objectively given to us at least in the form of
groups of what we may call independent, external
contents of sensation whose experience is warranted or permanently possible.
Moreover, as Mill also suggested,
(iii)
this possibility of experience must be (at least in principle
and indirectly) interpersonally accessible by allowing agreement in the description
of the experience;
(iv)
this experience can be more or less direct;
(v) it is (usually) independent
of our will; and
(vi)
it is also experienced as following causal laws regarded
as typical of things belonging to the external world.
It seems that all these things
together contribute to building the condition of an effective application of a semantic-cognitive
rule in the domain of the external world – they are contributing to warrant the
attribution of external existence.
There is, however, an important and seemingly
fatal objection to Mill’s view of matter, which is made more serious by the Berkeleyan
correction I made above.[29] It is that the group of sensations
or configurations of sensory criteria that satisfy a conceptual rule are by their
nature inevitably psychological. It seems clear that even sensations or contents
of sensations that are warranted as permanently possible must be psychological in
a dispositional way. This means that if we follow this path, we end up falling into
some form of Berkeleyan idealism in which there is no objective, external material
world to be contrasted with our subjective world of sensations or sensory criteria.
No really independent non-mental external trope needs to be there to match the apparently
satisfied dependent criterial conditions, as suggested in statement (5). It is true
that, as Mill noted, his possible sensations are independent of our will, that they
follow the regularities of nature, even that they appear to be interpersonally accessible
under circumstances that warrant their experience (under suitable circumstances
they are described as being experienced simultaneously by different subjects, etc.).
However, all these things do not seem to help because of the possibility of
skeptical scenarios: they can all be unwittingly imagined, as in the dreams.
They seem, therefore, insufficient to perform the magic of turning sensations qua sensations into something they aren’t,
namely, supposed elements of a non-mental objective external world of material objects
with their own tropical-properties. This is an important objection, whose answer
will be given only in the final chapter of this book, as a consequence of our discussion
of the adequation theory of truth in its relation to direct realism.
Notwithstanding, I can now anticipate something
of the way I intend to deal with the problem. Having in mind the suggested view
of existence, we can ask: What warrants an object’s external existence or
reality? One answer could be: the joint satisfaction of conditions (i) to (vi) by
(5) and nothing more. This would be all that we need to identify the external
reality with the contents of our experiences, for there is no way to verify whether
or not there is some radical skeptical truth concerning our whole external
world, which under normal circumstances makes radical skeptical doubt senseless.
(Ch. VI, sec. 30)
An associated question is: What is in this
context an external material object? A too daring answer would be: the external object (as it is
thought) must be the identification rule in itself, insofar as it is effectively
applicable; in this way, the multiplicity and diversity of objects would be explained
by the multiplicity and diversity of identification rules... However, this cannot
be, since a semantic-cognitive rule is also something essentially mental, and we
are definitely not what Plato called ‘friends of ideas.’
Looking for a less daring answer, we can suggest
that what we understand as the material object is not the semantic-cognitive rule,
but is supposed to have the same structure as this rule projected in a specular way onto the external world. There is a reason
for this suggestion: It seems that only something with a structure similar to its
semantic-cognitive rule would be able to give unity to the multiple and variable
criterial configurations by means of which external entities are able to give themselves
to us in our experience of them. Figuratively speaking, if the semantic-cognitive
rule has the form of a tree with branches whose ramifications end in criterial conditions
dependent to the rule, then the object of its application, as we believe it to be,
must have the structure of an inverted specular tree with branches whose ramifications
end in independent criterial configurations that (supposedly) should match the corresponding
subjective criterial configurations. Furthermore, these objective criterial configurations
should be nothing but external tropes and constructions out of them (objects, properties, facts). Of course, this
objective structure should be putative, so that the rule could always be improved
or corrected as a response to new information regarding such specular objective
counterparts. (Ch. VI, sec. 34)
21. The reference of
a sentence as its truth-value
Now we leave our speculative excurse
and come back to the more tangible Fregean semantics, considering what he has to
say about the reference of a sentence. Here I have no compliments to make. Frege was the author of the insane idea that the
references of sentences are their truth-values, so that the thoughts expressed by
them should be modes of presentation of truth-values.
How did he reach this strange conclusion? There
are several reasons. First, he notes that sentences are independent, saturated,
closed; they work in ways similar to those of names, and a truth-value is also closed,
since it does not require complementation. Second, he says that the search for truth
is what brings us from sense to reference. Third, he notes that sentences without
reference lack truth-value: ‘Vulcan is a warm planet’ has no reference and for him
no truth-value, since this hypothetical planet has been shown not to exist. Fourth,
he also noted that conforming to the principle of compositionality – according to
which the whole is a function of its
parts –
the reference must be what remains unchanged after we change the senses of a sentence’s
components without changing their references. This is what happens, for instance,
if we replace ‘Napoleon lost the Battle of Waterloo’ with ‘The man of destiny lost
his last battle.’ Since the references of the sentence-components do not change,
the reference of the whole sentence likewise does not change. Moreover, the truth-value
of both sentences remains the same: The Truth. Hence, their reference must be their
truth-value. The conclusion of all this is that in extensional languages the references
of sentences must be their truth-value (1892: 34). For Frege, all true sentences
have only one reference, which is the abstract object The True (das Wahre),
while all false sentences also have only one reference, which is the abstract object
The False (das Falsche).
However, there are a number of well-known embarrassing
objections to Frege’s identification of reference with truth-value that in my opinion
completely disqualify his view. A first objection is that, contrary to any healthy
intuition, Frege’s proposal frontally contradicts the meaning we normally give to
the word ‘reference.’ It is intuitively obvious that the sentence ‘Napoleon was
born on Corsica’ refers to something very different from the sentence ‘2 + 2 = 4,’
even if both are true. Moreover, if you replace ‘Venus is a planet & the Earth
is a planet’ with ‘Mars is a planet &
the Earth is a planet,’ both composite sentences remain true because of the truth
of the partial sentences, but the reference of ‘Venus’ is totally different from
the reference of ‘Mars,’ what runs against the principle of compositionality. Another
objection is that we expect the references of components of our sentences to be
on the same ontological level as the sentences’ references. But for a Fregean, this could not be the
case: the reference of the name ‘Napoleon’ is the Napoleon of flesh and blood, while
the reference of the sentence ‘Napoleon was born on Corsica’ must be the abstract
object called The True. Moreover, Frege’s solution violates his own principle of
compositionality. If the reference of a sentence is its truth-value, it cannot be
established by its parts, since a truth-value has no parts. And even if it had parts,
then all objects referred to by names in true sentences should be parts of The True,
which would hardly make sense. There are also serious
substitutability problems with Frege’s explanation of the references of sentences.
The first is that if all true sentences refer to The True, and the name ‘The True’
also refers to The True, then in the conditional sentence ‘If it rains, then water
falls from the sky,’ we can replace ‘it rains’ with ‘The True.’ But the result will
be the sentence ‘If The True, then water falls from the sky,’ which should be true
but is in fact unintelligible (Black 1954: 235-6). A second and fatal problem
of the kind is that a multitude of obviously false identities between true sentences
should be true. For example, ‘Paris is a city = snow is white’ should be a true assertoric composite sentence, since
the two sentences refer to the same thing: The True. Under critical scrutiny, Frege’s
view shows itself to be hopeless.
The most charitable interpretation is that
Frege uses the word ‘reference’ as truth-value because it is what counts, because
the word Bedeutung (meaning) in German,
more than in English, also means relevance,
pointing to semantic relevance or meaningfulness (Cf. Tugendhat
1992b: 231).[30]
Indeed, truth-value is of decisive relevance for logic, because it is what must
be preserved in valid arguments. The logician does not need to know more than truth-value
regarding the referring function of the sentences he is dealing with in order to
evaluate inferential possibilities.
A main problem with this interpretation is
that it contradicts expected principles
of Frege’s own theory. Since the reference (Bedeutung)
of the parts of a singular sentence (general and singular terms) can be seen as
their references in a literal sense (the concept and the object that can fall under it), truth-value
as relevance satisfies the principle of compositionality in an odd, non-linear form, since relevance
is normally only an adjective
applied to truth-value. This is different from
the principle of compositionality applied to senses in which the whole and
its components are linearly arranged in the same semantic domain. The attempt
to tell us that a reference is mere qualification attributable to it is
equivocal and confusive.
Finally, when we take the truth-value for the
reference of a sentence, this view can be – and in my judgment really has been –
utterly misleading from an epistemological standpoint. Since truth considered as in some way belonging to thought
has nothing to do with anything that can reasonably be understood as the reference
of our statements, calling truth-value ‘the reference’ contributes to placing the relation between language and
the world virtually beyond semantic reach.
22. Logical structure
of facts
The Fregean account of the references
of sentences as their truth-values turns out to be still less acceptable if we consider
that a much more natural alternative is available, which, as Sir Anthony Kenny has
noted, was not even mentioned by Frege (Kenny 2000: 133). This alternative, which
the logical atomism of Wittgenstein and Russell tried to explore, consists in the
appeal to facts. Since it is prima facie much more plausible that the
references of sentences are facts, it is important for us to investigate the logical
structure and ontological nature of facts.
Considering
first the logical structure of facts, a plausible view is that they correspond to
the logical structure of the thoughts representing them, assuming that these thoughts are what declarative
sentences express when logically analyzed, at least in accordance with the context of the linguistic
practices where they occur. Nevertheless, even respecting linguistic practices we
can go further, considering that they are placed within the factual language in
general and accepting a form of atomism in which the bottom line of the analysis
is the exposure of the logical components of what is stated in singular sentences
where we can find identification rules of singular termini associatively used with
ascription rules of predicative expressions. Singular empirical statements such
as ‘Frege has a beard’ and ‘The cat is on the mat’ belong to this bottom line and
respectively represent facts that should
have the logical structure depicted by Fa
and bRc.
Elements a, b and c, as singular terms, refer to individuals constructed as clusters of
appropriate compresent tropes, while F
and R would also be seen as designating
tropes, usually complex tropes forming complex criterial configurations dependent
on the clusters to which they are tied. The ties between b, R and c, and between F and a, in turn, are only
pseudo-relations, since admitting their existence as relational tropes would generate
an inevitable infinite regress. As we already noted, individuals and their property-tropes
are linked by ‘non-relational ties’ without any ontological addition (Cf. Appendix to Chapter III, sec. 1). Indeed,
what could be the relational ties between the application of the ascription rule
of ‘…was bearded’ to Aristotle with the already applied identification rule of Aristotle
in the fact represented by the statement ‘Aristotle was bearded’?
We should also pay attention to the somewhat
trivial rule of analysis according to which we
should not accept singular terms – and even candidates for this function – as components
of complex predicative expressions (I say candidates, intending sentences
like ‘The Minotaur has two horns’; since the horns are individuals, they must
be referred to by singular terms in the completely analyzed sentence). (Cf. IV, sec. 7) Thus, for instance, in a
sentence like ‘Stockholm is the capital of Sweden’ we should not view ‘…is the capital
of Sweden’ as a predicate, since Sweden is a proper name. Also inadequate would
be to analyze ‘the capital of Sweden’ as a definite description contextually referring
to Stockholm in our world, so that the analyzed sentence would have as its relational predicate ‘…is (the
same as)…’ The most appropriate analysis would be to consider ‘…is the capital of…’
as a relational predicate completed by the proper names ‘Stockholm’ and ‘Sweden,’
separating the relational trope
from the compresent bundles of tropes referred to by the proper names. Proper
names are stronger identifiers than definite descriptions and should therefore be
preferentially singled out in the logical analysis of thought.
Furthermore, it also seems possible to analyze
proper names and definite descriptions using Russell’s technique of transforming
them into quantified predicative expressions, insofar as to a limited degree this
device mirrors the neodescriptivist theory of proper names defended in this book,
a similar procedure being possible regarding general terms. Anyway, such sub-sentential
terms normally do not need to be analyzed when our task is to analyze sentences, since they are the proper elements of sentences, except when
they are not what they seem to be, as in
the case of nominalizations.
Finally, we have composite facts
represented by our extensional language, along with the general (universal, existential)
facts to be analyzed as having the same structure of sets (conjunctions, disjunctions)
of singular statements that make up general (universal, existential) statements,
which, as we already noted, can be reduced to associations of singular predicative
and relational statements. (I think that the philosophical problem of a hidden lingua mentis ends up in elements like those briefly pointed out in this section).
23. Ontological nature
of facts
If we accept that the references
of sentence-senses or thoughts are facts, then from an ontological perspective what
empirical sentences represent must be empirical facts, most typically located in
the external world, though possibly also located in the inner mental world. This
assumption speaks for the correspondence or adequation theory of truth, according
to which empirical facts are truth-makers normally seen as complex contingent arrangements
of elements in the world, that is, usually
contingent tropical arrangements
associating tropical individuals and property-tropes.
However,
this assumption conflicts with Frege’s anti-correspondentialist view of truth.
According to him, a fact would simply be a true
thought (1918: 74). Following similar
anti-correspondentialist lines, in a very influential article, P. F. Strawson suggested
that empirical facts are mere ‘pseudo-material correlates of the statement as a
whole’ and not something in the world (1950: 6). According to him, empirical facts,
unlike events or things, are not spatiotemporally localizable (‘the world is the totality
of things, not of facts’). One reason for this is that the description of a fact
usually begins with a that-clause. For instance, I can say ‘the fact
that the book is on the table,’ but not
‘the fact of a book on the table.’ On the other hand, the description of an event
typically lacks a that-clause: I can say ‘the event of a tsunami in Japan,’ but
not properly ‘the event that there was
a Tsunami in Japan.’ Facts are for Strawson what statements (when true) state, not
what statements are about. They are
not, like things or happenings on the surface of the
globe, witnessed or heard or seen, broken or overturned, interrupted or prolonged,
kicked, destroyed, mended or noisy. (1950: 6)
The same is for him the case with
states of affairs and situations. [31] Finally, to give a striking
example, the event of Caesar’s crossing the Rubicon occurred in the year 47 BC, while the fact that he crossed the Rubicon
did not occur in the year
47 BC, but it is still a fact today, since facts simply do not occur (Patzig 1980:
19-20).[32]
An easy way to dispose of this argument could
be the following. We need a word to describe the condition in the world that makes
our thoughts true. The word ‘fact’ is available. So, why don’t we use it stipulatively
in order to designate the truth-maker, whatever condition it is?[33]
However, it seems clear to me that even this
stipulative way to circumvent the problem is avoidable, since it is not difficult
to show that the problem exists only in the imagination of philosophers. To begin
with, of course not everything we may call a ‘fact’ is empirical in the usual sense
of the word. It is hard to assign empirical status to the fact that 2 + 2 = 4, even
if its supposed non-empirical character can be an object of controversy.[34] And we can say ‘It is a fact
that the Sun is not green,’ although this
seems to me only a linguistically modified way to say ‘There is no fact that the Sun is green’ or ‘The
fact that the sun is green does not exist.’ What I want to defend here is that there
is a privileged sense of the word ‘fact’ that involves references to more or less
obvious empirical facts, particularly so-called observational facts, which should
be considered objectively real: they exist in the external world and can be seen
as the ultimate truth-makers of their
statements.
To begin with, it is good to remember that
there is a well-known and very convincing reason to think that facts can be constituents
of the empirical world. This is that many facts are said to act causally. Consider
the following sentences:
(1) The fact that the match was scratched caused
the flame.
(2) Thomas died because of the fact that he forgot
to turn off the gas.
(3) Because of the fact that today is a holiday,
the class will be canceled.
(4) The fact that Caesar crossed the Rubicon had
important historical consequences.
It does not seem possible that
pseudo-material correlates (which I suppose to be abstract contents) can be causally
active in the empirical world, producing these effects.
But conceding the empirical nature of facts (1) to (4) solves the problem in obvious
ways. Scratching a match is a fact-event causing a flame. The situational fact created by Thomas’ forgetting to turn off the gas caused his death.
The fact-circumstance that today is a holiday causes the cancellation of a class.
The fact-event of crossing the Rubicon established a state of affairs that causally determined decisive political changes
in the Roman Empire.
Furthermore, I have a key-argument to regenerate
the idea that empirical facts are correlates of true thoughts, as the classical
correspondence theory of truth has held. According to the view I propose, empirical
facts are contingent tropical arrangements in the external and/or internal world
in general. Similar would be the case with facts apparently as simple as those referred
to by sentences like ‘Frege had a beard,’ ‘The Eiffel Tower is in Paris,’ and also
facts constituted by combinations of such facts.
My argument against Strawson’s opposition between
non-spatiotemporal facts and spatiotemporal events begins by showing that there
is a serious confusion in his argument. He treats facts (as much as states of affairs
and situations) as opposed to events.
His schema is:
FACTS x EVENTS
Pseudo-material Spatiotemporal
correlates phenomena
But this can easily be contested.
We begin to be suspicious when we perceive that every event can be called a fact,
but not every fact can be called an event. For instance: I can replace ‘the event
of the sinking of the Titanic’ with ‘the fact of the sinking of the Titanic,’ but
I cannot replace ‘the fact that Mt. Everest is more than 8,000 m. high’ with ‘the
event of Mt. Everest being more than 8,000 m. high.’ Strawson’s opposition isn’t
symmetrical. Now, since events can be called facts, it is much more reasonable to
consider events as particular kinds of facts than to oppose the two, as Strawson
did. Indeed, my proposal is that the word
‘fact’ is an umbrella term that encompasses events, occurrences, processes,
as much as situations, circumstances, states of affairs, etc. And the reason
for this proposal is that we can call all these things facts, but we cannot call
all these things states of affairs or events. We see that events are sub-types
of facts and that linguists could classify the word ‘event’ as a hyponym of the
word ‘fact.’ Considering things in this way, we can distinguish two great sub-classes
of facts:
1. STATIC FACTS: Can be formal or empirical, the
latter when clearly located in space and time. As a whole, static facts do not change while they last. Typical of
static facts is that the relationships between their tropical components do not
decisively change during the period of their existence. They are truth-makers of
a static kind. And ordinary language has names for them: they are called (with different
semantic nuances) ‘states,’ ‘situations,’ ‘conditions,’ ‘circumstances,’ ‘states
of affairs,’ ‘ways things are,’ etc.
2. DYNAMIC FACTS: These are always empirical. They
change while they last. The relationships
between the elements constitutive of them change decisively during the period of
their existence, so that they have a beginning, followed by some kind of development
that comes to an end after a certain amount of time. We will see that they work
as truth-makers of a dynamic kind. And ordinarily they can be called (with different
semantic nuances) ‘events,’ ‘episodes,’ ‘occurrences,’
‘occasions,’ ‘processes,’ ‘transformations,’ etc.
Facts said to be formal, like the
fact that 7 × 8 = 56, are static in the harmless sense that they do not need to
be considered as spatiotemporally located. They are not of concern to us here. Many
facts are empirical and static, insofar as the relationships between the elements
constitutive of them do not change during their existence. Static facts are usually
called ‘states,’ ‘situations,’ ‘conditions,’ ‘circumstances,’ ‘states of affairs’…
with different nuances of meaning. Examples of static facts are my state of poor health, the situation that I am lying in bed, the circumstance that the airport is closed,
the state of affairs that the Mona Lisa
is in the Louvre or that the Earth orbits the Sun. The Earth’s movement of revolving
around the Sun does not count because it is an internal cyclical relationship that
remains the same during the fact’s existence: as a whole, this state of affairs
does not change while it lasts (although each orbital period counts as an event).
Dynamic facts, on the other hand, can be called
‘events,’ ‘episodes,’ ‘occurrences,’ ‘occasions,’ ‘processes,’… They are defined
by changes in their overall composition and in relations among their elements during
the period of their existence. World War II, viewed a process, for instance, began
with a rapid expansion of the territories dominated by Nazi Germany and was marked
by events like the Battle of Britain, the Battle of Stalingrad and the Normandy
invasion – it had an unforeseeable history. Dynamic facts are usually called events
when their duration is comparatively short, occurrences when their duration isn’t
as short, processes when their duration is longer. Examples of events are an explosion
or a lightning flash in a storm. An example of an occurrence
is a volcanic eruption. The process of global warming is a very slow natural process,
slower than the process of economic globalization. We can predict the stages of
many events and processes, although many are also unpredictable in such a way that
(unlike static facts) we cannot grasp them in their integrity before they end. Important
is to see that all these things can be individually called events, occurrences,
occasions, happenings, processes… and also facts,
since they are all nothing but empirical facts – truth-makers of a dynamic kind.
We are now able to find what seems to be the
real reason why we use a that-clause in the description of facts, but not in the
description of events. When we speak of dynamic facts, we do not use a that-clause.
Thus, we can speak about the event of Caesar’s crossing the Rubicon, but not about
the event that he crossed the Rubicon. We can speak about the process of
climate change, but not about the process that
the climate changes… But this isn’t the case regarding static facts, which are typically
(though not necessarily) described as beginning with that-clauses. So, I can speak about the state of affairs
that my book is on the table or that I am lying on the bed, although I can
also speak about the state of affairs of my book being on the table and of my lying
on the bed. The conclusion is that if that-clauses have some function it is that
of excluding dynamic facts and
emphasizing static facts. Moreover, since the hyperonymic term ‘fact’ can be
applied to both – static facts as much as dynamic facts – it is reasonable to suppose
that this term inherits the property of
being used indifferently, with or without a that-clause. Indeed, you can say, ‘It is a fact that
Mount Vesuvius is located near Naples’ (referring to a state of affairs), as much
as ‘It is a fact that Mount Vesuvius has
erupted’ (referring to an event). And we can also say: ‘Caesar crossing the Rubicon
was an event,’ as much as ‘It is a fact that
Caesar crossed the Rubicon,’ referring less precisely to the event. We can summarize
these relationships in a schema:
(a) Static facts (states of affairs…): can be well
stated with or without a that-clause.
(b) Dynamic facts (events…): cannot be well stated
with a that-clause.
(c) Facts in general: admit both cases, because
being all-embracing they do not differentiate between (a) and (b).
Now, what about the fact that Caesar
crossed the Rubicon? Isn’t this fact timeless? The answer is that this is a good
case of a misleading statement. In most cases, it is not understood as the description
of an event, but as an illustrative way of referring to a static social fact: the state of affairs established by
the movement of Caesar’s army onto Roman territory, violating the law that prohibited
this and forcing the Roman state to declare war against him. Only occasionally is
the phrase ‘crossing the Rubicon’ understood in its literal sense, as the physical
event of crossing the river, which comprises Caesar’s sequential locations in relation
to the river from t1 to tn.
Due to the nature of dynamic facts like events
and processes, we say that they not only are, but also occur in time,
while of static facts we only say that they are located in time while they last. It seems, therefore, that because philosophers
such as Strawson did not realize that events are sub-types of facts, seeing only
that we may say of events that they occur in time, they hastily concluded that only
events (and things) are located in time, opposing them to timeless facts. But that
this isn’t true can be shown even by inter-substitutivity salva veritate:
it is correct to say that the event, the occurrence of Caesar’s crossing the Rubicon,
was a fact and that this fact occurred in 47 BC, as a concrete dynamic fact.
On the other hand, the static social fact, the political state of affairs established
by Caesar’s crossing the river was far more enduring. Being a static fact, it was
the political situation that led, as is
well-known, to the fall of the Republic. However, it seems clear that the state
of affairs brought about by the crossing of the Rubicon was spatially limited to
the Roman Empire and temporally limited to the time from Caesar’s crossing the Rubicon
to his coronation as Caesar and up until his assassination.
It was not something that existed in Greenland or that endured until the present,
even if in a misleading way our ordinary language can be confusive by allowing us
to use the present tense to speak about historical facts.
The relevant conclusion is that by having the
broadest scope, the so often vilified word ‘fact’ remains the ideal candidate for
the role of ultimate truth-maker in a correspondence theory of truth. Facts are
universal truth-makers.
24. Church’s slingshot
argument
As already noted, for Frege a sentence’s
reference is its truth-value. To refute the charge that this view is implausible,
the Fregean logician Alonzo Church devised a slingshot argument. He wanted to show that by means of inter-substitutability
of co-referentials we can prove that the most diverse sentences can only have a
truth-value as their reference.
Church’s argument is equivocal, but telling.
Its basic assumption is that when one constituent expression is replaced by another,
so that their partial references (the references of their singular
terms) are interchangeable, the reference
of the whole sentence does not change. I will begin by explaining his slingshot argument, underlining its supposedly
co-referential definite descriptions (Church 1956: 25):
1. Sir Walter Scott is the author of
Waverley.
2. Sir Walter Scott is the man who wrote
the twenty-nine Waverley novels altogether.
3. Twenty-nine is the number such that Sir
Walter Scott is the man who wrote that many Waverley novels altogether.
4. Twenty-nine is the number of counties
in Utah.
According to him, if it is plausible that sentences
(2) and (3) are, if not synonymous, at least co-referential sentences,
then (1) has the same reference as (4). Since (4) seems to concern a fact completely
different from (1), it seems that the only thing left as the same reference is the
truth of both sentences. Hence, The True is the only referent of all these sentences.
However,
the argument proves to be unsustainable when we pay attention to what should be
the real reference of each singular term of these sentences. In sentence (1) the
proper name ‘Sir Walter Scott’ and the definite description ‘the author of Waverley’ are two singular terms expressing
different modes of presentation of the same human being. These modes of
presentation make what we could call two partial
references to Walter Scott, namely,
references that must be partial relatively to the whole reference of the
sentence. In sentence (2) again, the nominal expression ‘Sir Walter Scott’ and the
definite description ‘the man who wrote the twenty-nine Waverley novels altogether’ both refer in different ways, that is, partially,
to the same Walter Scott. The third sentence
is the tricky one. Its reference is unclear: Walter Scott? The number 29? Both in
one? The combination Scott-29?
The answer appears when we paraphrase sentence (3) so that it gives back in a transparent
way its complete informative content. Now, carefully considering the confusing sentence
(3), we see that the only way to reveal its content in a transparent way without
any addition or loss of sense is to split the sentence into the following conjunction
of two sentences: (5) ‘29 is the number of Waverley
novels and Sir Walter Scott is the man
who wrote that many Waverley novels altogether.’
Sentence (5) makes explicit all the content wrapped up in sentence (3). For the sake of clarity, replacing
in (5) ‘=’ for ‘is (the same as)’ and ‘&’ for ‘and,’ we can still unpack (3)
as:
6. (29 = the number of Waverley novels) & (Sir Walter Scott
= the man who wrote the many Waverley
novels altogether).[35]
That is: Sentence (3) confusingly compresses nothing
less than a conjunction of two identity sentences, each with its own proper partial
references given by the singular terms flanking their identity signs. They are the
number 29 in the first sentence and Walter
Scott in the second. Finally, we come to the analysis of sentence (4): ‘29 is
the number of counties in Utah,’ which means the same as the identity sentence (7)
‘29 = the number of counties in Utah.’ Here, each singular term that flanks the
identity sign has the number 29 as its partial reference. So analyzed, the derivation
appears as:
1. Sir Walter Scott = the author of Waverley.
2. Sir Walter Scott = the man who wrote
the 29 Waverley novels altogether.
3. (5) (29 = the number of Waverley novels)
& (Sir Walter Scott = the man who wrote the many Waverley novels altogether).
4. (6) 29 = the number of counties in
Utah.
Now, although all these sentences are true, Church’s
argument has by now lost its initial plausibility. Sentences (1) and (2) have as
the partial references made by their singular terms Walter Scott under different guises. However, sentence (3) is a conjunction
of two identity sentences, each with its own very distinct partial references. The
object referred to by the flanking terms of the first identity sentence of (3) is
the number 29 (as the number of Waverley novels), while the object referred to by
the flanking terms of the second identity sentence of (3) is Sir Walter Scott (as
the man who wrote the Waverley novels). Finally, sentence (4) has as partial references
made by its singular terms only the number 29 (as the number of counties in Utah),
without referring to Walter Scott, as it should. That is:
In the composed
sentence (3), the second sentence of the conjunction is the only one that
preserves as the partial reference made by its singular terms the references of
(1) and (2), while (4) is an identity sentence that has as partial references
made by its singular terms only the same partial references of the first
sentence of (3). However, this is precisely what should not occur, because the
preserved partial references have nothing to do with the partial references
made by the singular terms of sentences (1) and (2) and the object referred to
by them. Consequently, the whole references of these sentences and sentence (4)
must be different.
In
other words, we can say that in a surreptitious way the replacements slide equivocally
from having partial references to Walter Scott in (1) and (2), to a Walter Scott, together with
the number 29 in (3), and to the number 29 in (4). This means, according to the
principle of compositionality applied to complete sentences, that the references
of sentences (1) and (4) should indeed be very different. Initially, the flaw is
not easy to spot, because sentence (3) contains both objects of partial references
conjoined in a grammatically confusing way. We have the impression that the partial
references of (3) seem to be something like an amalgam of Walter Scott and 29, say,
a ‘Scott-29,’ while they are and must, in fact, be totally distinct. The replacements
would only respect the compositionality principle, warranting the sameness of the
sentences’ references, if the argument could prove that the partial references of
all the sentences could be replaced without
furtively inviting the reader to conjoin in sentence (3) partial references to completely
different objects.
25. Sub-facts and grounding
facts
If we take the whole reference of the sentence as
not a truth-value but a fact, we get much
more intuitive results. In what follows, I will consider Church’s intended derivation,
not only to introduce facts as referents of sentences, but also to introduce a very
useful distinction between sub-facts and grounding facts. As will be
seen, this distinction fills a gap in Frege’s explanation.
We need
to distinguish at least two facts referred to by identity sentences. The first is
the sub-fact: it is the perspectival fact
as the appearance immediately revealed
through a particular mode of presentation expressed by the statement. I will
call it a sub-fact and make the diversified
sub-facts the objective correlates responsible for differences in the modes of presentation
constitutive of the different sentences’ senses (thoughts, rules) concerning one
and the same object, e.g., Walter Scott and the author of Waverley. This is why Church’s sentences (1) and (2) can be seen as
expressing different senses or thoughts. They evoke different perspectival sub-facts.
They indirectly represent different sub-facts, since (i) being Sir Walter Scott is not the same thing as (ii) being the author of Waverley and (iii)
being the man who wrote the 29 Waverley
novels altogether… In this way, sentences (1) and (2) respectively show two different
sub-facts that contain perspectival objects of reference that as such differ from
one another. Using the term ‘being’ to indicate that we are speaking about a matching
correlate, the sub-facts represented by:
(1) Sir Walter Scott is the author of Waverley.
(2) Sir Walter Scott is the man who
wrote the 29 Waverley novels
altogether.
Can be respectively represented as follows:
(1a) Being Sir Walter Scott ≠ being the author of the
Waverley novels.
(2a) Being Sir Walter Scott ≠ being the man who wrote
the 29 Waverley novels altogether.
These sub-facts are of contingent differences since Sir Walter Scott could
have not written the Waverley novels or
any novel in the first case, and he could have written a different number of Waverley novels in the second. (If you
accept that there are relational tropes of identity, you should accept that
there are here relational tropes of difference.)
Nonetheless,
it is also clear that (1) and (2) are identity sentences. This is so because these
sentences can be understood as referring under different guises to only one object,
the person called Walter Scott, justifying the employment of the ‘is’ of identity.
In this sense, sentences (1) and (2) represent an identity, which can be expressed
simply by ‘Walter Scott = Walter Scott.’ That is, they can represent the self-identity
of Walter Scott considered in full, as the ultimate bearer of all descriptions (under
all possible perspectives) that we might intend to use to refer to it. Among the
descriptions we associate with the name ‘Walter Scott’ we can select ‘the person
with the title of Sir named “Walter Scott”’ (that is, ‘Sir Walter Scott’), ‘the
author of Waverley’ and,
certainly, ‘the man who wrote the 29 Waverley novels altogether,’ that is,
the constituent expressions of (1) and (2). Now, this primary fact that Walter
Scott is (the same as) Walter Scott (considered in full) is what I call a grounding fact. Characteristic of the grounding
fact is that it must be able to unify all the sub-facts, all the facets revealed
by its multiple modes of presentation. This is what remitting us to sentences of
the form a = a make sentences with the form a = b identity sentences.
Now,
consider one of these definite descriptions more carefully, for instance, ‘the
author of Waverley.’ As we saw, the mode
of presentation is intentional and internal, considering that the reference can
be absent. But when the mode of presentation isn’t empty, as in this case, it also
exposes something external, evoking what I could spell out as ‘being the author of the Waverley novels.’
This should be seen as an objective phenomenal entity, a sub-object mediating our reference
to the object Walter Scott that belongs to the grounding fact of Walter Scott’s
self identity.
As well, ‘the author of Ivanhoe’ (who was also Walter Scott) is a mode
of presentation of the sub-object ‘being
the author of Ivanhoe,’ though
it ultimately refers to Walter Scott. Now, take the sentence:
(a) The author of the Waverley novels
is the author of Ivanhoe.
This sentence evokes two different sub-objects that
together form the contrastive sub-fact that being the author of Waverley
is not the same as being the author of Ivanhoe. But this sub-fact also consists
of two modes by which the same object is given, whose identity is the
grounding fact that can be directly represented by the sentence ‘Being Walter Scott
[in full] = Being Walter Scott [in full],’ where ‘in full’ here means that we are intending to consider
all the conceivable modes of presentation of the object Walter Scott, far beyond
the limited knowledge of this or that particular speaker.
Moreover, it seems clear that the sentence (a)
must also be able to express the two thoughts representing the two kinds of
facts considered. First, we have a derived
thought expressible by the sentence (a1)
‘Being the author of Waverley novels isn’t the same as being the author of
Ivanhoe,’ representing directly the sub-fact and indirectly the grounding fact.
Second, we have the basal thought directly
expressible by the sentence (a2) ‘Being Walter Scott [in full] =
being Walter Scott [in full],’ representing the grounding fact directly.[36]
According
to the foregoing analysis, when I say ‘The author of Waverley novels is the author of Ivanhoe,’
I am saying two things. First, by means of intentional modes of presentation, I
am expressing the derived thought evoking a factual objective difference.
This thought can be expressed by the sentence ‘Being the author of Waverley
≠ (isn’t) being the author of Ivanhoe,’ representing a derived fact. Indeed, it is an objective factual
difference that a person writing Waverley is not the same as a person writing
Ivanhoe, even if they are both the same person (he was writing different
stories at different places
and times…). However, since when I say ‘The author of Waverley is the author
of Ivanhoe’ I use
an ‘is’ of identity, I also mean the basal
thought expressible by the sentence ‘The
author of Waverley = the author of Ivanhoe,’ indicating that under
different guises I am presenting the grounding fact that ‘Being Walter Scott = Being
Walter Scott.’ It is because of the two – the grounding fact along with the sub-fact
– that identities of the kind a = b are able to express identities in their differences.
Now,
assuming the kind of neo-descriptivism proposed in Appendix I of this book, we can
make explicit the above-mentioned doubling of the presented facts by stating each
of the four sentences of Church’s reasoning as follows:
(1a) Sentence expressing the derived thought
representing the sub-fact: Being Sir Walter Scott ≠ being the author of Waverley.
(1b) Sentence expressing the basal thought
representing the grounding fact: Being Walter Scott [in full] = being Walter
Scott [in full].
(2a) Sentence expressing the derived thought
representing the sub-fact: Being Sir Walter Scott ≠ being the man who wrote
the 29 Waverley novels altogether.
(2b) Sentence expressing the basal thought
representing the grounding fact: Being Walter Scott [in full] = being Walter
Scott [in full].
(3a) Sentence expressing the derived thought
representing the sub-fact: (Being 29 ≠ being the number of Waverley novels)
& (Being Sir Walter Scott ≠ being the man who wrote the 29 Waverley novels
altogether).
3b) Sentence expressing the basal thought
representing the grounding fact: (Being 29 = being 29) & (Being Walter Scott
= being Walter Scott).
(4a) Sentence expressing the derived thought
representing the sub-fact: Being 29 ≠ being the number of counties in Utah.
(4b) Sentence expressing the basal thought
representing the grounding fact: Being 29 = being 29.
The sub-facts show why the semantic
contribution of each referential component in identities with the form a = b, due
to the semantic-cognitive rules constitutive of the derived thought, can be different.
The sub-fact that being Sir Walter Scott isn’t the same as being someone who wrote 29 Waverley novels discriminates more
than the sub-fact that being Scott isn’t the same as someone writing the Waverley
novels. And regarding true sentences, this
discrimination isn’t just a mentally considered mode of presentation, a cognitive
rule, but also the representation of something objectively or factually given in
the external world (corresponding to different ‘ways the object gives itself to us,’ using Frege’s words). The above
presented evocations of sub-facts all lead us to two grounding facts of identity
showing how many different senses referring immediately to qualitatively different sub-facts refer mediately to something
numerically identical. On the other hand, in sentences with the form a = a, such
as ‘the morning star = the morning star,’ the sub-fact is already the identity ‘Being
the morning star = being the morning star.’ The corresponding grounding-fact, additionally,
may also be the same identity, if not the identity ‘Being Venus = being Venus,’
depending on the speaker’s intention.
26. Taking seriously
the sentence’s reference as a fact
I think I have shown that the most
plausible option concerning the nature of reference is to side with philosophers like Russell and the
earlier Wittgenstein. These philosophers assumed that the reference of a statement
is a fact – a fact that in the usual case is understood as a contingent arrangement
of cognitively-independent tropical components commonly given (completely or partially)
in the external world, although they can also belong to an internal (psychologically
accessible) reality. Facts would satisfy the Fregean condition that the reference
of a sentence is an object: they are in some sense independent, complete, closed.
They would satisfy the condition that thoughts expressed by sentences should
also be modes of presentation of their
references, the latter – particularly as sub-facts – being as numerous and diverse
as their thoughts. Finally, unlike truth-values, facts would smoothly satisfy the
principle of compositionality: they would always vary in accordance with variations
in the references of the senses of component parts of the sentences as we understand
them.
If we assume the answer given above, we are
able to solve a vexing problem concerning which fact the thought expressed by a
sentence refers to. Consider the following sentences:
1. The morning star is the morning star.
2. The morning star is the evening star.
3. Venus is the morning star.
4. Venus is the second planet orbiting the Sun.
5. Venus is the brightest planet visible in the
sky.
6. Venus is the only planet in our solar system
shrouded by an opaque layer of highly reflective sulphuric acid clouds.
7. The morning star is the only planet in our solar
system shrouded by an opaque layer of highly reflective sulphuric acid clouds…
On the one hand, it is intuitively
correct to say that each of these sentences refers to a different fact. Sentence
(1) is tautological, proclaiming the factual self-identity of the morning star,
while sentences (2) to (7) provide information on different factual contents regarding
the planet Venus. On the other hand, since all singular terms composing these identity
sentences have the same ultimate reference, the planet Venus, it also seems clear
that in the end all these identity sentences must have the same reference, representing
the same fact in the world. How can
we reconcile
these two seemingly correct views?
The answer departs from the distinction already
made in the last section: first, there must be a privileged grounding fact
able to be described that can be identified as the ultimate truth-maker of all these
identity sentences about the planet Venus. Second, this grounding fact must in some
way contain the facts immediately indicated by the different cognitive values of
sentences (1) to (7) above as its perspectival sub-facts. My suggestion is that this last task can be accomplished
by the references of identity sentences, insofar as the identification rules of
their singular terms are considered in
full, including all their fundamental
and auxiliary descriptions.
Now, assuming our proposed view of proper names’
meanings as abbreviations of bundles of descriptions centered in those
constituting their fundamental identification rules, then the proper name ‘Venus’
in full includes in its most complete
content all the already known modes of presentation. This means that definite descriptions
such as ‘the morning star,’ ‘the second planet orbiting the Sun,’ ‘the brightest
planet visible in the sky,’ etc. can have their application made at least probable
by applying the concept of Venus in full. (I say ‘made at least probable’ because,
in the case of most identification rules, any particular description-rule of the
bundle might be wrong and remain unsatisfied.) If this view is correct, then there
is only one sentence that could describe the grounding fact as the ultimate truth-maker
or verifier of any identity sentence concerning the planet Venus, including the
sentences from (1) to (7) above. We can present it as the grounding fact (8) that
being Venus with all its known sub-factual identificational inferences is being
Venus with all its known sub-factual identificational inferences, represented
by the basal thought expressed by the sentence:
(9) Venus [in full] = Venus [in
full]
My contention is that rightly understood
this sentence summarizes the most complete basal thought able to represent the single grounding fact, which considered in its entirety can be regarded as the truth-maker for any identity sentence
about the planet Venus. (To represent
sub-facts
we have the already named derived thoughts.)
It is not hard to explain why things are so.
If the full meaning of the proper name ‘Venus’ is understood as an abbreviation
of the whole bundle of descriptions regarded as uniquely identifying its object (Cf.
Appendix of Chapter I, sec. 4), then this proper name should include descriptions
like ‘the morning star,’ ‘the evening star,’ ‘the second planet orbiting the Sun,’
‘the most brilliant planet visible in the sky,’ ‘the only planet in our solar system shrouded by an opaque
layer of highly reflective sulphuric acid clouds,’ and many others. Consequently, from the
sentence ‘Venus [in full] = Venus [in full]’ we can inferentially derive sentence
(2) ‘The morning star = the evening star.’ We do this simply by replacing the first
occurrence of the name ‘Venus’ with the definite description ‘the morning star,’
which the name ‘Venus’ (in full) abbreviates, and the second occurrence of the name
‘Venus’ (in full) with the description ‘the evening star,’ which the name Venus
also abbreviates. In a similar way, we can obviously (inductively, at least) infer
all the other above presented co-referential identities
from (1) to (7). Thus, rightly understood the sentence ‘Venus [in full] = Venus
[in full]’ should express the basal thought able to represent a fact complex enough
to comprehend all the sub-facts represented
by each of the thoughts expressed by the above sentences, which may be seen here
as contingent a posteriori. (To convince yourself of this, look at the meaning of
‘Venus’ as presented in any encyclopedia, since it aims to offer an abbreviation of Venus in full.)
In order to better support what I am suggesting,
I can also use numerical identities like the following:
1. 2 + 2 = 2 + 2
2. 2 + 2 = 1 + 1 + 1 + 1
3. 2 + 2 = 4
4. 4
= √16
5. 2 + 2 = (14 – 6) / 2
Of course, here the identity sentence
expressing the basal thought representing the grounding fact would be:
6. The number 4 [in full] = the number 4 [in full]
But could the sub-facts expressed
by sentences (1) to (5) be derived from (6)? Obviously, the answer must be in the
affirmative, since we are dealing with a deductive system. After all, I wrote the five sentences above simply
based on deductive inferences
from my knowledge of the grounding fact that being the number 4 = being the number
4!
However, one could still object that a sentence
like ‘Venus [in full] = Venus [in full]’ is a tautology: a necessary truth. How
could a necessary truth ground contingent truths like, ‘Venus is the brightest planet
visible in the sky’?
My answer is that for an idealized privileged
user of the word (or an astronomer) who is supposed to know all the relevant information
about Venus, this proper name expresses an identification rule that can be
approximatively summarized as follows:
IR-Venus: Our proper
name ‘Venus’ has a bearer, iff this bearer
belongs to the class of celestial bodies that satisfy sufficiently and more than
any other the condition of being the second planet orbiting the Sun between Mercury
and the Earth. (To this it is helpful to add very probably applicable auxiliary
descriptions like ‘the brightest planet visible in the sky,’ ‘a planet somewhat
smaller than the earth,’ ‘the morning star,’ ‘the evening star,’ etc.)
As in the case of the Venus
called ‘Hesperus’ (Appendix of Chapter I, sec. 10 (iii)), this is a kind of ‘one-foot’
identification rule, since the localizing rule is the only fundamental one and includes
what would count in the characterizing rule (being a planet). For suppose we have
as a characterizing rule ‘a bright planet somewhat smaller than the earth.’ In this
case, one can imagine that if there were only
one bright
planet somewhat smaller than the Earth, this planet would be Venus, since one term
of the inclusive disjunction of a fundamental identifying rule is already satisfied.
But if this were true, since we can imagine a possible world where there is just
one bright planet somewhat smaller than the
Earth with an orbit outside the Earth’s and no second planet, this planet should
then be Venus, which is absurd. And as noted, the localizing rule contains the
essential characterizing content: Venus as a planet. If Venus were to lose its atmosphere
or a major share of its mass (or in a different possible world never had them),
insofar as it had been discovered to be the second planet from the Sun and the Earth
the third, it would still be our Venus! Indeed, so understood it seems that the
identification rule for Venus is applicable in any possible world where the planet
Venus can be said to exist or to have existed.
The case of Venus is somewhat like the case
of the lines ‘aᴖb-aᴖc’ drawn to localize the center of a triangle without any call
for a characterizing property; the characterizing description can be irrelevant
or non-existent. By the same token, without the localizing condition established
by the identification rule of Venus as the second planet, it would be impossible
to identify Venus. The application of many other descriptions does not produce criteria,
but only symptoms of the planet’s existence, since they make the applicability of
the descriptions only more or less probable. Auxiliary descriptions like ‘the brightest
planet in the sky’ are symptoms, like ‘the highly reflective clouds of sulfuric
acid’ that cause this brightness. If Venus lost its reflective atmosphere, it might cease to be the brightest planet, but would still not cease to be Venus. If Venus
lost half of its mass but remained in the same orbit, it still would not cease to
be Venus. But if for some reason Venus lost nearly all its mass and became a small
orbiting object only a few miles in diameter, no longer large enough to be called
a planet, we could only say that it once was Venus. If in a possible world Mercury
never existed, Venus would be the first
planet of the solar system and even if it were called ‘Venus,’ it seems clear that
it would not really be our Venus, unless it had once been the second planet from
the Sun (Venus) for at least some period of time. Indeed, if in another possible
world the second planet were hurled out of the solar
system thousands of years ago (Kripke 1980: 57-58), it could still rightly be recognized
as our Venus, since it once satisfied its identification rule. We see that the condition
of sufficiency applied to the one-foot identification rule of Venus is more demanding
than in the usual two-foot case. And we see that limits can be set even in a swampy
terrain where vagueness prevails.
What I said about identity sentences also applies
to other singular predicative and relational sentences. Consider the following ones:
1. Bucephalus was a material thing.
2. Bucephalus was a living being.
3. Bucephalus was a horse.
4. Bucephalus was a black horse of the best Thessalonian strain.
5. Bucephalus was a massive black horse of the best Thessalonian strain,
owned by Alexander the Great.
6. Bucephalus: (355 BC – 326 BC) was the most famous horse of Antiquity;
it was a massive black horse of the best Thessalonian strain, owned by Alexander
the Great.
7. Bucephalus once swam across the river Granicus.
One could say that each of the
first six sentences expresses different derived thoughts representing different
sub-facts by means of increasingly detailed modes of presentation expressed by their
respective predicative expressions. However, relative to them there is a grounding
fact that in a summarized form is represented by the basal thought expressed by
sentence (6), since the truth of all the others can be implied by the truth of this
thought. Indeed, (6) is nothing but an abbreviated expression of the identification
rule for Bucephalus, with a localizing and a characterizing description and by these
means furnishing a summarized definitional criterion. The sub-facts represented by sentences (1) to (5) are
all included in the grounding fact represented by sentence (6). These facts are
the immediate satisfiers of the diverse modes of presentation of Bucephalus given
by each sentence. And the progression from (1) to (6) increases the complexity,
insofar as new relevant predications
are added. Statement (7) ‘Bucephalus once swam across the river Granicus’ is a different
case: the very contingent auxiliary description ‘the horse Bucephalus who once swam across the river Granicus’ isn’t a relevant
part of the fundamental description-rule (even if he didn’t swim across the
river, he would still be our Bucephalus). Nevertheless, it can still be derived
from (6) considered in full, since this is believed (by privileged speakers) to
be historically the case.
27. The riddle of identity
in difference
There is a final point concerning
the relationship between the sub-fact and the grounding fact. It concerns the unsatisfactory way that Frege solved the puzzle
of identity. As he wrote, unlike sentences with the form a = a, a sentence with the
form a = b is informative because it
refers to the same object by means of different modes of presentation, by means
of the different senses of a and b (1892: 26). However, we can still ask how
this identity is possible, since the modes of presentation are different and since
we are not intending to speak about the mere
self-identity of the reference, as Frege also acknowledged. I call this ‘the riddle
of identity in difference.’
To see the problem clearly, consider again
Frege’s sentence (i) ‘The morning star = (is) the evening star.’ A more fully unpacked
cognitive sense of (i) can be presented as:
The brightest star in
the morning sky, understood as referring
to the second planet orbiting the Sun between Earth and Mercury (Venus) =
(is) the brightest star in the evening
sky, understood as referring to the second planet orbiting the Sun between Earth
and Mercury (Venus).
Here I have not [j1] [c2] underlined non-definitional
expressions of what I call immediate senses presenting perceptual sub-objects
like the morning and the evening star, though I have underlined expressions of what I call mediated senses, which here are definitional. The immediate senses build the
derived thought representing a sub-fact (that being the morning star isn’t being
the evening star), while the mediated senses essentially build the basal thought
representing the grounding fact (that Venus is Venus). Here we have the hidden reason
for the riddle of identity in difference: the immediate senses of the expressions flanking the identity sign in (i) are obviously
different, but they both evoke the underlined mediated, in fact primary or leading sense (essentially building the
basal thought that Venus is Venus) with the form a = a.
Obviously, this last sense, the basic thought
that the second planet orbiting the Sun… is the second planet orbiting the Sun…
is not yet the reference, since it is constituted by the expression of the self-identity
of the cognitive identification rule constituting the core definitional sense of
the name ‘Venus’ and its conventionalized surroundings (Venus in full). It is only
because both expressions flanking the identity sign in (i) implicitly evoke the
same proper identification rule for the planet Venus that we are allowed to place
an identity sign between them! In order to make the point still clearer we can appeal
to the following schema:
Sentence: The morning star = (is) the evening star.
Derived: IR: the brightest ≠ IR:
the brightest
thought: star in the morning star
in the evening.
sub-fact:
Being the morning star
isn’t being the evening star.
Basal IR: The second planet… = IR: the second planet…
thought (Venus) (Venus).
grounding
fact: Being Venus is the same as being
Venus.
In sum: the singular terms ‘Morning
Star’ and ‘Evening Star’ are responsible for the difference present in what I call
the immediate senses of the descriptions
(the Fregean senses) constituting a derived thought evoking a relational sub-fact
showing the differences between two sub-references. Expressing the derived
thought we describe the sub-fact as: ‘being the brightest star seen in the morning
sky differs in place and time from being the brightest star seen in the evening
sky’ (one can even point to the two opposite sides
of the sky in which alternately
one or the other appears every twelve hours). Furthermore, the ‘is’ understood as ‘is
the same as’ is the only indication of the identity of the implicitly intended mediated senses building the basal thought expressed by the sentence ‘The second
planet orbiting the Sun between Earth and Mercury (Venus) = the second planet orbiting
the Sun between Earth and Mercury (Venus).’ These mediated senses have multiple
guises that are implicit in the names flanking the identity sign in the statement
‘Venus [in full] = Venus [in full]’ expressing the basal thought that could be known
in full only by specialists or idealized speakers. The statement expressing the
derived thought is contingent a posteriori,
while the statement expressing the basal thought can be seen as a necessary priori.
A somewhat different example is the sentence
‘The morning star is Venus.’ Here the schema is:
Sentence: The morning star = (is) Venus.
Derived: IR: the brightest ≠ IR: the second
Thought: star
at dawn planet.
sub-fact: Being the morning star isn’t being
Venus.
Basal IR: the second planet = IR:
the second planet
Thought: (Venus)
(Venus).
grounding
fact:
Being Venus is the same as being Venus.
It is by now clear that the identity
expressed by sentences of the kind a = b is an identity in difference. This means
that in fact we have two levels of sense or thought. The first is the derived
thought. It represents the perspectival sub-fact with its sub-objects expressing
a difference (Being the morning star isn’t
the same as being the second planet from the Sun). The second, intermediated by
the first one and indicated by the ‘is’ of identity, is the basal thought representing
the ultimate grounding fact that being Venus is the same as being Venus, which has
the sub-facts as facets, as manifestations. The derived thought is contingent a
posteriori, while the basic thought is a necessary
a priori expression of a conditioned rule.
Now, how should we deal with cases in which
the elements of the basal thought responsible for the identity, like the planet
called ‘Venus’ in the statement above, lack a proper name? Consider the identities
(i) ‘Everest = Chomolungma,’ (ii) ‘aᴖb = aᴖc’ (concerning Frege’s example of two
different ways to name the center of a triangle), (iii) ‘Afla = Ateb’ (the two names
that Frege gave for the same imaginary mountain). In order to get an answer, we
need to first consider that the derived Fregean senses are thoughts of a difference,
evoking different contingent sub-objects. But these sentences also implicitly evoke
a basal conjoining sense, a conjoining identification rule, which refers to
what we might call respectively the ‘Everest-Chomolungma,’ the ‘aᴖb-aᴖc,’ and the
‘Afla-Ateb,’ which in fact are three new nominative expressions. The law of identity
makes it obvious that:
(1) ‘Mt. Everest is Chomolungma’ so understood can be
replaced by ‘Everest[-Chomolungma] = [Everest-]Chomolungma,’
(2) ‘aᴖb = aᴖc’ can be replaced by ‘aᴖb[-aᴖc] = ‘[aᴖb-]aᴖc,’
and
(3) ‘Afla = Ateb’ can be replaced by ‘Afla[-Ateb] =
[Afla-]Ateb.’
These three replacing basal thoughts
respectively represent the three different grounding facts as the full self-identities
that they are. This is respectively what sustains the identities expressed by the
‘is’ in the sentences (i), (ii) and (iii).
We can apply a similar analysis to identities
between concept-words of the form (x)
(Fx = Gx). Consider the identity ‘Heat in gases is molecular kinetic energy.’
Note that the word ‘heat’ is ambiguous. It can mean a mere subjective feeling (heat1),
like the feeling of increased bodily heat after exercise, which cannot be identified
with molecular kinetic energy. But in the present case ‘heat’ means external temperature
as it is normally felt by people
(heat2).
A third sense is independent of our sensations: it is heat as ‘measured temperature’
determined by thermometers (heat3) (in the sense of heat2, our bodies serve as coarse,
imprecise thermometers). Moreover, since molecules can have different masses and
speeds, the most precise identity sentence would be ‘Temperature in a gas (heat3)
is the average kinetic energy of its molecules.’ This sentence expresses two different
modes of presentation of the same thing, that is, a derived thought that can be
expressed by means of the following difference:
(i)
Temperature in a gas (heat3) ≠ average kinetic energy of
its molecules.
This secondary thought refers only
to the sub-fact that the (macro-physical) temperature
that we can measure with a thermometer (and feel
as heat2) is something phenomenally different from the (microphysical) average kinetic
energy of the molecules of a gas such as the air around us.
In a next step, we are able to consider the basal thought establishing
a tautological identity based on conventions. This thought can be expressed by the
whole more complete assertoric sentence:
(ii) [Average kinetic energy-temperature-]
heat3 of a quantity of gas = average kinetic
energy-temperature [-heat3 of a quantity
of gas].
Now, we can read the sentence ‘Heat in
gases is molecular kinetic energy’ as something made explicit by sentence (ii),
which can be read in two ways: (a) considering only what is outside the brackets
as explicitly emphasized, which expresses the derived thought
of a difference and represents the sub-fact of the difference above; (b) emphasizing the whole, including what is in brackets.
Understanding (ii) as (b), what we have is a basal thought referring to a grounding
fact of definitional self-identity. This identity requires as an assumption the
acceptance of the kinetic theory of gases, which makes (b) a tautology. This means
that if we read (ii) in the sense (a), disregarding what is in the brackets, we
can see it as a contingent a posteriori thought,
since it can be denied without contradiction, while if we read (ii) in
the sense (b) it can be considered necessary
a priori, since it cannot be denied without contradiction.
Consider now the sentence ‘Water is H2O.’
I think Avrum Stroll was right when he noted that here the ‘is’ expresses constitution; the sentence more
often means ‘Water is made of H2O’
rather than ‘Water is the same as (quantities of) H2O.’ (1996, 46 f.)
However, this does not make a relevant difference for what I will try to say
and contexts can lead us easily to read this ‘is’ as expressing identity.
As already noted (Appendix to Chapter II),
the concept-word ‘water’ has two nuclei of meaning: a superficial one, that of an
aqueous liquid (transparent, tasteless,
odorless, etc.), and a deep one, a substance called by chemists dihydrogen oxide or H2O (which
includes much more than the simple chemical structure). This means that the complete
sense of water must include the two nuclei. However, as in fact the presence of
only one nucleus already allows us, in a proper context, to call the substance water,
the most embracing criteria for the application of the general term ‘water’ demands
sufficient satisfaction of the (summarized) inclusive disjunctive rule:
DR: (Water is an) aqueous liquid
and/or (water is) dihydrogen oxide (H2O).
Philosophers have created a pseudo-problem
by insisting that the criterion of application of the conceptual word ‘water’ must
be either aqueous liquid or dihydrogen oxide, as if it were a dilemma.[37]
Now, assuming that the ‘is’ is one of constitution
and not of identity, the statement (i) ‘Water is H2O’ in fact means:
(ii) ‘Aqueous liquid and/or dihydrogen oxide… is made of dihydrogen oxide.’ Since
it could be that water isn’t made of dihydrogen oxide and only the first statement
of the DR is true, it is possible for the whole statement to be false, which makes
it a contingent a posteriori truth and
not a necessary a posteriori truth, as
Kripke would like it to be. However, as we will see in the
next section, in some contexts statement (i) is rather seen as a necessary a priori truth.
28. Contexts of interest:
no need for a necessary
a posteriori
This double core sense of the general
term ‘water’ helps to explain Saul Kripke’s in my view as much insightful as illusory
discovery of the necessary a posteriori.
But in order to better understand the confusions involved, we need to add to the
sentences the contexts in which they are spoken.
A first point to notice is that in the case
of a sentences of the kind a = b uttered in different contexts we can enhance or magnify or emphasize its immediate
(Fregean) perspectival sense that builds a derived thought (representing a sub-fact),
or we can enhance or magnify or emphasize its mediated sense that builds the basal thought (representing
a grounding fact).[38] Thus, in cases like
‘Water is H2O’ we can emphasize the immediate core sense of the concept-word
‘water’ as an aqueous liquid or its
mediated core sense as dihydrogen oxide. Here I need to speak again of the contexts of interest of the linguistic agents,
meaning thereby contextualized practical
aims from which we can infer what is meant.
Two contexts of interest are important regarding
the main examples above: the popular and
the scientific one. Thus, considering
the sentence ‘The morning star is the evening star,’ we can contextually emphasize the derived thought composed by
immediate senses (modes of presentation, identification rules) representing the
external, phenomenally given objects, considering the difference between being the
brightest star in the morning and the brightest star in the evening. If we do this,
we leave the identity ‘Venus = Venus’ in the background. This can be the case, for
instance, when contemplating the beauty of the starry sky at night and, after localizing
the evening star, we tell a child that it is also
the morning star. In this case, we think like Frege. We emphasize the different
modes of presentation of the same object, a difference that as such represents nothing
but an empirical sub-fact made by two different aspectual presentations of what
we believe to be the same thing. We regard the thought that the morning star is
the evening star as contingent a posteriori,
since it mainly represents the sub-fact of the difference, although we are also
aware that we are emphasizing the different ways by means of which the same thing
presents itself to us.
Nonetheless, in a scientific context of interest,
such as one in which astronomers use a telescope to study the surface of Venus,
when they consider the sentence ‘The morning star is also the evening star,’ what
they usually have in mind and emphasize is the numerical identity of the object of both modes of presentation.
These are the mediated senses constituting the basal thought representing the grounding
fact of the self-identity of Venus, which Kripke particularly emphasized in his
writings. In this case, we read the statement as preferentially meaning the basal
thought that ‘Venus [in full] = Venus [in full],’ which is a necessary a priori statement, since what
we above all affirm is the tautological grounding fact that being Venus is the same
as being Venus. It leaves the different guises of sense in the background, as secondary
effects, insofar as we assume the truth of our scientific astronomical views.
Now, consider again the statement ‘Water is
H2O’.[39] In a popular context
of interest which arises when fishermen decide to dig a well to obtain fresh water for drinking and washing, this statement is
read as emphasizing the sense of the word ‘water’ as a precious aqueous liquid (transparent,
tasteless, odorless, drinkable… the popular nucleus of meaning), and it is for them
a contingent matter that it is made of H2O insofar as it satisfies
their practical aims. Because of this, the statement is seen as contingent a posteriori, since it means ‘This aqueous liquid is made of H2O,’ this expressing a derived thought
representing a sub-fact that does not demand that water is necessarily H2O,
being deniable without contradiction.
On the other hand, when the context of interest
is scientific, for instance, formed by chemists measuring the acidity of a sample
of water, the word ‘water’ in the sentence ‘Water is H2O’ can be read
as emphasizing the sense of water as dihydrogen oxide (the scientific nucleus of
meaning). In this case, the whole sentence is seen as preferentially expressing
a thought representing a grounding fact expressed by the identity ‘Water [H2O]
= H2O [water],’ which has the form a = a, that is, of a necessary
a priori tautology based on our intuitive and scientific assumptions.
I think that philosophers like Kripke, by considering
‘Water is H2O’ a necessary a posteriori
statement, simply confuse (i) the aposteriority
of the statement which emphasizes that water is an aqueous liquid made of H2O
with (ii) the a priori necessity of the statement that emphasizes
the convention that water must be the same as H2O, mixing the aposteriority of (i) with the
conditioned necessity of (ii).
A somewhat different emphasis can be found
in the statement ‘Heat is molecular movement,’ here understood as ‘Heat = molecular
movement.’ If we emphasize the ordinary immediate senses, the derived thought, the
difference between heat2 (heat as it is normally felt) and the average kinetic energy
of a gas, the emphasized sense or thought is contingent a posteriori, and the fact referred to is something
learned by experience. This could be the case even using heat3 (temperature) as
a fallible measure of average kinetic
energy.
On the other hand, if we assume the truth of
the kinetic theory of gases in a scientific context in which we are measuring temperatures,
the statement can be understood as emphasizing the mediated sense of the identity
expressible by: ‘Temperature of a gas [-average kinetic energy] = average kinetic
energy [-temperature of a gas],’ insofar as it is read as expressing the basal thought
representing the grounding fact of an assumed identity, being therefore a (conditional)
necessary a priori thought. In this reading,
our conceptual rules for temperature and for average kinetic energy are blended
into a single identification rule which assumes the kinetic theory of gases.
It seems to me that by considering identities
of the kind a = b, Kripke misleadingly
conjoined the aposteriority of the emphasized
derived identity thought with the necessity
of the emphasized basal identity thought, concluding that the identities between
nominal and conceptual terms have a necessary
a posteriori nature that is only metaphysically explicable. However, if these
names or concept-words serve as rigid designators applying to the same entities
in all possible worlds, this is explained by their assumed mediated senses, which
are of the kind a = a (or a[b] = [a]b) and not only as a = b
representing a difference. A Wittgensteinian therapist would conclude that in the
considered cases Kripke was the victim of deep grammatical ambiguities. Finally,
insofar as the terms a and b used in identity sentences are viewed as
rigid designators unavoidably applying to the same ultimate object in all possible
worlds where it exists, this is also only justified by the self-identity of a grounding
fact.
29. Sense of a sentence:
the thought
Now it is time to consider the
sense of a sentence. Here is Frege at his best! He made the right decision in suggesting that the
meaning of the whole sentence is the thought (Gedanke) it expresses.
To reach this conclusion, he applied his compositionality principle:
combined in the right way, the senses of the component terms constitute the sense
of the whole sentence. If, for instance, in the sentence ‘The morning star is a
planet’ we replace the description ‘the morning star’ with the description ‘the
evening star,’ which is co-referential though having a different sense, the reference
of the sentence does not change; but the sense of the sentence must change. Indeed,
the sense of the sentence ‘The evening star is a planet’ is different. However,
the only other thing that has changed is what
we use to call the thought expressed by the resulting sentence.
Consequently, the sense of a sentence must be the thought it expresses. (Frege
1892: 32)
The word ‘thought’ is ambiguous. One can use
it to describe a psychological process
of thinking, as in the utterance ‘I was just thinking of you!’ But it also seems
to designate something independent of specific mental occurrences – a content of thought – such
as the thought expressed by the sentence ‘12 x 12 = 144’ in the utterance:
‘The sentence “12 x 12 = 144” expresses a true thought.’ Frege had the latter
sense in mind. In this usage, the word ‘thought’ means simply what the sentence
(statement) says,
which Frege conceived of as some sort of eternal (timeless) Platonic entity. A
way to make the difference explicit would be to call the Fregean thought a thought-content. The terminology here counts because the word ‘thought’ is the
only term in ordinary language that has a sense corresponding to more technical
terms like ‘proposition’ or ‘propositional content.’[40]
Frege has a criterion for deciding what belongs
to a thought. For him, everything that contributes
to determining the truth-value of a sentence should belong to its thought. Thus,
using his own example, the sentences ‘Alfred hasn’t arrived’ and ‘Alfred hasn’t
arrived yet’ express the same thought, since the word ‘yet’ means only an expectation
regarding Alfred’s arrival without contributing to the sentence’s truth-value (Frege
1918: 64). The sentences ‘The morning star is Venus’ and ‘The evening star is Venus’
can be considered to express different thoughts because although the singular terms
that make up these two identity sentences all refer to the same planet, they do
this by means of different modes of presentation. That is, they make us follow different
paths in determining their truth-value, or, as I prefer to think, they make us follow
different associations of semantic-cognitive rules able to constitute correspondingly
different verifiability procedures.
30. The thought as
the truth-bearer
Another quite plausible Fregean
thesis was that the primary bearer
of truth is not the sentence, but rather the thought (proposition) expressed
by it. I agree with this view. Although we can say that sentences, beliefs and even
things and persons are true, they all seem to be true in a derivative sense.
Consider the cases of things and persons. A
useful test to identify secondary uses is that when a word is derivatively used
we can replace it with a more appropriate
word. If we say that a diamond is false, what we mean is that it is only an
imitation diamond: a fake or counterfeit of a real diamond that deceives us so much that we can think
false thoughts about it. When we say that Socrates was ‘true’ as a person, what
we mean is that he was a truthful, trustworthy
or reliable person, someone with integrity.
But this is not always so. When
we say that Sam’s belief is true, although we secondarily mean that he has a subjective
psychological attitude concerning his (dispositional) thought – of finding it
true – we primarily mean that his thought is true in a Fregean sense.
One reason for preferring to say that the thought
is the truth-bearer concerns the logical behavior of this concept. We deal with
our concept of truth as an ‘as if’ directive
idea, so that the real or actual truth-value
of a thought is naturally conceived of as something invariant: if something is
(really) true, it is always true; if something is (really) false, it is always false.
Obviously, we can always err in judging
and claiming something to be true (as
das Fürwahrhalten) and can later discover
it is false, and we can err in believing
something to be false (das Fürfalschhalten) when it is actually true – this is often
the case, and this possibility
is inevitable, due to our inherent epistemic fallibility. But when we discover our
error, we correct ourselves, in the first case not by claiming that the thought was previously true
and now has become false, but by saying that it was always false, and in the second
case we correct ourselves not by claiming that the thought was previously false
and now has become true, but by saying that it was always true. What changed was our truth-claim expressing our
judgment, not the truth-value. Moreover, it is fundamental to perceive that our
inherent fallibility in holding thoughts to be true does not affect the invariability
or immutability of the truth-value of the thought or proposition in itself. It must
be so because it is beyond our fallible capacities to know with absolute certainty
whether we have achieved this ideal, if we have indeed achieved it. This is how the logical grammar of our concept
of truth works (and, beyond this, the
grammar of our own concept of knowledge). If one wants to change something so fundamental,
then to prevent confusion one should invent new terms instead, like ‘hturt’ and ‘eslaf’.
Now, if the actual truth-value is immutable,
its truth-bearer must also be unchanging, able to remain the same in order to retain
this same truth-value independently of the time or place where we discovered it. Indeed, for Frege a really
true thought remains true forever, just as a really false thought remains false
forever. These entities are even abbreviated as ‘truths’ and ‘falsities’ respectively.
Thus, it is deeply ingrained in our conceptual grammar that the entity that can
be primarily called true or false must remain the same and possess the same truth-value so that what
may change is only our cognitive grasp of it, our believing in its truth-value (das Fürwahrhalten). If this is so, then only
the thought has the necessary stability
to be the archetypical truth-bearer; for a thought is, according to Frege, unchangeable
and eternal (a-temporal), being eternally (a-temporally) true or false independently
of our grasping (fassen) it.
Consider now the case of sentences as candidates
for truth-bearers. Ambiguous sentences can express different Fregean thoughts, such
as ‘John saw the man on the mountain with a telescope.’ In this case, the truth-value
of the thought will be able to change according to the different thoughts or interpretations
that we assign to the sentence. But if the truth-bearer were the sentence, the truth-value
should remain the same, which cannot be correct. This
is obvious in the case of indexical utterances like ‘I am in pain,’ which has different
truth-values depending on the speaker.[41] The same sentence can change
its sense-thought when uttered by different persons, and even when uttered by the
same person at different times; correspondingly, what may change with the change
in thought is the truth-value. Hence, thoughts and their truth-values are co-variant,
while sentences and their truth-values are not, which leads us to the conclusion
that the primary bearer of truth-value must be the thought or proposition.
One could suppose that perhaps the sentence-token would be the truth-bearer, since it would be a different one depending
on the time and place of the utterance, changing with the truth-value. However,
we still have cases in which different sentences (token or not) say the same thing
– express the same thought – in this way preserving the same truth-value. Consider,
for example, the following statements, ‘It is raining,’ ‘Il pleut,’ ‘Es regnet,’
‘Chove’… uttered in the same context. They all say the same thing, express the same
thought, and all have the same truth-value, while their sentence-tokens are quite
different. Indeed, the only justification for insisting on the immutability of the truth-value
of these four different sentence-tokens (and types) is that their primary truth-bearer is the thought expressed by them,
since what they say – their senses, their thoughts – is what remains the same. Finally,
this is the case not only for indexical sentences but also for eternal sentences
with the same content, though expressed in different languages.
Likewise, beliefs, understood in a psychological
sense, can only be derivative truth-bearers: if someone who believes something dies,
his psychological belief also ceases to exist. Consequently, the truth-bearer
must be the content of his belief. It must be his belief-content and not his belief
in a dispositional psychological sense, since only the belief-content isn’t
transitory. But this is so only because we understand the belief-content as the
same as a Fregean thought, a propositional content.
The core of the foregoing arguments can be
summarized as follows: thoughts and their truth-values are not just invariantly
related; when thoughts vary, they maintain a
relationship of co-variance with their truth-values. This relationship is missing
in the relationships between sentences or psychological beliefs and their truth-values.
Because of this, the proper bearer of truth must be the thought (proposition, propositional
content, belief-content), not the sentence or some personal psychological disposition
to agree on a truth-value.
31. Facts as true thoughts?
As already noted, Frege also proposed
that what we call a fact is the same thing as a true thought, because when a scientist discovers a true thought, he
claims to have discovered a fact. As he wrote:
‘Facts! Facts! Facts!’ exclaims the researcher of nature,
when he wants to proclaim the need for a secure basis of science. What is a fact?
A fact is a thought that is true. (1918: 74)
Indeed, when we say ‘John stated
several relevant facts in his speech,’ we are speaking about facts as true thoughts.
However, there is no warrant that this is not a derivative use of the word ‘fact.’
A researcher of nature can well exclaim ‘Facts! Facts! Facts!’ understanding by
a fact simply what corresponds to the true thought, namely, some objectively
given tropical arrangement. After all, it seems natural to think that if someone
discovers a true thought, it is because he has a fortiori discovered the fact corresponding to it.
A more decisive argument against thoughts as
true facts came from J. L. Austin, who made it clear that Frege’s identification
does not resist all linguistic replacements (1990: 170-171). If the sentence ‘What
he affirms is true’ had the same sense as ‘What he affirms is a fact,’ then the
replacement of ‘what he affirms’ with ‘his affirmation’ should be allowed without
any change of sense. But, ‘His affirmation is true’ preserves the meaning, while
‘His affirmation is a fact’ makes sense only as a meta-linguistic sentence referring
to the occurrence of his affirmation, and not to the content of the affirmation
itself. The reason for this can only be that the true content of an affirmation
– the Fregean thought – cannot be properly identified with a fact.
The main reason why Frege believed that a fact is a true thought is that he advocated a conception
of truth as redundancy, rejecting
the correspondence theory. However, on the one hand, his arguments against
correspondence theory (1918: 59-60) are unconvincing.[42] On the other hand, correspondence
theory remains the prima facie most plausible
view. It is the most natural and historically influential conception of truth, suggesting
that propositions or thoughts are true when they correspond to facts as arrangements
of elements in the world (Rasmussen 2014; Vision 2004). Moreover, the view of truth
as correspondence is commonsensical, agreeing with our methodological principle
of the primacy of common knowledge. Because of this, I will defend this theory in
the last chapter of this book.
Finally, I think I have found a plausible way
to explain why some are tempted to say that facts are true thoughts. It seems that
the source of confusion resides in a persistent ambiguity of our own natural language.
Dictionaries in very different languages present us a variety of trivial meanings
for the word ‘truth.’ However, two general meanings are almost invariably emphasized.
I call them: thought-truth and fact-truth. Here are their definitions, according
to the best dictionaries:
(a) Thought-truth: Truth as consisting of things
being as we believe they are, as conformity or accordance or correspondence of the
thought with the fact it represents.
(b) Fact-truth: Truth as the actual, real, existing
fact in the world.[43]
It is regarding the philosophically
most proper sense (a) that we have singled out the thought as the primary bearer
of truth. This usage is shown clearly in sentences like ‘His words are true,’ ‘Tell
me the truth.’ In the factual sense (b), we single out facts in the world as secondary
truth-bearers in the sense of being real,
and we use sentences like ‘The mentioned occurrence was true (was real),’ ‘We are
searching for the true facts (the real facts),’ ‘The truth (the fact) is out there.’
The possibility of more adequate semantic replacements indicates the derivative
character of fact-truths.
As we have already seen, there are good reasons
to think that sense (a) is primary while sense (b) is derivative, since in this
last case we can replace the word ‘truth’ with more adequate ones like ‘reality,’
‘existence,’ ‘actuality’… Anyway, ‘truth’ is
very often used not only as ‘correspondence with facts’ but also replacing
‘an existing fact in the world.’ Thus, we can easily be misled by some extraneous motivation
and confuse the two usages, mistakenly concluding that facts are true thoughts. This
is what seems to have originated Frege’s confusion, giving us another example of
equivocity as a common way of transgressing the internal limits of language (Ch.
III, sec. 11).
32. The thought as
a verifiability rule
As the application of the ascription
rule (sense of the predicate) is subsidiary to the application of the identification
rule (sense of the nominative term), the rule for applying the singular sentence
(its sense or thought) can be seen as an association of semantic-cognitive rules.
Ernst Tugendhat has identified this association with the verifiability rule in the
case of the singular predicative statement (1976: 259, 484, 487-8), which
implies the suggestion that this view can be generalized to all meaningful
statements (See 1983: 235-6). Indeed, if the thought is an association of rules,
then what results from such an association – the verifiability rule – must also
have the character of a rule, even if it isn’t something previously conventionalized. Combining this with our acceptance
of the correspondence view of truth and our salvaging of the fact as the
universal truth-maker, this means that the thought should be a kind of associated
or combined semantic-cognitive rule – a verifiability
rule – whose function is to make us aware of a corresponding fact to which it is
applied.[44]
This reasoning
unavoidably leads us back to the controversial idea of ‘verificationism,’
more precisely (and still worse) to semantic
verificationism: the doctrine first
proposed by Wittgenstein, according to which the (cognitive, informative) sense
of a sentence is the rule or method or procedure used in its verification (1980:
29). As it is well-known, Wittgenstein’s idea was soon appropriated by the philosophers
of logical positivism. However, after varied attempts to give it a precise formulation,
it was in the end abandoned due to strong criticism, internal and external to the
logical-positivist circle,
which led to it being considered by many as unsustainable. This is presently the
received view, even if sophisticated philosophers have never really abandoned the
idea that some form or other of verificationism is indispensable (Cf. Misak 1995). Indeed, in the next chapter
of this book I intend to offer replies to the main objections that philosophers
have made against semantic verificationism, showing that these objections were not
directed against its correct form, but rather against a straw-man called the ‘principle of verifiability,’
as it was wrongly construed by logical positivists.
I am introducing semantic verificationism in
this chapter speculatively, as an alternative and in fact as the most natural way
to analyze Frege’s discovery of the thought as the cognitive sense (epistemic value,
informative content) of a sentence. Now, suppose
that the combined semantic-cognitive rule that constitutes the thought as expressed
in an assertoric sentence is its verifiability rule, as complex as it may be. Then the
verifiability rule in itself is the most proper truth-bearer. Then, if we show that
this verifiability sense-thought rule is effectively applicable to the expected
fact, this makes the rule true, which allows us to say derivatively that the sentence
expressing it is also true. If, on the other hand, we show that this thought-sense-rule,
though conceivable, isn’t effectively applicable to the expected fact, this makes
it false and likewise the sentence expressing it. Moreover, if we cannot formulate
a verifiability rule able to be at least in principle applicable to the fact, if
we cannot even conceive its application, we must conclude that the declarative sentence
is devoid of meaning, devoid of sense or thought, even if it may in some cases seem
to have meaning.
I think that this way to understand the truth
of a thought is in line with Frege’s remark that although he regarded truth as the property of a thought,
it does not seem to be a property in the usual sense of the word (Frege 1918: 61).
Indeed, truth does not add anything to the combined
cognitive rule called ‘the thought,’ except something dispositional, namely, its
effective applicability as a verifiability rule in the appropriate context for its
application. Moreover, the proposed identity between the Fregean
concept of thought and the concept of a verifiability rule is also supported by
the Fregean proposal that the identification criterion for what belongs to a thought
is that it must have at least some role
in the establishment of the thought’s truth-value.[45]
33. Frege’s Platonism
It is important to remember that
for Frege thoughts and the senses that compose them are Platonic entities belonging
to a third ontological realm, which is neither psychological nor physical (Frege
1918). For him, taking (a) the criterion of objectivity as being inter-subjectivity
and independence of will, and taking (b) the criterion of reality as existence
in space and time, we combine them in order to get three ontological realms:
1. Realm
of the objective and real
2. Realm
of the subjective and real
3. Realm
of the objective but non-real
The first realm is that of physical
entities such as concrete objects, which are objective and real. These entities
satisfy criteria (a) and (b): they are objective, since they are interpersonally
accessible and independent of our will, and they are real since they are located
in space and time. The second realm is that of psychological entities, mental states
that he calls representations (Frege uses the word ‘Vorstellungen’ in a way
that could be easily translated as qualia).
These entities satisfy criterion (b) but not (a): they are subjective and real.
By not being interpersonally accessible, they are subjective and often dependent
on the will. However, they are still real, because they are in the mind and, consequently,
in time and (we can add) space. There is, finally, a third realm, that of thoughts
(propositions) and their constitutive senses. This realm satisfies criterion (a)
but not (b). For Frege thoughts are objective but not real. Thoughts are
objective, because, true or false, they are always interpersonally accessible: we
can all agree, for example, that the Pythagorean Theorem expresses a true thought
in Euclidean geometry. However, this third realm of thoughts is not real, because
according to him thoughts are abstract things that cannot be found in space or time.
Thus, the thought (the sense) of Pythagoras’ theorem is objective but non-real.
There are, however, problems. One of them,
noted by Frege, is that although for him thoughts are eternal (timeless), immutable,
forever true or false, and not created but only grasped (gefasst) by us, they must have some kind of causal effect: they must be able to cause our grasping them in order to make
judgments and act in the external world (Frege 1918: 77). How this interaction with
something non-spatiotemporal is possible remains an unexplained mystery.
Frege was aware of the difficulties, but the
main reason why he felt he had to introduce this third realm of thoughts is that
thoughts are interpersonally accessible, that is, they are objective, which makes
them able to be communicable. Representations (Vorstellungen), on the other hand, are rather subjective psychological
states that can vary depending on personal psychology and according to him could
never become interpersonally accessible and therefore are not communicable. Thus,
for him the right way to explain how it is possible that we are able to share the
same thoughts in conversation is to strictly distinguish thoughts from mere psychological
representations, placing them in a supposedly shareable Platonic realm. In addition,
if thoughts were on the level of representations, they would be dependent on changeable
personal psychology and would lack their required stability as truth-bearers.
34. Avoiding Frege’s
Platonism
Despite the above-suggested arguments,
few today would accept Frege’s appeal to Platonism. After all, the Fregean form
of Platonism not only commits us to an infinite multiplication of objective entities
(all the infinite variety of true and false thoughts and their constitutive senses)
but also seems to lack intelligibility. The price that Frege was willing to pay
in order to avoid psychological subjectivism seems too high for
us today.
In my judgment, if we understand senses as
rules, which usually are implicitly established conventions or something
derived from them, there is a clear way to bring the empiricist view of thoughts
as having a psychological-empirical nature in line with the view that as truth-bearers
they must have stability and the possibility of being communicated. In order to
establish this conclusion, I want to apply again the same strategy inspired by the
ontological particularism of English empiricists, which I used in the construction
of universals by means of tropes.[46] This is understandable since
according to trope ontology, a thought should be made up of, at least dispositional,
internal tropes: the mental tropes constitutive of some conventionally grounded
verifiability rule whose application is at least conceivable. In order to accomplish
this, I need only show that something like Fregean Platonic thoughts (objective
non-real truth-bearers…), which I call f-thoughts (‘f’ from Fregean) can be defined
in terms of psychological (real and subjective) p-thoughts (‘p’ from psychological),
though typically based on intersubjective linguistic conventions. In other words,
I suggest that we can warrant the existence and stability of f-thoughts without
hypostasizing them as Platonic entities and even without resorting to classes of
p-thoughts if we replace them with what I call extensible thoughts or e-thoughts.
We can do this by means of the following disjunctive definition, which is as simple
as it is efficacious:
An e-thought (Df)
= a given tropical p-thought X* (used as the model) embodied in some mind
or any other tropical p-thought Y qualitatively identical to X*, embodied
in the same mind or in any other mind.
The e-thought is our empiricist
version of what Frege should have meant with his f-thought (objective non-real thought).
The p-thought X* can be any X thought that someone decides to use as a model. The aim of this definition
of an e-thought is that any supposed f-thought is reduced to mental p-thoughts without
depriving it of its epistemic objectivity (mainly inter-subjectivity) grounded on
conventional rules, along with its expected stability or immutability. This procedure
works at least insofar as my criticism of the private language argument is acceptable,
though I have no doubts about this (See Ch. III, sec. 13).
The so defined e-thought – which is the same
as a verifiability rule, a tropical thought-content or simply a proposition – though usually distributed across space and time, doesn’t
need to have any particular spatiotemporal location and can be seen as the most
proper truth-bearer. For example: the e-thought or e-thought-content or e-thought-content-rule
expressed by the sentence ‘The Eiffel Tour is made of iron’ can be instantiated
as the p-thought that I have in mind when writing this sentence. However, it can
also be instantiated by, say, the p-thought that you have in mind when you read
it, such as by any qualitatively identical p-thought that I, we, or any other person
can have at any place or time, insofar as it is considered
an f-thought, namely, a model for any qualitatively identical p-thoughts. Characterized
by the disjunction between qualitatively identical thoughts embodied in individual
minds, the e-thought is apt to be regarded in abstraction from any particular
human mind that causally instantiates it. This is what really occurs when we think
an f-thought, and it is this abstraction from singular human minds resulting
from the spreading character of the real thought-contents that gave Frege the impression
that he had found a Platonic entity outside of space and time.
As with model-tropes in the construction of
universals, it is not necessary to have only one particular model as the object
of interpersonal consideration. To the contrary, what we need to do is simply to
single out the first thought given to us by memory and use it arbitrarily as a model:
first the one, and then any other that we recognize as being precisely (qualitatively)
identical to the first, and we can choose any of them as a new model. In some way
language is only the vehicle of communication that allows the reproduction of qualitatively
identical psychological p-thoughts in the minds of hearers, insofar as they are
rooted in the usually implicit interpersonal conventions we have attached to their
semantic components. Since p-thoughts are tropes, we have simply applied to p-thoughts
the same strategy we applied to singular tropes, as we needed to construct
universals based on them. The e-thought verifiability rules are p-thoughts read
as universals.
With the help of the above definition, we avoid
not only appealing to psychologically specific occurrences of thoughts, but also
the most expected alternative, which would be to explain one e-thought in terms
of a sum or set of p-thoughts qualitatively identical to each other. This could
lead us not only to the problem of defining sets, but also to the problem that sets
and sums have or could have size, while thoughts cannot. If an e-thought were a
set of p-thoughts, even if considered an open set, it would at the ontological
level grow ever larger, the greater the number of people there were who grasped
it.
Under the proposed definition, in order to
exist, an e-thought must always have at least one psychological occurrence. The
e-thought is not less psychological than any p-thought, since it cannot be considered
independently of its instantiation in at least one mind. This means that
when we say that we both had the same idea, or the same thought, this
is merely a manner of speaking. What we really mean is only that there is a qualitative
identity between the (tropical) psychological verifiability p-thought-contents
rules that we have respectively instantiated in our minds. We share the e-thought
in the sense that we instantiate qualitatively identical p-thoughts. This has the
advantage of bringing Fregean thoughts out of the ethereal Platonic heaven back
to the concrete psychological realm without making any serious commitment to the
transient psychology of individual minds.
This understanding of the true nature of thought-contents
explains something that Frege was unable to explain satisfactorily, namely, why
and how they may have causal powers. Since as an open disjunction of p-thoughts,
e-thoughts only exist as psychological instantiations of p-thoughts, this enables
them to play a causal role: they can cause other psychological states and, combined
with desires, human actions and their effects in the external world.
At this point one could raise an objection
of multiple realizability: the same p-thought could be differently realized in different
human brains, making the qualitative identity of p-thoughts impossible. I agree
with the very probable multiple realizability of p-thoughts but disagree that this
makes their qualitative identity impossible. There is no reason why we cannot present
things that can be considered qualitatively identical on a linguistic or even psychological
level and different on a neurophysiological level, in the same way as different
devices can have different internal mechanisms and perform exactly the same tasks.[47] Moreover, my suggestion is
that e-thoughts are constituted of p-thoughts that are internal tropical verifiability
rules, which although complex, ramified and variable, are also able to be satisfied
by foreseeable independent tropical configurations.
In my judgment, one of the most unyielding
and deceitful philosophical errors in ontology has always been seeing numerical identity where there is only
qualitative identity. It is true that we can ask for the meaning of the
general term ‘chair’ using the definite article ‘the’ in the phrase ‘the chair.’ But this is only a linguistic
device that changes nothing! In a similar way, we can speak of the geometrical form of circularity, and
of the number 2 in the singular… But this
is just for the sake of simplicity of expression. What we are ultimately able to have in mind in all these
cases are occurrences of qualitatively identical meanings, that is, of qualitatively
identical concepts of chairs, circles, and cognitive arithmetical concepts of duality, and not something more, since we don’t need
something more to get something more.[48] In the same way, we can talk
about the thought expressed by ‘12 x 12
= 144,’ but if we do not intend a specific occurrence of this thought, we are only
referring to some occurrence, but without
taking into account or having to specify which occurrence and in what
mind. We speak in the singular of the thought that 12 x 12 = 144 for reasons of simplicity.
The adoption of the definition of e-thoughts
proposed above, which is easily generalizable to all kinds of Fregean senses, seems
to me the only plausible abstraction we can arrive at without committing any of
various forms of reification that have infested ontology throughout its long history.
At this point, a stubborn Fregean defender
can still ask: how is it possible that the psychologically dependent definition
of e-thoughts suggested above could be able to ensure the objectivity of e-thoughts,
their interpersonal accessibility or communicability?
As we saw, Frege concluded that if we regard thoughts as psychological representations,
as is the case with p-thoughts, they would unavoidably be subjective, and we could
not compare them with each other. However, it still seems clear that Frege was too
hasty when he admitted that his f-thoughts belong to a third realm of Platonic entities.
One could note that there is no doubt that what Frege calls representations (phenomenal mental contents) have in fact
possibilities of interpersonal communication, even if limited.[49] But much more important is something that Frege hasn’t considered at all, namely, that senses and
e-thoughts, without being Platonic entities, could be understood as rule-complexes built upon adequate associations of
interpersonally accepted conventions established with the help of public signs that are communicable precisely because of their grounding interpersonal
character. That is, because e-thoughts are verifiability rules rooted in
linguistically shareable interpersonal conventions, they can well be able to satisfy
Frege’s demand for objectivity as interpersonal accessibility followed by the possibility
of communication and truth-evaluation.
It may, at first sight, seem implausible that
language is capable of repeatedly being reproduced in other minds and even in the
same mind with the same subjective
pattern, the same thought-content, the same recognizable instantiation of an adequate
association of conventionally established semantic-cognitive rules attached to our
words. However, compare by analogy this case with that of genetic information able to endlessly reproduce the
same characteristics in successive biological individuals.[50] Why cannot the conventions
and ways they can be combined in the constitution
of p-thoughts do a similar job, even if only inferentially?
More than this (and probably also in the case of genetic information), it is easy to suppose that there are corrective mechanisms
able to interpersonally and intra-personally impose a limit on divergence
from conventionalized standards (See Ch. V, sec. 11). There is no reason, except
an anti-empiricist bias, to think that things could not be that way.
Finally, let us apply to e-thoughts John Searle’s
important distinction between what is ontologically objective/subjective
and what is epistemologically objective/subjective (Searle 1999:
43-45). Searle noted that we have a strong tendency to take what is epistemologically
subjective for what is only ontologically subjective. However, something can be ontologically objective
– for instance, ‘How justifiable was the First World War?’ – without ceasing to
be epistemologically subjective, because it is not easy to reach a common agreement
about this issue. In contrast, a phenomenon can be ontologically subjective without
ceasing to be epistemologically objective – for instance, the stabbing pain caused by a seizure of acute
pancreatitis – because everyone (doctors and patients alike) will agree on the
form and existence of this pain, even if the patient alone knows exactly how it
feels.
Something of the kind can also be said not
only of Fregean subjective mental representations, but also of e-thoughts. In themselves they are ontologically
subjective, since we admit that they are
psychological events instantiated in one mind or another. But even so, they do not
cease to be epistemologically objective, since we are capable of interpersonally
agreeing about them and their truth-values. We
can agree that an objectively assertoric sentence like ‘The Eiffel Tower
is made of metal’ expresses a true e-thought that is epistemologically objective, even though as an e-thought ontologically subjective, since
it is distributed among the minds of those who think it. Like any e-thought, it
remains epistemologically objective, given that it is grounded on conventions associating
words with things in the world, which makes it fully measurable and communicable.
An arithmetical sentence like ‘2 + 3 = 5’ is epistemologically objective (since
we are all able to inter-subjectively agree on its truth-value), but it also expresses
an ontologically subjective e-thought, and as I tried to show in speaking of numbers, it seems to
be a thin kind of tropical arrangement sustained by lower-order tropes. On the other
hand, a sentence like ‘Love is the Amen of the universe’ (Novalis), unlike an e-thought,
has no truth-value. It is only suggestive and expressive. Like poetry, it is based
on non-conventional subjective coloration, being susceptible only to emotive-aesthetic
appreciation with differing degrees of subjective interpersonal agreement.
Regarding ontology, Frege was no exception.
Like Husserl, Bolzano and several other continental philosophers of his time with
mathematical training, he believed that the ontologically subjective character of
psychologically conceived thought-contents would inevitably be condemned to epistemological
subjectivity. But this was a mistake.
35. Further ontological
consequences
Our ultimately psychological reformulation
of Fregean thoughts has some interesting ontological consequences. If the thought
of the Pythagorean Theorem isn’t an eternal (timeless) entity belonging to a Platonic
realm, always true or false, where and when does it exist? The answer is that if
there is at least one occurrence of its thought or any other qualitatively identical
occurrence, regardless of the bearer, something like the Pythagorean theorem acquires
an existence dependent on minds. It is not an existence dependent on any of the
many particular minds that will eventually think it since it would continue to exist
without having been thought by this or that particular mind. In fact, since this
thought has been thought by both you and me and certainly by many others in the
past, its existence must be spread over space
and time. It must be distributed over the space and time occupied by the heads
of mathematicians starting with Pythagoras himself and perhaps ending in the head
of some cognitive being at some unknown future time. This is what gives the impression
that the thought is something abstract,
beyond the psychological realm.
Another consequence of the proposed view is
that unlike the Platonic entity that Frege called a ‘thought,’ our e-thought of
the Pythagorean theorem did not in fact exist before Pythagoras thought it for the
first time (supposing he was the first), and will cease to exist if it ceases to
be thought by anyone. The Pythagorean theorem certainly exists, has existed and
will continue to exist in the sense that
it is thought, has been thought and will probably be thought in the future, referring
to occurrences of this thought, but without having to take into account who thinks
it.
One could object that this result sounds strange:
it seems that the Pythagorean Theorem applies independently of minds. However, this strangeness
can be softened by the fact that nobody can truly deny it. One cannot have the true
thought, ‘The theorem according to which the sum of the squares of the shorter sides
of a right triangle equals the square of the hypotenuse has been thought in the
past and now is no longer thinkable.’ And the reason is that this judgment will
already be an occurrence of the thought of the Pythagorean Theorem and insofar will falsify what it states.
Anyway, the conclusion remains that the e-thought of this theorem would not have
come into existence if nobody had ever thought it. Putting this more incisively:
it would not exist in a world without cognitive beings.
The last remark suggests the following objection.
Imagine a possible world Ww similar to
ours, with planets, stars, and galaxies, but without any cognitive being. In Ww the e-thoughts that there are planets,
stars and galaxies could not have been thought and, e-thoughts, being the primary bearers of truth, could not be true. Nevertheless, it seems very
reasonable to think that in this world the fact that there are planets, stars and
galaxies would still be true, even though
there would be no cognitive Beings to think this.
It seems to me that the right answer to the
strangeness is that here we are again victims of a confusion between thought-truth
and fact-truth. As we saw, the first is the truth applied to the primary bearer
of the truth, which is the e-thought, while the second is a derivative but very
common application of truth to the real existing thing or fact in the world, as
a secondary bearer of truth, meaning a real thing or fact. Indeed, that there would
be planets, stars and galaxies in a mindless world would still be true as
a fact in Ww. Hence, the applicability of the Pythagorean Theorem would still
be a fact-truth in Ww, even though neither
their e-thoughts nor their truth in the form of correspondence would exist. The
flexibility of natural language has once again misled us.
Still another objection that could be made
against the idea that the bearers of truth are non-Platonic e-thoughts is the following.
Many truths have been discovered. Pythagoras
is credited with discovering the theorem that bears his name; Archimedes was one
of the discoverers of the law of the lever, according to which magnitudes are in
equilibrium at distances inversely proportional to their weights. However, if something
is discovered, then logically it must have existed before being discovered. Consequently,
the above-described thoughts must already have existed before their discovery.
Again, the answer is that this naïve objection
results from a confusion between the thought as the primary bearer of truth on the
one hand, and the fact as a derived bearer of truth on the other. This is clear
in the case of typical empirical truths. That the law of the lever was always applicable
in principle is surely true. However, this is only a general fact-truth!
Its thought-truth was only part of the empirical (mental) world after scientists
like Archimedes conceived it. Similarly, common sense tells us that the fact expressed
by the Pythagorean Theorem must always have existed. However, our e-thought of it
only came into existence after the theorem was thought by Pythagoras and since then
has been thought by many others. Real facts, on their turn, as long lasting as they
may be, are not the primary bearers of truth, but rather their truth-makers or verifiers.
They exist independently and are said to be true only in the derived sense (b) of
fact-truths, not in the sense (a) of thought-truths. They are what occurrences of
their thoughts represent. Hence, in the most proper and demanding sense, no truths or falsehoods would
exist in a world where there were no minds to think them. The most we could think
of in this direction is to say that if the law of the lever were thought in Ww, it would be recognized as true.
An e-thought that has never been thought does
not exist and thus cannot be true. The same holds for falsehoods. Consider the thought ‘The Colossus
of Rhodes is floating in the Sargasso Sea.’ In all probability this thought has never been thought before
the present moment. But the moment we think that it has never been thought before,
we are already thinking it, and we can even attribute falsehood to it. Even the e-thought ‘The
world could exist, even if there were no minds to think about it’ is only a true
thought insofar as there are minds to think it.
36. A short digression
on contingent futures
Before we finish, it
is interesting to examine the Aristotelian problem of contingent futures in the
light of our conclusions (1984, vol. 1, De
Interpretatione, sec. 9). According to a plausible interpretation of Aristotle,
the following argument is valid:
Argument A
1. Necessarily, it is true or false that there
will be a sea-battle tomorrow.
2. If (1) is true, then the future is predetermined
and there are no chance events.
3. Therefore, the future is fixed and there are
no chance events.
It seems that for Aristotle this
conclusion would be unacceptable, because if the future were predetermined, then
there would be no chance events, and if there were no chance events, there would
be no free will. Hence, according to a traditional interpretation, he thought that although this argument is sound,
premise (1) is false because it exemplifies the principle of bivalence, and the
principle of bivalence – according to which any significant proposition is either
true or false – is not applicable to future events (only to present and past ones).
I cannot agree with this conclusion, since
I believe that we should preserve a strongly understood principle of bivalence for
e-thoughts.[51]
But premise (1) can be questioned from a different perspective. Suppose, first,
that outside any context we consider the
e-thought expressed by the sentence ‘There will be a sea battle tomorrow,’ which
we can abbreviate as ├p. Is this statement true or false? The answer is the
following: if taken literally, ├p is unable
to express any e-thought because a verifiability e-thought rule is something to
which we must possibly attribute a truth-value. Normally ‘There will be a sea battle
tomorrow’ is an incomplete indexical statement, so that without any further contextual
information we are totally at a loss for the task of associating p with any appropriate truth-maker in order
to assign it a truth-value.
Moreover, one could argue that the sentence
├p (as much as ├~p) is misleading
and causes confusion, like argument A, because ├p only seems to express
cognitive thought-content. The reason for this is that ├p is very easily
confused with the meaningful sentence
├p*: ‘[It is likely that] a sea-battle will take place tomorrow,’
stated when there are reasons to think
so. For example: having broken Japanese naval codes and having lured the Japanese
fleet into an ambush at Midway, the Americans already knew on the night of June
3, 1942, that on June 4 there would almost certainly be a major naval battle. The
sentence ├p* is easily confused with ├p, because ├p* is almost always abbreviated as ├p: ‘A sea-battle will
take place tomorrow.’
For example: suppose that American Admiral
Nimitz had said on June 3:
Tomorrow there will be a sea-battle.
Everyone would understand that
he was saying that all the factual evidence was leading to the conclusion that the
expected battle would begin on June 4. This probability – made explicit or not –
is in this case objectively measurable in terms of verification by actual empirical
evidence, so that the assertion ├p* expresses an e-thought that is held to
be true, for it is true that, with the information already available, it was very
probable that a sea-battle would occur the next day. Indeed, the utterance ‘It is
likely that a naval battle will take place tomorrow’ could be regarded as definitely true on the night of June 3, 1942, without violating any principle of
bivalence!
Suppose now, by contrast, that I am standing
on the calm beach of Praia Bonita in Northeastern Brazil, looking out across the
Atlantic Ocean, and without any reason I say ├q*: ‘A naval battle will take place in this region tomorrow,’
meaning by it ‘It is likely that a naval battle will take place in this region tomorrow.’
This statement can be regarded as definitely
false, since there are many different
reasons to believe that this kind of event is extremely improbable in this region
and at this time.
The conclusion is that in the absence of a
context (and not in the above senses of ├p* or ├q*), the statement ├p would be a linguistic bluff devoid of any meaning or justification. Aristotle would
be right in rejecting the application of the principle of bivalence to it, not because
this principle has exceptions, but simply because it expresses no e-thought, no
proposition, no verifiability rule. All that this sentence does is to induce us
to imagine a naval battle that takes place tomorrow, as if there were hidden verifiability
criteria. However, insofar as no context is furnished, no real criteria can be given.
Statements like ├p*,├~p* and ├q*, on the other hand, aim to say something
probabilistic about the future that can be confirmed and made true by criterial
reasons already found in the present. But from such statements premise (2) and the
conclusion (3) of the argument A do not follow, because all that such statements can warrant, if true,
is the inductive probability of a sea-battle.
The upshot is that the metaphysical riddle
about contingent futures can be eliminated if we consider with enough care what
we are really able to mean by affirming e-thoughts regarding the future.
37. Conclusion
My first aim in this chapter was
to insert in the framework of Fregean semantics the results of my reconstruction
of Wittgenstein’s view of (cognitive) meaning as given by the application of
semantic-cognitive rules in order to better distinguish the most relevant forms
of meaning-rules and their functions. This insertion requires strong corrections
in Frege’s own framework. Even if the results are complex and could only be sketched
here, they nonetheless seem to me clearly more auspicious than Frege’s own original
views.
Appendix to Chapter IV
Frege, Russell, and the Puzzles
of Reference
Too much perfection
is a mistake.
—Alexandro Jodorowski
Bertrand Russell conceived his theory of descriptions as
a way to solve so-called puzzles of reference. Frege’s theory of sense suggests
a very different way to solve the same puzzles. While these two alternative solutions
are usually assumed to be irreconcilable, each of them has its own appeal. Considering
this, my proposal is that the best way to deal with this contrast is not by means
of dispute, but by means of reconciliation. I will show that we can reach this reconciliation
by salvaging the truth in each solution and discarding the falsity, justifying in
this way their resilient appeal. More specifically, I will proceed first by removing
the metaphysical load from each of these views and then by showing that with the
help of appropriate adjustments, a bridge between Russell’s and Frege’s solutions
will be built making them fully compatible, since they are only two different ways
of saying the same thing.
1. Russell’s solutions
to puzzles of reference
I will first present Russell’s
four puzzles and his solutions by means of his theory of descriptions (Russell 1905:
479-493; 1919, Ch. XVI).
(i) Reference to the non-existent: Consider first a statement whose grammatical
subject does not refer to anything, ‘The present King of France is bald.’ How can
we attribute baldness to someone who does
not exist?
Russell’s response is that this problem only
arises when we understand a definite description like (1) ‘the present King of France’
as a referential expression functioning as a proper name. But we can easily show
that it actually does not function in this way. Letting K abbreviate ‘…is a present
King of France’ and letting B abbreviate the predicate ‘…is bald,’ the theory of
descriptions allows us to symbolize the ‘The present King of France is bald’ as
(2) ‘(Ǝx) [(Kx & (y) (Ky → y
= x)) & Bx].’ Or, to use an intuitively clearer formulation, we get the following
false sentence:
(3) There is at least
one x and at most one x, such that
x is a present King of France and x is bald.
In these last two formulations,
one thing is clear: there is no baldness predicated of a present King of France.
When the definite description ‘the present King of France’ is replaced by quantified
predicates, it becomes clear that we do not need to assume the existence of any
present King of France to whom we should apply the predicate baldness. Moreover,
since the first statement of the conjunction is false, the whole statement must
be false.
(ii) Negative Existential:
The second puzzle concerns the apparent impossibility of denying the existence of
an object when the expression that denies the existence is about the same object.
The problem assumes a striking form when we consider the following two statements:
1. The
present King of France does not exist.
2. Statement
(1) is about the present King of France.
Both statements seem to be true.
However, they are mutually inconsistent. If statement (2) is true because it claims
that statement (1) is about the present King of France, (1) must be false and vice
versa.
Russell solves the riddle by suggesting that
statement (2) is false. In order to show this, he interprets the negation in statement
(1) as possessing wide scope in relation to the definite description. The analyzed
form of statement (1) is (3) ~(Ǝx) [Kx & (y) (Ky
→ y = x)]; more intuitively:
4.
It is not the case that there is at least one x and at most one x, such that x is a present King of France.
This is a true sentence since it is the negation of a false conjunction. However,
it does not commit us to the existence of the present King of France, since it only
commits us to denying the existence of at least one and at most one thing that has
the property of being a present King of France.
(iii) Identity Statements: A third puzzle is the Fregean paradox
of identity. Consider the statement: (1) ‘The author of Waverley is Scott.’ It contains two referential expressions, both referring
to the same object. But if this is so, then statement (1) should be tautological,
stating the same thing as (2) ‘Scott is Scott.’ However, we definitely know that
(1) is a contingent and informative statement and not a tautology. Why?
Once more, Russell’s solution is to make the
definite description disappear. Letting s
abbreviate the name ‘Scott,’ w abbreviate
‘Waverley’ and A abbreviate the two-place
predicate ‘…is the author of…,’ we can paraphrase the identity statement (1) as
(3) ‘(Ǝx) [Axw & (y)
(Ayw → y = x) & (x = s)].’ More intuitively:
4. There is precisely
one x who is the author of Waverley, and this x is Scott.
From these last two formulations,
it is clear that (1) is an informative statement since there is no doubt that its
analyzed form (4) is an informative statement, very different from (2).
(iv) Intentional context:
A final riddle that the theory of descriptions is expected to solve is that of inter-substitutability
in statements of propositional attitudes.
These statements express relational states connecting a mental attitude expressed
by verbs like ‘believe,’ ‘desire,’ ‘hope,’ ‘think,’ ‘want’… to what I here prefer
to call a thought-content (e-thought, proposition). Consider, for instance, the
two following statements:
(1) George IV believes that Scott is Scott.
(2) George IV believes that the author of Waverley is Scott.
Statement (1) is true since George
IV was certainly able to apply the principle of identity to a proper name. However,
since the name ‘Scott’ and the description ‘the author of Waverley’ refer to the same person, it seems that here we can apply
the principle of identity substitution. It seems that we can replace the first occurrence
of the word ‘Scott’ in statement (1) with the description ‘the author of Waverley,’ obtaining statement (2), ‘George
IV believes that the author of Waverley
is Scott,’ so that (2) will preserve the truth-value true. However, this does not
happen: it may well be that statement (2) is false simply because George IV does
not know that the author of Waverley is
Scott, despite the obvious truth of (1). Why is this so?
In order to answer such objections Russell
uses his theory of descriptions, paraphrasing (at least in relevant cases) (2) with
statement (3) ‘George IV believes that Ǝx
[Axw & (y) (Ayw → y= x) & (x =
s)].’ More intuitively, we can express (3) as:
4. George IV believes that there is at least one
x and at most one x, such that x is the author of Waverley
and that this x is Scott.
Certainly, this is an informative
belief, clearly distinct from the tautological belief that Scott is Scott. This
is why George IV can believe in (1) and disbelieve (2).
2. Fregean solutions
to the same puzzles
Frege has explicit answers to the
last two puzzles of reference. As for the first two, we can only presume how should
be the Fregean solutions.
(i) Reference to the non-existent:
Frege suggested that in a scientific language a singular term without reference
could refer to an empty set. If we try to apply this suggestion to natural language,
the sentence:
(1) The present King of France is bald,
should be false, since the empty set isn’t bald. However, in addition
to being arbitrary, this suggestion would lead to absurd conclusions, such as that
the statement ‘Pegasus = the present King of France’ is true, since both singular
terms, ‘Pegasus’ and ‘the present King of France’ refer to the same thing, namely,
the empty set.
The alternative I would like to propose starts
from the notion that we can say things about non-existents insofar as the corresponding
empty singular terms still preserve their senses, that is, their identification
rules, even if only roughly sketched. Once we have these senses-rules in mind, we
are still able to say something about their objects, not as real ones, but merely as conceivable ones. This is the case of the present King
of France, a title which has a sense-rule, allowing us to apply it only in our imagination, thinking of
France today as a Kingdom like Belgium... In this way, we are still able to articulate
in rehearsal the sense-rule of the predicate with the sense-rule of the singular
term. This allows us to understand Frege’s sentence (i) ‘Odysseus, while sleeping,
was set ashore in Ithaca,’ which has no real reference, but only an imaginable one.
According to Frege’s view, the thought-content
of a sentence such as (i) should have no truth-value: since if a part of a thought
(Odysseus) has no reference, the thought as a whole is also devoid of reference,
devoid of truth-value (1892: 32-33). P. F. Strawson influentially supported this
view, considering such statements to have what some today call ‘truth-value gaps’
(Cf. Strawson 1971: 85). This view is
opposed to that of Russell’s theory of descriptions, according to which statements
such as (i) must be false, as for him
‘Odysseus’ should be the abbreviation of a bundle of definite descriptions without
reference.[52] (Cf. Russell 1912, Ch. 5)
As to the question of the truth-value of statements
without reference, after more than half a century of disputes, it seems to me clear
that the strongest arguments favor Russell. First, it seems definitional that a
proposition (e-thought-content-rule) is the kind of thing that for intrinsic reasons
given by its function of saying something
that has a minimal amount of informative usefulness must be able to have a known
or at least an unknown but in some way possibly known truth-value. Second, although
one might doubt that the statement ‘The present King of France is wise’ (Strawson)
is false, just a little reflection will show that it is more reasonable to view
it as false. Consider, first, examples of statements in which the singular term
is also empty, but which have predicates that have more weight – defining ‘weight’
as the power of semantically attract our attention – either
because they have a more complex semantic structure or because they are particularly
relevant or curious or puzzling. Some examples:
1. I saw the present King of France strolling on
the beach last week.
2. The present King of France has forbidden tourists
to visit the Palace of Versailles.
3. Yesterday the present King of France was inebriated
and therefore unable to perform his official duties.
4. The present King of France visited me this afternoon
and we had the opportunity to discuss the EU’s inability to solve European problems.
5. The present King of France is sitting on that
chair.
These statements are all intuitively
perceived as false, and it seems that the reason lies in the weight of the expressions
complementing the descriptions: they force us to pay attention to their complex
and curious predicative informational content (1 to 4) or to something that would
attract great attention if it were not glaringly false (5). We see them as false
because we pay attention to the non-applicability of the predicate.
Moreover, when we say ‘The present King of
France does not exist’ (the denial of
the presupposition), this statement is obviously true. However, statements like
this should lack truth-value according to a Strawsonian presuppositional analysis.[53]
Additional evidence for this point is the following
statement considered by Stephen Neale:[54]
6. The present King of France isn’t wise, because
there is no present King of France.
Statement (6) seems intuitively
true. But (6) could not be true if the statement ‘The present King of France is
wise’ were not really false. If it had
no truth-value, all of statement (6) would also be devoid of truth-value.
As some have seen (Russell 1957, III; Sainsbury
1979: 118; Blackburn 1984: 309-10), the reason why the statement ‘The present King
of France is wise,’ chosen by Strawson, appears to lack truth-value is only a pragmatic one. This reason can be explained as follows. First, we normally regard
a statement as false because its predicative expression does not apply while we
assume that the singular term applies; for instance, the statement ‘Bertrand Russell
was bald’ is obviously false since this is a standard case of a predicate that does
not apply to its subject. This is the expected case. However, we are not used to
considering the truth-value of singular statements when the singular term has no
reference, since these statements only rarely appear in our language for the simple
reason that it is pointless to ascribe properties to something that does not exist!
This is why we hesitate to say Strawson’s statement ‘The present King of France
is wise’ is false; our first reaction is to see it as a misunderstanding if not
a statement devoid of sense or pointless. However, strictly speaking, the statement
is false. Or, more weakly expressed, in this case the language-in-use has nothing
to tell. And we can suggest that Russell’s formal analysis exposes a universal deep
layer of our natural language that sometimes seems to us artificial in the same
way as the material implication exposes a universal deep layer of our natural language
that often seems artificial only because it is superposed by other layers in almost
all linguistically effective practical uses. Consequently, Strawson’s example provides
no argument against the much stronger reasonableness of the decision to generalize,
treating all statements with void singular
term in the same way, namely, as false.
Moreover, statements that put weight on the
predicative expression or on what is said complementarily to the definite description,
like (1), (2), (3), (4) and (5), are seen by us as patently false. Why? Not because
they belong to a different category, as some would like to believe. Their falsity
is clear to us because of their predicative weight. They motivate us to pay attention
to their predicative or relational expressions as being clearly inapplicable, in
this way satisfying our usual criterion of falsity for singular statements. However,
the ultimate cause of this inapplicability is still the same as in Strawson’s examples:
there is no object for them to be applied to in order to make the whole statement
possibly true. By contrast, statements like:
7. The present King of France is slipping.
8. The present King of France is a dunce.
9. The present King of France is a human being.
do not seem to have any truth-value.
Why? Because their predicates have little semantic weight. For this reason, we focus
our attention on the void subject, and since we are not used to extracting falsity
from a statement when the predicate does not apply because its singular term lacks
reference, we tend to see the whole statement as lacking truth-value and being devoid
of sense. However, we can say that they are all false for the same reason, namely,
that we cannot ascribe these predicates to a nothing, since predicate ascription
is also a usual pragmatic criterion for truth attribution.
Furthermore, consider statements that in a
fictional context are undoubtedly true, such as:
10. Santa
Claus has a white beard.
If understood as a statement about
a fictional realm (10) is obviously true. But if understood as a statement about
the real world, (10) would be a statement like (1): a statement that seems to have
no truth-value though it must be false. And with good reason it shows its falsity
when we make a statement with a weightier predication like:
11. I trimmed Santa Claus’s white beard
last Christmas.
It is false because
it suggests that Santa Claus is a man of flesh and blood belonging to our real world.
Since this man doesn’t exist, the predicate cannot apply.
Finally, it is worth noting that we can
possibly construct verifiability rules for these statements, which also shows that
they are meaningful, expressing e-thought-rules. One can consider ways to verify
that there is no bald or wise present King of France, that there is no real Santa
Claus whose beard someone trimmed last Christmas, etc. All the given statements
can be directly or indirectly falsified by the absence of independent external criteria
for the satisfaction of their verifiability rules.
(ii) Negative Existential: It is not so easy to give a Fregean
explanation for the enigma of negative existentials. However, consider the following
statement:
(1) The present King
of France does not exist.
It is true that ‘the present King
of France’ is a definite description that does not refer to anything. But here as
well the description ‘The present King of France’ has at least a conceptual sense, that is, a rough identification rule
whose application can be at least conceived. Now, if existence is the property of
effective applicability of a semantic-cognitive rule in a proper domain or context,
and the identification rule expresses by the description ‘the present King of France’
does not apply to any object in this context, which is here inserted in the fundamental
domain of real things, our conclusion is the following. The e-thought-content-rule
expressed by the assertoric sentence (1) is true, since the predicate ‘…does not
exist’ simply says that the sense, mode of presentation or identification rule of
‘The present King of France’ isn’t satisfied, that is, this rule isn’t applicable to any object in the present
domain of real things, as suggested, though it remains applicable in a conceivable,
merely imaginary domain, which makes the statement sufficiently meaningful.
The same can be said for the denial that the
referent of a proper name exists. If the sense of a proper name, as Frege indirectly
suggested, is the abbreviation of bundles of definite descriptions, or, as I have
defended, the abbreviation of a properly characterized disjunction of fundamental
descriptions, then a similar strategy is applicable to negative existential statements
with empty names. Take for example statements like (i) ‘Vulcan does not exist,’
calling ‘V’ ‘…a small planet circling the sun inside the orbit of Mercury,’ we can
symbolize the sentence (i) as ~Ǝx [Vx & (y) (Vy → y = x)]. What sentence
(i) means is that the conceptual sense expressed by the fundamental descriptions
abbreviated by the name of the small planet ‘Vulcan’ has no effective application in its proper domain, that its identification
rule isn’t satisfied by any real object, which is true.
(iii) Identity Statements: The
riddle of identity between descriptions can be exemplified by the most discussed
sentence of analytic philosophy:
(i) The morning star
is the evening star.
For Frege this identity sentence
is informative because the descriptions ‘the morning star’ and ‘the evening star’
express different senses or modes of presentation of the same object, the first
as the brightest celestial body that appears to us at dawn, and the second as the
brightest celestial body that appears to us in the evening…
As already seen (Ch. IV, sec. 27), particularly
concerning proper names, due to their semantic flexibility, a double answer could
be given depending on different contextual emphases. To make it easier, suppose that we have the proper names ‘Phosphorus’
(Morning Star) and ‘Hesperus’ (Evening Star) building the sentence (ii) ‘Phosphorus
is Hesperus.’ There are two main ways of understanding this sentence, depending
on which semantic element we are emphasizing in accordance with the context:
Immediate-derived Emphasis: In this case, the senses, the
modes of presentation for Phosphorus and Hesperus as their separate identification
rules, are emphasized, Phosphorus being understood as the last star to disappear
at dawn and Hesperus as the first star to appear in the evening... Here the whole
mode of presentation of Venus, which contains both visible stars and is responsible
for their identity, is left in the background, being only the resulting datum of
an identity that we expect to preserve. In this case, the statement is seen as
expressing a derived contingent a posteriori
thought, emphasizing the difference as
opposed to the identity, being this identity informative, since it still informs us in an implicit supplementary way that these two different senses
or identification rules have the same ultimate reference. The derived statement
refers first to the apparent sub-fact
that Phosphorus isn’t Hesperus and only secondarily lets us infer the further grounding
fact of Venus’ self-identity. Its emphasized modal form can be read as ◊ (a = b).
This is how Frege saw the identity.
Mediated-basal emphasis: In this case, with both names
we emphasize that we mean Venus, attaching to both terms the same fundamental localizing
astronomical description (say, the second planet of the solar system, etc.) that
forms an accepted identification rule that has a variety of guises, of ramifications
as modes of presentation, under the assumption of our current astronomical views. Here the descriptions of Venus’ appearances to us
play only the role of irrelevant auxiliary descriptions. Because of this, the sentence
‘Phosphorus is Hesperus’ is here seen as an uninformative analytic identity sentence
– a necessary a priori sentence – even
if it has different fringes of meaning depending on the different auxiliary descriptions
related to different usual modes of presentation. In this case the assertoric sentence
has as its most proper sense the basal thought referring to the grounding fact of Venus’ self-identity,
being expressed by the sentence ‘Venus [in full] = Venus [in full],’ from which
we may derive ‘Phosphorus [-Venus] = Hesperus [-Venus],’ or ‘Phosphorus = Hesperus.’
These statements are necessary a priori,
emphasizing the identity in the difference. Their emphasized modal
form can be rendered as □ (a = b). This is how Saul Kripke chose to see the identity.
As was noted in the last chapter,
Kripke’s necessary a posteriori identity
between proper names is the result of a confusion of the necessity of the mediated-basal
emphasis with the contingency of the immediate-derived emphasis.
(iv)
Intentional contexts: As for the enigma of intentional contexts, Frege suggests
that in statements of propositional attitudes, the subordinate sentence does not
have its usual reference – its truth-value – but rather an indirect reference, which
is its sense. Thus, in saying (1) ‘George
IV believes that Scott is Scott,’ the reference of the subordinate sentence ‘Scott
is Scott’ isn’t its truth-value or a corresponding fact, but simply the thought
expressed by this sentence. And in saying (2) ‘George IV believes that the author
of Waverley is Scott,’ the subordinate
sentence ‘the author of Waverley is Scott’
also refers to a thought. Since the references of ‘Scott is Scott’ and ‘the author
of Waverley is Scott’ are different, the
sentences (1) and (2) cannot be interchangeable salva veritate.
I do not wish to discuss here the
objections of detail that could be made to Russell’s and Frege’s solutions. I want
to mention only the general objection made to Fregean-kind solutions for riddles
of reference, according to which they induce us to accept some kind of Platonism
of senses and thoughts, unlike Russell’s ontologically more economical solutions.
Against this, the last chapter made clear that we can preserve objectivity of sense
as something interpersonally accessible without any recourse to ontological realism.
All we need is to understand senses as embodied semantic-cognitive rules developed
as interpersonally corrigible rules or conventions or as their derived adequate
associations.
3. Reviewing Fregean
assumptions
Who is right? Russell or Frege?
As I noted at the outset, my hypothesis is that it is not a matter of choosing between
two views. The fact that we have achieved no consensus regarding the right theory
reinforces my suspicion that both theories have some truth. This is why I suppose
that each of them has insightful content mixed with very implausible metaphysical
assumptions, and that these implausible assumptions are what make them appear irreconcilable.
Thus, in the course of this Appendix I will reconstruct these theories by eschewing
their metaphysical assumptions and filling the resulting gaps with more plausible
views.
Let’s start with Frege. We have already seen
that we can eliminate the anachronistic ontological realism of sense if we replace
it with any psychological instantiation
of a semantic-cognitive rule qualitatively identical to the one with which we are
associating the expression. Repeating what has already been proposed in our reading
of Ernst Tugendhat in the introductory chapter, it is perfectly plausible to identify
what Frege called the senses of singular predicative sentences in terms of semantic
rules, so that: (i) the sense of
a nominative expression (the mode of presentation of the object) is the same as
the identification rule (Identifikationsregel) of a singular term, whose criteria of application
are adequate configurations of identifying tropes of the object; (ii) The sense
of a predicative expression (as its conceptual content) is the same as its ascription
or application rule (Verwendungsregel),
whose criteria of application are tropes dependently associated with the object;
the sense of a singular declarative sentence (its e-thought or thought-content)
is the same as its verifiability rule (Verifikationsregel) associating (i) and (ii). (See Tugendhat 1976: 262;
Tugendhat & Wolf 1983, Ch. 13) To this, we have added that verifiability rules
demand criteria of application which are their possible truth-makers, which can
often be better identified (differing from Frege) with the sub-fact referred to by the statement, this sub-fact remitting to a
grounding fact as aspects of the latter.
A second point is to reject some of Frege’s
odd ideas concerning reference, like those of an unsaturated concept as the reference
of a predicate and of truth-value as the reference of a sentence, as I argued in
the last chapter. It is much more plausible to see the concept in a natural way
as the sense of a predicative expression – a conventionally grounded rule – and
the reference of a sentence not as a truth-value, but simply as a fact.
A further thing we did in the last chapter
was to paraphrase the Fregean concept of existence. For Frege existence was the
property of a concept of being satisfied by at least one object. For us existence
is the property of a possible conceptual sense – of a possible semantic-cognitive
rule – of being effectively (and not merely putatively) applicable to at least one
referent belonging to a chosen domain or context (usually the most proper domain
or context) during some period of time (the period in which the object is said to
exist). Thus, to know that a referent exists is to know that its conceptual rule,
if it exists, is effectively and continuously applicable in its most proper domain
or context in the time during which the referent (a tropical property, an object,
a fact) can be said to exist. Moreover, as we have seen, this does not deprive existence
of objectivity, because if the effective applicability of a conceptual rule is a
tropical property of the rule, it is also a higher-order tropical property of the
referent, which is that of having its conceptual rule effectively applicable to
it – even if this rule was never applied and even if it does not exist as an actuality
but merely as a possibility (a dispositional or possibility-trope)! – if the
right conditions were given, the rule would exist and be definitely applicable.
This is a minimal condition allowing us to envisage an object as really existing
in the outside world.
This result can be conceded for each of the
rules (senses) already suggested in Tugendhat’s analysis of singular statements:
(i) The existence of an object (made up
of a certain relatively independent compresent cluster of tropes) is the same as
the effective applicability of its proper identification rule to itself. (ii) The
existence of a property-trope – differing from the object to which it is attached
by a relative dependence – is the same as the effective applicability of its ascription
rule to itself. (iii) By symmetry with cases (i) and (ii), the existence of a fact in the world (minimally an arrangement
of an independent cluster of compresent tropes and a dependent property-trope) is
the same as the effective applicability of the verifiability rule constitutive of
the e-thoughts to the verifier (truth-maker) of this fact. Since the verifiability
rule is the real Fregean thought, the existence of the fact is also the effective
applicability of its thought, expressible by an assertoric sentence. Existence here,
as you remember, is also called ‘truth’ in the derivative sense of the reality of a fact.[55]
Finally, even in the context of Fregean theory,
I want to treat sentences without a reference as ultimately false and not
as simply devoid of truth-value, as Frege suggested. After all, the reason Frege
believed that sentences with components that lack reference are devoid of truth-value
lies in his insistence on the indefensible idea that a sentence’s reference should
be its truth-value. However, at this point we are already certain that a sentence’s
reference is a fact. Therefore, the absence of such a fact just leads us to the
falsity of the whole sentence, as we have shown in our discussion of the Fregean
solution to the question of the reference of non-existents. This heavily corrected
version of Frege’s view is already close to the position held by Russell, who regarded
sentences with empty attributive definite descriptions as false.
4. Reviewing Russellian
Assumptions
Now it is time to review the assumptions
of Russell’s theory of descriptions. A first step is to rule out (i): his thesis
according to which:
Definite descriptions
and even our usual names (which for him were clusters of descriptions) are not to
be viewed as referential terms, but rather as incomplete symbols. (Cf. Russell 1994)
This Russellian thesis flies in the face of
our most fundamental natural language intuitions. For what could better exemplify
a referential expression than a proper name or even a definite description? One
could even say that our usual proper names, definite descriptions, and indexicals,
are patterns of singular referential terms
whose definitional function is to select precisely
one object, indicating which it is among all other objects of a certain domain.[56] The attempt to change
this is to distort natural language in a way that only serves to spread confusion.
Thus, without denying that definite descriptions are incomplete symbols, I will
maintain that definite descriptions are patterns of referential terms.
Russell’s intention with his logical atomism
and semantic referentialism was to eschew the supposed referential and semantic
role of definite descriptions with the ultimate goal of replacing natural language
referential expressions with what he called logically
proper names – the only truly referential expressions. However, as we have
already seen earlier in this book (Ch. III, sec. 3), this doctrine is hopeless,
and his semantic referentialism indefensible (Cf. Tugendhat 1976: 437; also Kripke 2013, Ch. 1).
Once we reject Russell’s atomistic doctrine
of logically proper names, there is no reason to deny that ordinary names and definite
descriptions are referential terms. Even when a definite description is analyzed
in the form of a conjunction of quantified predicative expressions, as Russell does,
it can continue to do the same referential work of a singular term, since it is
assumed that the definite description is able to pick out a single object and distinguish
it from all other objects of a given domain. This is all that is required for an
expression to be a singular term.
We must also reject a second assumption made
by Russell, namely, his strange suggestion that (ii) definite descriptions do not have any meaning in themselves. As he
wrote:
I advocate that a denoting
phrase is essentially part of a statement,
and does not, like most single words, have any significance on its own account.’
(1994: 51)
This assumption makes sense within
the semantic referentialism of Russell’s logical atomism: since for him descriptions
aren’t referential expressions and reference is the source of meaning, it is justified
to say that they aren’t intrinsically meaningful. But even if you complete them
by constructing meaningful statements like ‘The man who wrote “On Denoting” was
a philosopher,’ it seems impossible to explain why the addition of a new predicate
produces a meaningful statement. Assumption (ii) only reaffirms the incoherence
of Russell’s semantic referentialism. One cannot reasonably doubt that definite
descriptions have meanings in themselves or that they are referential expressions.
Now, once we reject Russell’s semantic referentialism
and admit that we usually make our references by means of semantic-cognitive rules,
one thing is clear: the Russellian requirement of applying a predicate to a single
object with such-and-such characteristics already constructs something at least
close to an identification rule with a complete sense allowing us to refer to something
unique.[57]
5. Building a bridge
between both views
Once in possession of a metaphysically
unspoiled understanding of Frege’s and Russell’s analysis – one that strips them
of their implausible speculative wrappers – we are ready to take the final step.
We need to use the semantic-cognitive rules constitutive of senses, together with
the concept of existence as the effective application of these rules, in order to
build a bridge allowing us to travel from Fregean solutions for riddles of reference
to Russellian ones and vice versa. In this way, I will demonstrate that their answers
to puzzles of reference are in essence inter-translatable and therefore reconcilable.
Here is how this can be done:
(i)
Reference to non-existents. As we have seen, the most reasonable answer to the
Fregean problem of how to give meanings to statements referring to non-existent
objects is that we can at least conceive how we can supplement the dependent (unsaturated)
sense of a predicative expression with the independent (saturated) sense of a singular
term, thus constituting the complete content of a thought. This is what allows us
to think of the present King of France as bald or wise… without having to admit
his actual existence.
A better understanding emerges when we translate
Fregean senses in terms of semantic-cognitive rules. In this case – following Tugendhat
– we normally say that the true ascription rule of the predicate always applies
to its usual reference as a consequence of the application of the
identification rule. Returning to an example considered in the introduction of
this book: Seeing the Earth from outside the Earth’s atmosphere for the first time,
Russian cosmonaut Yuri Gagarin remarked: ‘The Earth is blue.’ But in order to formulate
this thought, he first had to identify something outside his space capsule, an object,
the planet Earth. Only by means of this identification could he apply
the predicate ‘…is blue’ to the trope of blue belonging to the object he had visually
located. We see that the rule for the application of the predicate ‘…is blue’ needs
to be first, say, driven by the selective application of the identification
rule in order to find the object called ‘Earth,’ only then being able to be applied
in the identification of the particularized property-trope of this object of being
blue.[58]
Let us now consider the case of empty singular
terms, the alleged reference to non-existents, as found in the sentence ‘Vulcan
is red.’ According to the calculations of the astronomer Le Verrier, Vulcan should
be a small planet located in an orbit approximately 21 million kilometers from the
Sun… Now, this is the Fregean sense of
this name, the mode of presentation of its reference, the identification rule for
the planet Vulcan. However, since we are now certain that the planet Vulcan does
not exist, we know that the name’s reference is empty, that its identification rule
is inapplicable. As a result, the effective application of the ascription rule of
the predicate ‘…is red’ is also impossible. As the identification rule of the singular
term doesn’t apply to any expected object, an application of this rule cannot be
made, remaining non-satisfied by any actually given cluster of tropes. Thus, the
predicate cannot be applied, making the sentence false (pace Frege and Strawson).
As noted above, we do not need complex metaphysical
theories to explain what happens in this case. The right explanation appeals to
our capacity for imagination. We
are at least in some measure always able to conceive
what it would be like to apply both rules in association, even if we cannot find
a way to apply them to the real world.[59] To use a Wittgensteinian
expression, we are able to conceive the application of a statement like ‘Vulcan
is red’ as a possible state of affairs
(1984a, 3.02). It is only to the extent that we are able to conceive the possibility of applying both
rules in the constitution of a verifiability rule that we can understand the cognitive
meaning of the statement. When we do this, we realize that the proper name is empty
and that the e-thought-rule (cognitive meaning, verifiability rule) that
contains it has no effective application to a real fact in the world. This is why
the statement ‘The present King of France is wise’ is already able to express a
complete sense as an e-thought-rule. We are capable of conceiving the two rules
used in association in order to form the verifiability e-thought rule, the sense
of the statement, imaginatively applicable in our minds to a possible fact, but
without effective application in its most proper domain as a real fact in the world;
and this impossibility makes this e-thought-rule false.
As to the question of how it is possible to
assign baldness or wisdom to a non-existent person, the answer is now clear: we
are capable, at least in some measure, of conceiving the application of semantic-cognitive
rules and their adequate associations, and by doing this we give meaning to the
terms and the sentence as a whole. Mentally we are able to make a fictitious predication,
even if only to a limited degree, without endowing it with a proper assertoric and
judicative force.
Now, in light of this reconstruction, it is
easier to make the theory of sense agree with the theory of descriptions. We can
paraphrase the definite description of the statement ‘The present King of France
exists’ in a Russellian way as:
1. There is at least one x and at most one x,
such that x is a present King of France.
And we can say that what is expressed
here (disregarding the attribution of existence) is a somewhat abbreviated formulation
of the Fregean sense of the same identification rule for the present King of France,
which is seen as having two components:
(i) the condition of uniqueness,
(ii) the ascription rule for the predicative expression
‘…is a present King of France.’
Together (i) and (ii)
constitute a kind of identification rule, because they give us the possibility to
distinguish at least one and at most one object by means of criterial properties
derived from the predicate, such as the supposed existence of a hereditary head
of state governing France today.
The non-existence of the present King of France
corresponds to the lack of effective applicability of the identification rule roughly
expressed by the conjunction of (i) and (ii) and, therefore, to the lack of a reference.
As for the predicate ‘…is wise’ in the sentence ‘The present King of France is wise,’
its ascription rule also does not apply, since no one has the property of being
the present King of France to whom the rule could
apply. Anyway, this predicate still expresses an ascription rule as something
only conceivably applicable, a conceivable Fregean sense understood as a mode
of presentation.
Pulling the threads together, with the statement
‘There is at least one x and at most one x, such that x is a present King of France, and x
is wise’ we do nothing more than try to apply the same verifiability rule expressed
by the statement ‘The present King of France is wise.’ That is, we realize that
the identification rule cannot find a bearer and that consequently, the ascription
rule is also inapplicable, the same being the case with their adequate associations
in the form of a verifiability rule. In this way, analyzing the case of reference
of non-existents, we are already able to see how we can exchange a ‘Fregean’ explanation
for a ‘Russellian’ explanation and vice versa.
(ii)
Negative Existentials. In the last chapter (despite Frege’s view) we identified
the concept with the sense of a predicative expression. This also means that to
say ‘The present King of France does not exist’ becomes the same thing as saying
that the sense of ‘the present King of France’ does not determine its reference.
How would we express this using semantic-cognitive
rules in place of the sense? Well, we would again say that the sense or meaning
expressed by a singular term like ‘the present King of France’ consists in the identification
rule of this definite description in its only conceivable application. We know this
because we know we can at least to some extent imagine how we would apply this definite
description. But we cannot gain any awareness of the effective applicability of
this rule, that is, we cannot say that the object that should be referred to by
this definite description exists, since we know that this rule cannot be definitely
applied in its most proper context.
Finally, we come to the corresponding ‘Russellian’
analysis. A description like ‘the present King of France’ is here transformed into
1. at least one x and at most one x
is such that x is a present King of France.
Here again, what we have is an
identification rule for a particular object, which is composed of two sub-rules:
(i) a rule demanding unity,
(ii) a rule of application of the predicate ‘...is
a present King of France.’
Now, to say, ‘The present King
of France does not exist,’ is to say:
It is not the case that there is at least one x
and at most one x such that x is a present King of France.
But this is the same thing as to
say that the identification rule roughly composed of conditions (i) and (ii) is
not effectively applicable. What is the
difference between this rule and the Fregean sense of the description? The answer
is again that the ‘Russellian’ analysis only decomposes the identification rule
of the definite description ‘the present King of France’ into two rules: a unity
rule and a rule of application for the predicate. Saying that the present king of France does not exist is to say that the ascription rule
of the predicate ‘…is a present King of France’ does not effectively apply in its proper context, in this case, because it
does not fulfill the implicit existential condition. Once more, the ‘Russellian’
and ‘Fregean’ analyses of negative existentials reveal themselves as two different
ways to say almost the same thing.
(iii) Identity. Consider now identity sentences like ‘The Morning Star
is the Evening Star.’ How can this sentence be informative, if the two descriptions
refer to the same object? Frege’s reply is that despite the fact that these descriptions
refer to the same object, they express different modes of presentation of this object,
being therefore informative.
Paraphrasing the concept of meaning in terms
of a semantic-cognitive rule, what a Fregean semantics suggests is that the sentence
above is informative because it tells us that we identify the same object using
(a) two different identification rules, or (b) two branches of the same identification
rule. These rules or branches are respectively a rule for the identification of
the last star to disappear at dawn and a rule for the identification of the first
star to appear in the evening. These rules call for different criterial settings,
emphasizing the apparent sub-fact of the difference between the Morning Star and
the Evening Star. That in the end they refer to the same object is – in the context
considered by Frege – a further piece
of information, a complementary identification rule for the planet Venus. If we add this last piece of information
in order to build a unifying rule requiring assumptions about our astronomical
knowledge, we have a conditioned necessary
a priori e-thought-rule. Otherwise, the e-thought-rule is seen as contingent a posteriori (See section 2 above;
also Ch. IV, sec. 26).
In Russellian terms, letting M abbreviate the
predicate ‘…is a morning star’ and E abbreviate
the predicate ‘…is an evening star,’ the identity sentence can be symbolized as:
(1) Ǝx
[(Mx & Ex) &
(y) (My → y = x) & (z) (Ez → z
= x)].
In other
words:
(2) There
is precisely one x that is the morning star and this same x is also
the evening star.
In this case, what we are doing
with the identity sentence is (i) making a conjunction of two different ascription
rules of predicates and adding to it the condition (ii) that they both apply to
one and the same object. Thus, the ‘Russellian’ analysis only assures us that the
identification rule constituted by ‘Ǝx
[Mx & (y) (My → y = x)]’
applies to the same object that the identification rule constituted by ‘Ǝx [Ex
& (z) (Ez → z = x)]’ applies to, since by transitivity, if
y = x and x = z, then y = z. But this is already near to the claim that we have two
different identification rules, two different Fregean modes of presentation, further known as having the same object. Again, the two
analyses turn out to be largely interchangeable.[60]
(iv) Intentional Contexts.
Finally, consider expressions of propositional attitudes such as:
(1) George
IV believes that Scott is Scott.
And
(2) George
IV believes that the author of Waverley
is Scott.
Why doesn’t the truth of (1) guarantee the truth
of (2), if both subordinate clauses are identity sentences about the same person?
As we have noted, for Frege the answer is
that in such cases a subordinate clause does not have its usual reference, which
for him is its truth-value. Subordinate clauses, he holds, refer to the thoughts expressed by them, and the thoughts
expressed by them in (1) and (2) are different. Hence, the truth-value of the whole
sentence that expresses a propositional attitude cannot depend from the truth-value
of the subordinate clause, which makes inter-substitution salva veritate impossible.
Since we reject Frege’s artificial idea that
a sentence’s normal reference should be its truth-value, we must first reformulate
his solution. For us, an isolated statement such as ‘The author of Waverley is Scott’
has as its immediate reference the aspectually given sub-fact represented by the
identification of the modes of presentation of the singular terms flanking the identity
relation. This sub-fact can be represented by the statement ‘Being the author of Waverley ≠ being Scott,’ while the
mediated reference, the grounding fact, can be represented by the statement ‘Scott
= Scott’ (The underscore ‘_’ signals that I am speaking about facts). As
already explained, both facts are complex tropical arrangements.
Now, what fact is represented in the case of propositional attitudes? First, we
can preserve Frege’s idea that in utterances of propositional attitudes the reference
of the subordinate sentence is its sense,
for us an e-thought-content that is ultimately a mental fact. But there is
more to the matter. This mental fact is part of the whole fact represented by a
propositional attitude, which has the form aAp, in which a abbreviates the relevant descriptions identifying
the person who has the attitude, p is the subordinate sentence referring
to a’s e-thought-content, and A abbreviates
the attitudinal verb applied by a to p, which can be one of belief, knowledge,
desire, etc. Hence, the reference of ‘Henry IV believes the author of Waverley is Scott’ is no typical fact in
the external world. It is a fact consisting in the psychological belief of the real Henry IV that the author of Waverley is
Scott. In other words, a propositional attitude conventionally refers to
an essentially mental fact: the (mental) attitude of a (partly non-mental)
speaker (a person[61]) concerning a certain (mental) thought-content that we can symbolize
as aAp. Here p refers
to a thought-content (dispositional or not) in the mind of person a,
such that it no longer refers to any fact in the external world that could possibly
match p, making it true. Here, if ├aAp affirms the essentially mental fact that
aAp, then the statement is true,
otherwise it is false; and while as a person a should be a cluster of compresent (physical and mental) tropes
in the world, Ap distinguishes
itself by being a mental relational tropical complex appropriately linking person
a with a factual arrangement of her own
mental tropes. In other words, what matters in statements of propositional attitudes
is a certain relationship between the contents of the main clause (usually expressing
the speaker’s dispositional mood or mental act) and the e-thought-content expressed
by the subordinate clause. And it must be that the truth of a sentence of propositional
attitude depends only on the fact of this
attitudinal relationship A to p really being in person a’s mind, independently of the truth or falsity of the thought-content expressed by
p concerning any independent fact in the
real word.
We can now see more clearly why the thought expressed
by the subordinate clause cannot be replaced salva veritate in (1)
and (2): in each case a’s mental dispositions
or acts concern different factual thought-contents expressed by different subordinate
clauses. Finally, it is worth noting that the person who judges these propositional
attitudes is a third person or even the first person in an introspective mood, or
in a later time, and there is no distinction between the senses and the facts reported
when the ascription is true.[62]
Now, to paraphrase thought-contents as verifiability
rules for sentences, we need only note that the verifiability rules of the sentences
of (1) and (2) are different, applying only to the essentially mental fact of the
kind aAp, without committing us
to the effective applicability of p
to any real fact in the world. Thus, considering the sense of the proper name Scott
as an identification rule, we can in many cases paraphrase (1) as:
(1’) George IV believes
that the identification rule (a) (sense (a)) that he has for ‘Scott’ applies to
the same object as the identification rule (a) (sense (a)) that he has for ‘Scott.’
This tautological belief is true
even if George IV knows nothing about Scott. We can paraphrase (2) as:
(2’) George IV believes
that his identification rule (a) (sense (a)) for ‘Scott’ applies to the same object
as the different identification rule (b) (sense (b)) that he has for ‘the author
of Waverley.’
The obvious argument drawn from
this is the following:
1. The truth-value of the propositional attitude
statements depends on the existence of the proper (essentially) mental fact that
an e-thought-content p is the object of
person a’s attitude A.
2. The (essentially) mental facts represented by
(1’) and (2’) are different because
the e-thought-contents p are
different.
3. Statements (1’) and (2’) are analyzed forms
of (1) and (2).
4. Conclusion: We do not need to preserve the same
truth-value in statements (1) and (2).
The two subordinate clauses cannot
replace one another salva veritate because they have different factual e-thoughts-contents
p’s as references and so also the two
whole attitudinal statements.
Finally, consider the Russellian paraphrases.
Statement (1) can be formulated as ‘George IV believes that Ǝx [(x = s) & (y) ((y = s) → (y = x))
& (s = s)],’ or simply as:
(1’’) George IV believes
that there is at least one x and at most
one x, such that x is Scott, who is the same as Scott.
And statement (2) can (in a secondary
occurrence) be formulated as ‘George IV believes that Ǝx [Axw & (y) (Ayw
→ y = x)) & (x = s)]’ or, more
naturally:
(2’’) George IV believes
that there is at least one x and at most
one x, such that x is the author
of Waverley and x is Scott.
Now, as the subordinate clauses
expressing George IV’s beliefs (i) ‘there is precisely one x that is Scott’
and (ii) ‘there is precisely one x that is the author of Waverley’ are different,
‘Scott is Scott’ cannot mean the same as ‘Scott is the author of Waverley.’ The e-thought-rules expressed
by (i) and (ii) are different and so also the sub-facts conceived by George IV.
It should be remarked that our version of Russellian
analysis and our version of Fregean analysis have different emphases. After all,
we can present the Fregean analysis in (2’) for example, as:
(2’’’) George IV believes
there is at least one x and at most one x, such that the rule of identification (a) for Scott (sense (a))
and the rule of identification (b) for the description ‘the author of Waverley’ (sense (b)) apply to x.
But (2’) and (2’’’) do not differ
significantly in what they say. After all, suppose we say, based on Russell, that
George IV believes the rule of identification (a) that he knows for the name ‘Scott’
and the ascription rule (b) that he knows for the predicate ‘…is the author of Waverley’
effectively apply to precisely one and the
same object. This amounts to almost the same thing as to say, based on Frege,
that George IV believes that the identification rule (a) (the sense (a)) he knows
for the singular term ‘Scott’ has the same
referent as the rule of identification (b) (the sense (b)) of the definite description
‘the author of Waverley.’ Now it is clear:
also in the case of propositional attitudes, the Fregean and Russellian analyses
are at least to a great extent intertranslatable.
5. Conclusion
Summarizing, we can analyze the
referential function of definite descriptions in at least three ways: (a) in terms
of abstract entities, as did Frege when speaking of senses, (b) in terms of semantic-cognitive
criterial rules inspired by approaches like those of Tugendhat and Dummett, and (c) using resources from
predicative logic, as Russell tried to do in his theory of descriptions. These are only three complementary endeavors
to say the same thing.
As I have noted, the initial impression of
strangeness of the proposed view comes from the acceptance of the metaphysical assumptions
that permeate what Frege and Russell wrote on the issue. Against Russell’s own belief,
his paraphrases of definite descriptions are nothing more than limited expressions
of semantic-cognitive rules. These paraphrases make it possible to express the referential
function of definite descriptions in their attributive use by means of quantified
predicative expressions used in a domain that grants them a singularizing application.
In this reading, they are reformulations of senses or modes of presentation that
cannot be more than semantic-cognitive criterial rules. Assuming that these last
rules only exist in their applications – either in imaginative psychological rehearsals
or in effective cognitive instantiations concerning real entities in the world –
the compatibility of the so-understood theory of descriptions with our cognitivist
approach is clear.
[1] On the thorny issue of how to translate
‘Bedeutung,’ see Beaney 1997: 36 f.
[2] Searching in the literature, the
only place where I have found a similar view on this point is Kneale & Kneale
1985: 495.
[3] One can read singular terms like
‘the morning star’ as definite descriptions or as proper names (like ‘The Morning
Star’). I prefer to read them here as definite descriptions, since for proper names
we can use the words ‘Phosphorus.’
[4] As shown in the introduction, Ernst
Tugendhat later defended a similar understanding of the meanings of singular statements
in a more systematic and detailed way, though refraining from doing it as a reconstruction
of Frege’s semantics.
[5] If we compare these two passages,
it becomes clear that in opposition to Kripke’s interpretation (1980, Lecture I),
Frege already had in mind the essentials of the later bundle theory of proper names.
The same can be said of Russell (Cf. Russell
1911, Ch. 5).
[6] Assuming Kripke’s views, François
Recanati replaces senses with mental files as supposedly non-descriptive modes
of presentation (2012: 34). However, since these files are clusters of information
and not subjective Vorstellungen,
they should be able to be linguistically expressed by means of descriptions, bringing
us back to the descriptivist standpoint. For this reason, it seems that semantic-cognitive
rules are able to do the same job with higher explanatory potential and (as we will
see) with important epistemological consequences. Moreover, these rules or
combinations of rules do not need to contain less information than files. They can
be as informational, durable, transitory, changeable and flexible as required by
the context.
[7] Mere similarity would not do,
as this concept is intransitive. Strict similarity means here the same as qualitative
identity, which is transitive. Strict similarity must also be a trope, since it
is spatiotemporally located between tropes, even if, as an internal relation, it
is a subordinate trope.
[8] I suggested this disjunctive construction
of universal by means of tropes as the best way to circumvent the usual but problematic
definition of a universal as a set or sum of tropes that are strictly similar, one
with the other (See Appendix of Chapter III).
[9] Here I agree with Keith Campbell,
who has suggested an epistemic primacy of identification over the generalizing function
(1990: 24-25).
[10] Even D. C. Williams portrayed things
misleadingly here. For him ‘Socrates is wise’ (or any Fa) means ‘The concurrence
[togetherness] sum (Socrates) includes a trope that is a member of the similarity set.’ (my italics, 1953: 11)
[11] There are several asymmetries.
The most discussed is probably the asymmetry of subjects and predicates regarding
negation: you can negate the predicate, but not the subject (nominal term) (Strawson
1971, Ch. 5). The answer seems to me
clear. The negation of the predicate means the admission of the inapplicability
of the ascription rule to the object identified by the identification rule. However,
since the application of the ascription rule is dependent on the application of
the identification rule, whenever you negate the application of the identification
rule of the subject you also negate the applicability of the ascription rule and
in this way the whole statement. Hence, it is impossible to negate the subject as
the nominal term alone.
[12] Notice that the demonstrative ‘that’
does not have here the function of a constituent of the identification rule of Socrates,
but expresses the identification rule of a certain place. In indexical statements
like ‘This is a daisy,’ the demonstrative ‘this’ expresses a one-foot
identification rule, localizing a place in time, while the sortal ‘daisy’ is
placed as part of the predicate ‘…is a daisy,’ expressing the ascription rule.
It is different from ‘This daisy is
yellow,’ in which the sortal ‘daisy’ is the characterizing part of the
identification rule, whose localizing part is given by the demonstrative
‘this.’ The logical form of the statement ‘This is Socrates’ is already revealed by the relational statement ‘<This spatiotemporal place>
is where <Socrates> is located.’ (For the role of localization and
characterization in identification rules, see Appendix to Chapter I, sec. 1.)
[13] Ignoring Frege’s theses that the
reference of a sentence is a truth-value and that a fact is a true thought, I will
in the present context call the sentence’s reference a fact. This choice will be justified in the sections 21 to 23 of this
chapter.
[14] I take these examples from Mulligan
et al. (1984: 300, 301 and 306), though
their point wasn’t the same.
[15] As Ernst Tugendhat wrote: ‘‘Fa’
is just the case to the extent that the rule of identification for ‘a’ is followed,
and based on this result ‘F,’ is
applicable in accordance with its rule of application’. (Tugendhat & Wolf 1983: 235)
[16] The Valkyries were maidens who served the god Odin,
choosing the soldiers on battlefields worthy of admission to Valhalla.
[17] It is easy to see that singular statements implicitly attribute
existence to their objects, since a predicative statement with the form Fa could
be written as Ǝx [Fx & (y) (Fy → (y
= x)) & (x = a)] in order to make this attribution more explicit.
[18] Socrates lived in Greece from 470
to 399 BC. But usually the time and place of existence are abstracted when we talk
about existence, since existence is essentially only the effective applicability
of the conceptual rule, not the time of its applicability.
[19] It was W. V-O. Quine who suggested
using the name Pegasus as a way to change a name into a predicate such as ‘the thing
that pegasizes’ (1948/9: 27).
[20] There are less successful attempts, like Michael Devitt’s
interesting book Designation (1981).
[21] David Braun and Marga Reimer, two
renowned specialists, made a balanced comparison of descriptivist and causal-historical
views in their respective articles for the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
The results were inconclusive.
[22] In some cases, like ‘Queen Elizabeth
II,’ the family and even genetic origin is part of the localizing description, although
this isn’t necessarily so (See Appendix to Chapter II).
[23] What symbolic form a proper name
receives is contingent. What makes this form necessary is the identification rule
that we attach to it. In a possible world where the name attached to the identification
rule for the name Hitler was attached to the name Hartman, this different name would
mean what we mean by the name Hitler.
[24] Remembering that there is no sharp boundary between fundamental
and auxiliary descriptions.
[25] One could object that rules are
changeable and that if we change the identification rule, it ceases to be a rigid
designator, unaware that auxiliary descriptions can be changed as much as one
will. Nonetheless, if we change the fundamental rules so that the set of possible
worlds to which the proper name applies can be distinguished as a different one,
we are not applying the same proper name anymore. However, you may introduce changes
like additions to the fundamental description-rules insofar as this only specifies
the identification better, and thus affecting nothing essential, only adding the
application or non-application to possible worlds where the applicability of the
rule was in an earlier stage indeterminate.
(Cf. Appendix to Chapter I, sec. 7)
[26] This is again a didactic simplification (See Appendix of Chapter I).
[27] However, if the assertion that
there are round squares were merely an equivocal manner of saying that we can syntactically
combine the adjectives ‘square’ and ‘round,’ that is, a misleading way of saying
that there is a syntactical rule allowing the combination of these incompatible
words, then it makes some sense to attribute existence. But in this case, what we
are trying to say will be more correctly expressed by the meta-linguistic sentence:
‘The rule for constructing the phrase “round square” is applicable, and therefore,
the phrase “round square” exists as a grammatical construction.’ The Meinongian
Sosein is reduced here to the recognition of a syntactical triviality.
[28] In accord with Berkeley’s official
view, things that are not actually perceived by us exist because they are continuously
being perceived by God. (Urmson 1983)
[29] I believe that Mill’s confusion
in the definition of matter was in fact an attempt to evade the objection of idealism
open to Berkeley.
[30] See Frege, Letter to Russell of
28.12.1912.
[31] Without offering a justification, Strawson writes:
‘a situation or state of affairs is, roughly, a set of facts, not a set of things.’
(1950: 8)
[32] For an important reply, see J.
L. Austin, ‘Unfair to Facts’ (1961, Ch. 5). It seems to me at least curious that
the posthumously published arguments of Austin against Strawson’s view have had
so little impact.
[33] John
Searle once proposed something approaching this answer: ‘…we neither have nor need
a thick metaphysical notion of “fact.” Anything sufficient to make a statement true
is a fact. Thus the fact that there are no three-headed cats is as much a fact as
the fact that the cat is on the mat.’ (1998: 392)
[34] See Appendix of Chapter III, sec.
4.
[35] This also gives back the whole
sense of Church’s still more convoluted original sentence: ‘The number such that
Sir Walter Scott is the man who wrote that many Waverley Novels altogether is twenty-nine.’
[36] I think that the mode
of presentation of the sub-fact can be approximated with what defenders of two-dimensionalism
call a primary intention (here called derived thought)
while the mode of presentation of the grounding fact can be approximated with what
they call a secondary intention (here
called basal thought) (Cf. Chalmers 2002). Anyway, the present
suggestion is clearly more perspicuous and natural.
[37] For instance, A. J. Ayer in the
first case and Hilary Putnam in the second. (See also Costa 2014, Ch. 3.)
[38] The concept of emphasization was fruitfully applied in Jürgen
Habermas’s excellent work on universal pragmatics
(Habermas 1976).
[39] The example was already
considered in the Addendum of the Appendix
to Chapter II in this book.
[40] As Tyler Burge wrote: ‘the word
“thought” is the best substitute for ‘proposition’ for the naturalness of its semantics
within the scope appropriate to the linguistic philosophy.’ (Burge, 2005: 227-8)
[41] For Frege, in the case of indexical
sentences, the context of the utterance belongs to the expression of thought. See
also addendum of the Appendix to Chapter II, sec. 8.
[42] According to his main argument,
if you say that the truth of p is its
correspondence with reality, you need to admit that p must have the property j in order to be true by correspondence with reality, and that to have the property j in order to be true
by corresponding with reality will demand the property j’ and so successively.
The answer (already given by Aquinas) is that to say that p is true by corresponding to reality, and to say that p has the property j due to being true by
corresponding to reality are one and the same
thing; consequently, N is redundant. (Cf.
Künne 2003: 129-133).
[43] For instance: ‘truth (principle): that which is true in
accordance with the fact or reality’; ‘truth (fact): the actual fact about the matter’…
(Oxford-Cambridge Dictionary).
[44] See Tugendhat’s verificationist
correspondentialism in 1983: 235-6.
[45] Nonetheless, there is an at
least seemingly alternative way to understand the property of effective
applicability of the verifiability rule, which is to identify it with the existence of the fact. To reach this
conclusion, we need only consider that the existence of an object (an
independent cluster of compresent tropes) is the higher-order property of
effective applicability of an identification rule expressed by a nominal term, and that the existence of a property – a
dependent property-trope – is the higher-order property of effective
applicability of the ascription rule of a predicative expression. If we accept
this, then by symmetry the existence of a singular fact should be the
higher-order property of effective applicability of the verifiability rule of
the singular declarative sentence to which it applies. It seems that we could
say, in an almost Hegelian fashion, that existence is the truth of the concept,
while the truth is the existence of the thought… We have here two alternative understandings
of the property of effective applicability of a verifiability rule, what
generates a dilemma that will only be solved in the beginning of chapter VI.
[46] See Appendix to Chapter III, sec. 2.
[47] As T. W. Polger has shown, in order to illustrate the flaw
of the multiple realizability argument, we
can explain how a carburetor has the function of mixing fuel and air for a combustion engine; but it is a multiply realizable device:
it can be made of various different materials with various designs, provided
it functions
properly. (2004: 19-20).
[48] The phrase is from Murray
Gell-Mann. Against this, however, one could ask: haven’t we learned that geometry
deals with perfect circles and that arithmetic deals with entirely abstract numbers?
Take the case of circles. The answer is, of course, in the negative, because we
can make a new circle more perfect than the last one, and another even more perfect,
and this process can continue indefinitely. The perfect circle is like the actual
infinite: it does not exist. It is nothing more than a projection of our awareness
of the possibility of making increasingly perfect empirical circles without any
conceivable end. Geometry does not work with actual perfect circles, but with potentially
perfect circles.
[49] Against Frege, we could hold that
to some extent even imagetic representations can be expressed through language and
by its means could be subjectively identified and re-identified as being the same
(e.g., a police sketch or a Photofit). It is true that a mental state that only
one person is capable of having, for instance, a sort of epileptic aura, is not
communicable, except indirectly, metaphorically. But it seems very plausible that
typical mental states, such as feelings, images, sensations, are things that all
of us are able to communicate and learn to identify in ourselves through induction
by exclusion, added to induction
by analogy and reinforced by a great variety of interpersonally accessible physical
states strongly intermingled with them (Cf.
Ch. III, sec. 8; See also Costa 2011, Ch. 3).
[50] Biological mutations are accidents
whose occurrence should be evolutionarily calibrated.
Species are only
likely to
survive if they can mutate to the right degree in the right period of
time in order to adapt to environmental changes.
Too many mutations, as well as too few, would be dangerous for species survival.
It seems possible that an unchanging species with no mutation is conceivable, but
it would be unable to adapt to changing external conditions.
[51] I mean a principle of bivalence understood as a
different formulation of the principle of non-contradiction.
[52] Saul Kripke has denied
this, suggesting that Russell and Frege appealed to a simplified model of descriptivism
with only one definite description, while the bundle theory arose later. But we
need only read with attention Chapter 5 of Russell’s The Problems of Philosophy (1912) and Frege’s remarks (1882, 1918) to
see that both were well aware that proper names abbreviate complex sets of descriptions.
[53] In his book on
logic, Strawson suggested that statements without a reference like ‘The present
King of France is wise’ have no truth-value, because in order to have truth-value
such statements must assume the truth of the presupposed statement ‘The present King of France exists.’ (1952: 185)
[54] In my view, in his classical
work Descriptions, Stephen Neale settled the case in favor
of Russell’s analysis (1990: 26-28).
[55] Certainly, all three
cases can be expressed using formal devices in which referential terms are transformed
into predicative expressions. Thus, consider the existence of what is predicated in the statement ‘Marsupials exist’:
symbolizing ‘…is a marsupial’ as M, we have ‘(Ǝx) (Mx).’ Consider now the definite description in the statement ‘The Morning Star exists’: symbolizing
the predicate ‘… is a morning star’ as M, we have ‘Ǝx [Mx & (y) (My → y = x)].’
For the proper name in the statement ‘Socrates exists,’ abbreviating the complex descriptive
content that the name contains with the predicate ‘socratizes’ and symbolizing this
last predicate as ‘S’, we have (Ǝx) [Sx & (y) (Sy → y = x)]. Finally, consider
the statement ‘Socrates is wise’: symbolizing
‘…is wise’ by W, we have (Ǝx) [Sx & (y) (Sy → y = x) & Wx].
[56] As Ernst Tugendhat
pointed out, in opposition to Donald Davidson, to refer to one object is not only
to coordinate the name with it but ‘to distinguish it from all the others belonging
to a certain domain.’ (Tugendhat & Wolf 1983: 153)
[57] I will leave aside all
the complexities related to ‘non-Russellian’ definite descriptions like ‘the round
table in this room’ (indexical use), ‘the man drinking a martini over there’ (referential
use), ‘the White Anglo-Saxon Protestant’ (general use), ‘the reason why I like beans’
(justifying use)... All they do here is to divert us from our intended point, creating
specious distractions.
[58] Surely, Gagarin could also say
‘The blue thing out there is the Earth.’ But then he would use ‘The blue thing
out there’ as a singular term and the ‘is’ (‘…is the same as…’) as expression
of the relational ascription rule applicable only after the application of the
two identification rules. On the other hand, if the statements were ‘The Earth is
red’ or ‘Out there is red,’ they would be false because the object/place located
by means of the identification rule would not have the property-trope able to
satisfy the ascription rule of the predicate ‘…is red’ (Cf. Ch. I, sec. 2)
[59] I use ‘conceive’
and ‘imagine’ as equivalent verbs thought with
different emphases. In a broad sense, not all imagination is imagistic. We can speak,
for instance, of ‘mathematical imagination’.
[60] It is not our topic here, but it is worth noting that in
any case the identity can be seen as necessary
a priori insofar as we take for granted our astronomical knowledge. In this
case, the identity is a priori and conditionally (hypothetically) necessary, and
both identification rules are aspects of a single, more complex identification rule
of Venus.
[61] Here I understand a
person in P. F. Strawson’s sense as an object to which both (physical) p-predicates
and (mental) m-predicates are ascribed. (1959, I, Ch. 3)
[62] Since the reference
is determined by the sense, for a Fregean there must be a second indirect sense
here determining the indirect sense of the subordinate clause. But no one was able
to point to this hidden indirect-indirect sense or to the regress that it might
be apt to produce. We circumvent this by holding that the whole attitude
described by ├aAp is first that of a third
person (or the same person in a reflexive mood) concerning the essentially mental
fact that aAp. If this fact
exists, aAp is true, otherwise not. For
example: ‘[I am sure that] Anna believes that Goya painted the Third of May, 1808’. Here the fact that Anna
believes that Goya painted the Third of May,
1808, must have an external mode of presentation for me. This could be because
we visited the Prado Museum yesterday, which determines the reference or fact, in
a case where I use an e-thought to refer to Anna’s belief in her own thought-content.
Nenhum comentário:
Postar um comentário