This ROUGH DRAFT elaborates on a suggestion presented in the book How Do Proper Names Really Work? (De Gruyter 2023), p. 44.
UNIVERSALIZING TROPES: A
SIMPLE WAY
I intend to propose what seems to me the right way
of building universals by means of tropes. I will examine Donald Williams’s
standard method (2018: 29) and then consider some of its shortcomings. In the
sequence, I present what seems to be the most credible alternative solution.
I
According to Williams, universals are nothing but
sets, classes, or even groups of tropes precisely similar. Consider the
universal of red. For a Platonist, it should be the idea of red or
“the-red-in-itself.” For a class nominalist, it could be the class of red
objects. For Williams, however, it is nothing but the set of all the tropes
that are precisely similar to each other as tropes of red. A sentence such as
“Red is a color” could be analyzed by him as: “The set of precisely similar
tropes of red is contained in the set of precisely similar tropes of color.”
The standard objection against
William’s is that if we need to identify a set of tropes as a set of precisely
similar tropes, then we have a problem concerning the ontological status of
precise similarity. Assuming, as Williams does, that precise similarities are
tropes, we are allowed to ask what the ontological status of a precise
similarity is. Assuming William’s view that our world must be completely
constituted by its tropes, a precise similarity is a trope. Precise
similarities of the tropes belonging to the set must be precisely similar to
the other. But if so, we have generated a second-order set of precise
similarity tropes. This would not be too much if two second-order tropes of
similarity would not need to be precisely similar. This leads to the admission
of a third-order set of similarity tropes, and so on indefinitely. Regression
is inevitable.
The question is if this regression is
virtuous or vicious. To evaluate whether the regression is vicious here, we can
be satisfied with the view that a virtuous regression is a regression that can
be stopped as one wishes, while a vicious regression is not (Maurin 2007).
Consider, for instance, Plato’s doctrine of ideas. The explanation of the
doctrine contains ideas of ideas. One could even appeal to ideas of the ideas
of ideas by considering his theory further. But no step requires any consideration
of ideas in a still higher level... The same goes for the concept of precisely
similar tropes in William’s definition of universals. There is a regression,
but it is virtuous, and we do not need to get bored with it.
However, William’s solution has more
worrisome drawbacks. What is the ontological status of the set of tropes? How
can we grasp a universal as a set of tropes? Suppose that the set is infinite.
In this case, it seems we could not grasp the universal. And for medical
reasons, we couldn’t grasp any universal as a great set of tropes. Moreover, a set
can grow or shrink in size. But can a universal grow or shrink? An alternative
would be to treat a tropical universal as an open set. But isn’t an open set a
construction existing only in our minds while things are more completely
determined in the outside nature? And what would be its minimal size?
At this point, an advocate of
William’s view could suggest that we must distinguish two questions. The first
is ontological: are there universals meant as classes or sets built from
tropes? The second is epistemological: how can we grasp universals meant as
classes built from tropes? At first view, the really interesting question is
the first one, the only truly metaphysical. Since the problems above seem to
arise from epistemological questions, we do not need to worry too much about
them. A closer look, however, shows that this is a misleading way to see the
problem because it is not true that the metaphysical problem comes first, but
rather the other way around.
Doubts arise when we ask ourselves
about the origins of the problem of universals. They remounted to Plato and
Aristotle. The problem arises from the question: “How can we apply the same
predicate to many different things? Plato’s answer was that “we are in the
habit of posit a simple idea or form in the case of the various multiplicities
to which we give the same name” (1961: 596 a-b). That is, we appeal to an idea
or form that would be “copied” by many different things, or from which
those many different things would “participate.” A nominalist answer could be
that we apply a general term to a class of objects so that the universal would
be that reference class (Wolterstorff 1970: 173 ss.). We see here that the important
problem posed by Plato was not metaphysical but epistemological, namely, how
can we apply the same general term to many different things? How is predication
possible? How can we achieve this most fundamental kind of synthesis? The
metaphysical solution arose from an epistemological question concerning our
cognitive capacities. Hence, we will have nothing to lose if we can answer the
epistemological question without further metaphysical embroilment.
Assuming the priority of the cognitive
problem, the question regarding the universalization of tropes is: how can we
apply the same conceptual word to many different things, assuming that the
conceptual word designates a trope? The answer to this question does not need
to include the hypothesis that we are acquainted with a class, set, or group of
tropes. I suggest we get a much better answer when we remember how bishop Berkeley
solved the problem of universals – the solution considered by Hume “one of the
greatest and the most valuable discoveries in the republic of letters” (1978:
I, I, VII), as he tried to implement on it. According to Berkeley, all the
universe, except the spirits (like we and God), is totally constituted, not by
tropes, but by ideas. Ideas, he considered, can be general but not abstract,
that is, not platonic entities. Now, how can ideas be general without having to
be abstract? Well, because we associate a general term with one or more similar
particular ideas, using them as a pattern to identify external things given to
us insofar as these things (that for him are literally ideas existing in the
mind of God (1975b: 224)) are sufficiently similar to the pattern. As Berkeley
writes: “But it seems that a word becomes general by being made the sign, not
of an abstract general idea but of several particular ideas, any one of which
it indifferently suggests to the mind.” (1975a: Introd. Sec. 11) This means
that to identify a given object as a triangle, we only need to retrieve some particular
ideas (meant as images) of triangles like the isosceles, the scalenus, the
obtuse, etc., associated in our minds with the word ‘triangle’ and by
experiencing the object look for the similarities. For Berkeley and Hume, the
problem of universals is solved by employing a simple operation of the mind without
requiring any further metaphysical commitment. It is true that this empiricist
solution is generally viewed as defective because of the imagistic concept of the
idea held by those empiricist philosophers… However, this problem does not need
to worry us at all since the bulk of my proposal will be to adopt Berkeley’s
schema, replacing the concept of idea with the concept of trope. My countenance
is that since tropes are not necessarily imagistic and have the most varied
structure, they will be able to perform the expected role much better than
purely sensory images.
To recast a procedure similar to that of Berkeley-Hume
using tropes instead of ideas, what we, as a rule, need is that the epistemic
agent had previous contact or information with a particular trope and its name
and, afterward, can identify a given trope that is precisely similar to the
trope or tropes he or she was originally acquainted with. Having this in mind,
the solution to the problem of predication is the following: we can apply the
same concept word for many referents of names insofar as we make ourselves able
to distinguish any given trope as precisely similar to a trope model or
those trope models we remember to have experienced.
To highlight the essentials, we can
imagine a simple language game. A group of persons lacking color memories is
placed within an exposition of paintings to find in which paintings a certain
tonality of color can be found. To make this possible, each person receives a
tablet with a patch with a shade of color, its name, and a sheet of paper to
mark the number of the painting where the same shade of color is found. For
instance, suppose that the color is burnt Siena and that the person has marked
paintings 1, 5, and 8 under 12 paintings. Now, this is an exercise of finding
the one over many in which the memory of the model isn’t necessary. Now, the
operation will generate a set. For instance, the set is formed by paintings 1,
5, and 8. This is the set of paintings that have the trope of burnt Siena. The
question is: if there is something that could be called a universal here, what
is it? Two answers are at hand. The first is that the universal is the set
generated in the room's domain, namely, the set formed by the objects 1, 5, and
8. This would be William’s type of answer. The second answer is that the universal
is the trope model of burnt Sienna in the tablet or any other patch of color
that, in the established domain, is precisely similar to the model prescribed
in the tablet. This is the answer that follows Berkeley’s model.
As we noted, the second type of answer
is prior because we begin with the question of how we can apply the same
general term to many different things. We answer it by a cognitive operation
through which we could identify any trope precisely similar to the trope chosen
as a model. We can, however, search for something we could call the
‘ontological universal,’ namely, the set {1, 5, 8}. This set can be generated
by comparing the model and the patches. Its establishment was the finality of
the game, and it can be abstracted from the operations in which the person applies
the same general term to many different things.
Considering the priority of the
cognitive element, I suggest that in the above case, the universal must be
identified with the operation itself, namely, the universalization operation
through which one discovers patches similar to the model.
Going beyond the language game, we can
now consider how a model-trope can produce the universal of burnt Siena.
The universal for the trope
of burnt Siena (Df.) = a (randomly chosen) model trope of color called
‘burnt Siena’ or any other trope that can be identified as precisely similar to
the model trope.
Understood this way, a universal can always, in
principle, generate a set of tropes, which is often impossible to determine in
a real situation. No one knows the innumerable patches of burnt Siena that
could be found worldwide. And no one cares since a metaphysical commitment
becomes idle after the real problem is satisfactorily solved.
We can now generalize our definition
of universal to any trope:
The universal for a trope T
(Df.) = a (randomly chosen) model trope of color called Tm or any
other trope that can be identified as precisely similar to that model trope.
This view has an immense advantage of simplicity.
Though it generates infinite regress, it is a virtuous one. We do not need to
verify whether the precise similarities between models and examples are
precisely similar. Moreover, the simplicity of my example (burnt Siena) should
not deceive. Tropes can be of any complexity. They can also be rules,
satisfying Kant’s condition that to learn a concept is to acquire an ability
governed by rules (Allison 2004: 79-80, 208-9), which is said to have
historically overthrown the simplistic imagism of the empiricist philosophers
Needless to say, unlike the language
game presented above, we usually appeal to memory. We hold in our memory the model
trope, which we once learned to attach with the conceptual word, in the most
primitive cases by perceiving one or more tropes in interpersonal circumstances
of teaching the names of things. Memory has no mystery. It is like a copy of
something by something that we learned to trust because it usually works well
enough to be trusted. Moreover, we do not need to appeal to any fixed model,
and we can change our memorized model arbitrarily as long as it remains
precisely the same as some first concept word was conventionally associated
with a model.
Why have Williams and many others after
him followed the same lead of replacing the universal with a set or a class of
tropes? The answer seems to be the misleading emphasis on the metaphysical commitment,
forgetting that it has only arisen as a sequel of some answer to the relevant
epistemic problem. The universal was traditionally seen by Platonists as the
reference of nominalized predicates, together with the nominalist tradition of
using logic extensions as the reference of predicates. Thus, instead of a class
of objects sharing a property, Williams had the original idea of using a class
of tropes that are precisely similar. Interesting as it was, this choice in the
end betrays what Wittgenstein called those persisting “images” that insistently
trouble philosophers because they forget to consider what they were looking for
in the first place.
Literature:
Allison, H. E. (2004): Kant’s Transcendental
Idealism: An Interpretation and Defense. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Berkeley, George (1973a): The Principles of Human
Knowledge. In Philosophical Works Including the Works on Vision ed.
by M. R, Ayers (London: Everyman).
Berkeley, George (1973b): Three Dialogues Between
Hylas and Philonous. In Philosophical Works Including the Works on Vision ed.
by M. R, Ayers (London: Everyman).
Hume, David (1978): A Treatise of Human Nature.
Edited by L. A. Selby-Bigge, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Maurin, Anna-Sofia (2007): “Infinite Regress: Virtue
or Vice?”, in: Hommage à Wlodek. Philosophical Papers Dedicated to Wlodek
Rabinowicz. Ed. T. Rønnow-Rasmussen, B. Petersson, J. Josefsson & D.
Egonsson.
Plato (1961): The Republic. In The Collected
Dialogues of Plato. Edited by Edith Hamilton and Huntington Cairns.
Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Williams, D. C. (2018): The Elements and Patterns
of Being: Essays in Metaphysics, edited by R. J. Fisher (Oxford: Oxford
University Press).
Wolterstorff, Nicholas (1970): On Universals: An
Essay in Ontology. Chicago: Chicago University Press).
Nenhum comentário:
Postar um comentário