This is from an advanced draft of the book "Philosophical Semantic: Reintegrating Theoretical Philosophy" (CSP 2018)
Chapter II
The Most Suitable Methodology for Conceptual
Analysis
Eine Art zu philosophieren steht nicht neben anderen
wie eine Art zu Tanzen neben anderen Tanzarten ... Die Tanzarten schließen sich
nicht gegenseitig aus oder ein … Aber man kann nicht ernsthaft auf eine Art philosophieren,
ohne die anderen verworfen oder aber einbezogen zu haben. In der Philosophie geht
es demgegenüber wie in jeder Wissenschaft um Wahrheit.
[A way of philosophizing is not one way among others, like
one way of dancing among others … Ways of dancing are not mutually exclusive or
inclusive … But no one can seriously philosophize in one way without having dismissed
or incorporated others. In philosophy as in every science, the concern is with truth.]
—Ernst Tugendhat
Philosophy has no other
roots but the principles of Common Sense; it grows out of them, and draws its nourishment
from them. Severed from this root, its honours wither, its sap is dried up, it dies
and rots.
—Thomas Reid
Given the commonsense assumptions involved when we take
the social role of language as a starting point, at least part of this book must
be critical. The reason is clear. The new orthodoxy that dominates much of contemporary
philosophy of language is largely based on what I wish to call a metaphysics of reference and meaning. Its
views often focus on reference more than on meaning, or on something like reference-as-meaning,
displaying a strong version of semantic externalism, hypostasized causalism, and anti-cognitivism. I call these
views metaphysical not only because they oppose modest common sense but mainly because,
as will be shown, they arise from sophisticated attempts to unduly ‘transcend’ the
limits of what can be meaningfully said (Cf.
Appendixes to Chs. I and II).
One example of the metaphysics of reference
is the position of philosophers like Saul Kripke, Keith Donnellan, and others on
how to explain the referential function of proper names and natural species terms.
According to them, it is not our cognitive access to the world but rather the mere
appeal to external causal chains beginning with acts of baptism that really matters.
On the other hand, what we may have in mind when using a proper name is for them
secondary and contingent.
Another example is the strong externalist view
of Hilary Putnam, John McDowell, Tyler Burge and others, according to whom the conceptual
meaning of an expression, its understanding, thought, and even our own minds (!)
in some way belong to the external (physical, social) world. Using a metaphor always
hinted at but never spelled out, it is as if these things were floating outside,
determined by the entities referred to with words, in a way that recalls Plotinus’
emanations, this time not from the ‘One,’ but in some naturalistic fashion, from
the ‘Many.’ In writing this, I am only
trying to supply the right images for what is explanatorily wanting… In fact, externalism
is an unclean concept. After refinements,
externalism is defined in a vague way as the general idea that ‘certain types of
mental contents must be determined by the external world’ (Lau & Deutsch 2014).
This would be an obvious truism, insofar as we understand the expression ‘determined
by the external world’ as saying that any mental content referring to the external
world is in one way or another causally associated with things belonging
to an external world. As Leszek Kolakowski once noted,
‘if there is nothing outside myself, I am nothing’ (2001). But this is trivial enough
to be accepted by a reasonable internalist like myself (or by a very weak externalist,
which in my view amounts to the same thing). Nonetheless, externalists have proposed
in their most central and radical writings to read ‘determined’ as suggesting that
the locus of our meanings, beliefs, thoughts and even minds is not in our
heads, but somewhere in the external world… However, this sounds very much like
a genetic fallacy.
A third example is the view accepted by David
Kaplan, John Perry, Nathan Salmon and others, according to whom many of our statements
have as their proper semantic contents structured
propositions, whose constituents (things,
properties, relations) belong to the external world alone, as if the external world
had any proper meaning beyond the meaning we give to it. As a last example – which
I examine in the present chapter – we can take the views of John McDowell and Gareth
Evans. According to them, we cannot sum up most of the semantics of our language
in tacit conventional rules that can be made reflexively explicit, as has been traditionally
assumed. Consistent with causal externalism, their semantic carriers tend to take
the form of things that can be understood chiefly in the third person, like the
neuronal machinery responsible for linguistic
dispositions unable to become objects of reflexive consciousness.
Notwithstanding
the fact that most such ideas are contrary to the semantic intuition of any reasonable
human being who hasn’t yet been philosophically indoctrinated, they have become
the mainstream understanding of specialists. Today many theorists still view them
as ‘solid’ results of philosophical inquiry, rather than crystallized products of
ambitious formalist inspired reductionism averse to cognitivism. It is true that
they have in the meantime rhetorically softened their extreme views, though still
holding them in vaguer, more elusive terms. However, if taken too seriously, such
ideas can both stir the imagination of unprepared readers and, more seriously, limit
their scope of inquiry.
In the course of this book, I intend to make
plausible the idea that the metaphysics of reference is far from having found the
ultimate truth of the matter. This is not the same, I must note, as to reject the
originality and philosophical interest of its main arguments. If I did reject them
on this ground, there would be no point in discussing them here. Such philosophical
arguments usually cover insights related to their equivocal conclusions and
remain of interest even if they are in the end-effect flawed. If so, they would
ultimately require not additional support, but careful critical analysis. In the
process of disproving them, we could face views with greater explanatory power,
since philosophical progress is very often dialectical.
For this reason, we should judge the best arguments of the metaphysics of reference
in the same critical way we value McTaggart’s argument against the reality of time
or Berkeley’s remarkable arguments against materialism. Consider Hume’s impressive
skeptical arguments to show there is nothing in the world except flocks of ideas
– an absurd conclusion that was first countered by Thomas Reid. What all these arguments
surely did, even if we are unable to agree with them, was to draw illusory consequences
from insufficiently known conceptual structures, presenting in this way real challenges
to philosophical investigation, useful insofar as they force us to reconsider
our views, answering them by means of a more careful analysis of assumed
structures as they really are. Indeed, without the imaginative and bold revisionism
of the metaphysicians of reference, without the challenges and problems they presented,
it is improbable that corresponding competing views would ever acquire enough intellectual
fuel to get off the ground.
1. Common sense and
meaning
To contend with the metaphysics
of reference, some artillery pieces are essential. They are methodological in character.
The first concerns the decision to take seriously the so often neglected fundamental
principles of common sense and natural language philosophy, respectively assumed
by analytic philosophers like G. E. Moore and the later Wittgenstein. According
to philosophers with this outlook,
we should seek the starting point of our philosophical arguments as much as possible
in pre-philosophical commonsense intuitions often reflected in our natural language.
The link between common sense and natural language is easy to understand. We should
expect that commonsense intuitions – often due to millennia of cultural sedimentation – will come to be strongly
mirrored in our linguistic forms and practices.
As Noah Lemos wrote, we can characterize commonsense
knowledge as:
...a set of truths that we know fairly well, that have
been held at all times and by almost everyone, that do not seem to be outweighed
by philosophical theories asserting their falsity, and that can be taken as data
for assessing philosophical theories (2004: 5).
Indeed, commonsense truths seem
to have always reconfirmed themselves, often approaching species wisdom. Examples
of common sense statements are: ‘Black isn’t white,’ ‘Fire burns,’ ‘Material things
exist,’ ‘The past existed,’ ‘I am a human being,’ ‘I have feelings,’ ‘Other people
exist,’ ‘The Earth has existed for many years,’ ‘I have never been very far from
the Earth,’… (See Moore 1959: 32-45).
Philosophers have treasured some of these commonsense statements as particularly
worthy of careful analytical scrutiny. These include: ‘A thing is itself’ (principle
of identity), ‘The same thought cannot be both true and false’ (principle of non-contradiction),
‘I exist as a thinking being’ (version of the cogito), ‘The external world is real’ (expressing a realist position
on the external world’s existence), and even ‘A thought is true if it agrees with
reality’ (correspondence theory of truth).
The most flagrant objection to the validity
of commonsense principles is that they are not absolutely certain. Clearly, a statement
like ‘Fire burns’ isn’t beyond any possibility of falsification. Moreover, science
has truly falsified many commonsense beliefs. Einstein’s relativity theory decisively
refuted the commonsense belief that the length of a physical object remains the
same independently of its velocity. But there was a time when people regarded this
belief as a self-evident truth!
This latter kind of objection is particularly
important in our context because metaphysicians of reference have made this point
to justify philosophy of language theories that contradict common sense. Just as
in modern physics new theories often conflict with common sense, they feel emboldened
to advance a new philosophy whose conclusions depart radically from common sense
and natural language. As Hilary Putnam wrote to justify the strangeness of his externalist
theory of meaning:
Indeed, the upshot of our discussion will be that meanings
don’t exist in quite the way we tend to think they do. But electrons don’t exist
in quite the way Bohr thought they did, either. (1978: 216)
One answer to this kind of comparison
emphasizes the striking differences between philosophy of meaning and physics: the
way we arrive at meanings is much more
direct than the way we discover the nature of subatomic particles. We make meanings;
we don’t make electrons. We find subatomic particles by empirical research; we don’t
find meanings: we establish them. We do not need to read Plato’s Cratylus to realize that the meanings of
our words are dependent on our shared semantic customs and conventions.
2. Ambitious versus
Modest Common Sense
I do not have the ambition to end
the debates over the ultimate value
of common sense. However, I can reasonably
demonstrate
that two deeply ingrained objections to the validity of commonsense principles are seriously flawed, one based on
the progress of science and the other based on changes in our worldviews (Weltanschauungen). The first is that science
defeats common sense. This can
be illustrated by the claim attributed to Albert Einstein that common sense is a
collection of prejudices acquired by the age of eighteen… (Most physicists are philosophically
naïve.) Changes in worldviews are transformations in our whole system of beliefs,
affecting deeply settled ideas like moral values and religious beliefs. In my view,
these two charges against common sense are faulty because they arise from confusion
between misleading ambitious formulations
of commonsense truths and their authentic formulations, which I call modest ones.
I wish to begin with a closer examination of
objections based on the progress of science. With regard to empirical science, consider
the sentences:
(a) The Earth is a flat
disk with land in the center surrounded by water.
(b) The sun is a bright
sphere that revolves around the Earth every 24 hours.
(c) Heavy bodies fall more
rapidly than light ones, disregarding air resistance.
(d) Time flows uniformly,
even for a body moving near the speed of light.
(e) Light consists of extremely
small particles.
According to the objection, it
is widely known that science has disproved all
these once commonsense statements. Already in Antiquity, Eratosthenes of
Alexandria was able to disprove the Homeric view that (a) the Earth is a flat disk
rimmed by water by measuring the circumference of the Earth with reasonable precision.
Galileo showed that (b) and (c) are false statements, the first because the Earth
circles the sun, the second because in a vacuum all bodies fall with the same acceleration.
And Einstein’s relativity theory predicted that time becomes exponentially slower
as a body approaches the speed of light, falsifying statement (d). Bertrand Russell
once pointed out that the theory of relativity showed that statement (d), like some
other important commonsense beliefs, cannot withstand precise scientific examination
(Cf. Russell 1925, Ch. 1; Popper 1972,
Ch. 2, sec. 2). Finally, statement (e), affirming the seemingly commonsense corpuscular
theory of light (defended by Newton, but already in some way evinced in Antiquity), has been found to be mistaken, since light consists
of transverse waves (Huygens-Young theory), even though under certain conditions
it behaves as though it consisted of particles (wave-particle theory).
The point I wish to emphasize, however, is
that none of the five above-cited statements legitimately belongs to correctly understood common
sense – a sense I call ‘modest.’ If we examine these statements more closely, we
see they are in fact extrapolations grounded
on statements of modest common sense. These extrapolations are of speculative interest
and were made in the name of science by scientists and even by philosophers projecting
ideas of common sense into new domains that would later belong to science. In my
view, the true statements of common sense – the modest statements for which (a),
(b), (c), (d) and (e) could be the corresponding non-modest extrapolations – are
respectively the following:
(a’) The Earth is flat.
(b’) Each day the sun crosses the sky.
(c’) Heavier bodies around us fall
more rapidly than lighter ones.
(d’) Time flows uniformly for all bodies
around us, independently of their motion.
(e’) Light has rays.
Now, what is at stake is that these
statements have been made for thousands of years and have been confirmed thousands of times by everyday observation and
continue to be confirmed, independently of the scientific development. It is obvious
that (a’) is a true statement if we understand it to mean that when we look at the
world around us without having the ambition to generalize this observation to the
whole Earth, we see that – discounting hills, valleys, and mountains – the landscape
is obviously flat. Statement (b’) is also true since it is anterior to the distinction
between the real and the apparent motion of the sun. If we consider only the
apparent motion of the sun, we see that the sentence ‘The sun crosses the sky each
day’ can be considered true without implying that the sun revolves around the Earth.
All it affirms is that in equatorial and sub-equatorial regions of the Earth we
see that each day the sun rises in the East, crosses the sky, and sets in the West,
which no sensible person would ever doubt.[1] Even after science proved that
bodies of different masses fall with the same acceleration in a vacuum, statement
(c’) remains true for everyday experience. After all, it only affirms the commonplace
notion that under ordinary conditions a light object such as a feather falls much
more slowly than a heavy one such as a stone... Statement (d’) also remains true,
since it concerns the movements of things in our surroundings, leaving aside extremely
high speeds or incredibly accurate measurements of time. (In everyday life, one
would never need to measure time dilation, which is detectable only when a body
approaches the speed of light and
has nothing
to do with everyday experience. In everyday
life, no one ever comes home from a two-week bus trip to discover that family members
are now many years older than before). Finally, (e’) has been accepted, at least
since Homer, as is shown by his poetic epithet ‘rosy-fingered dawn.’ And we often
see sunbeams at dawn or dusk or peeping
through gaps in the clouds on overcast days.
But then, what is the point in comparing statements
(a)-(b)-(c)-(d)-(e) with the corresponding statements (a’)-(b’)-(c’)-(d’)-(e’),
making the first set refutable by science, while the latter statements remain true?
The answer is that scientifically or speculatively motivated commonsense statements
exemplified by (a)-(b)-(c)-(d)-(e) have very often been viewed equivocally as if
they were legitimate commonsense statements. However, statements of modest common
sense like (a’)-(b’)-(c’)-(d’)-(e’) are the only ones naturally originating from
community life, being omnipresent in the most ordinary linguistic practices. They
continue to be perfectly reliable despite the theoretical conclusions of Galileo and Einstein, since their
truth is independent of science. The contrast between these two kinds of example
shows how mistaken the claim is that many or most commonsense truths have been refuted
by science. What science has refuted are extrapolations of commonsense truths by
scientists and philosophers who have projected such humble commonsense truths beyond
the narrow limits of their original context. If we take into account the aforementioned
distinction, we find a lack of conflict between the discoveries of science and the
claims of commonsense wisdom, also including ones used as examples by philosophers
like G. E. Moore. [2]
I do not claim modest commonsense truths are
in principle irrefutable, but only that no one has managed to refute them. Nothing
warrants, for instance, asserting that from now on the world around us will be different
in fundamental ways. A statement like (b’) can be falsified. Perhaps for some unexpected
reason, the Earth’s rotation on its axis will slow down so much that the sun will
cease its apparent movement across the sky. In this case, (b’) would also be refuted
for our future expectations. But even in this case, (b’) remains true concerning
the past, while the corresponding ambitious extrapolation (b) has always been false.
In fact, all I want to show is that true commonsense statements – modest ones –
are much more reliable than scientifically oriented minds believe, and science has
been unable to refute them, insofar as we take them at their proper, humble face
value.
Similar reasoning applies to the a priori knowledge of common sense. To justify
this new claim, consider first the case of statements like (i) ‘Goodness is praiseworthy,’
which is grammatically identical with statements like (ii) ‘Socrates is wise.’ Both
have the same superficial subject-predicate grammatical structure. Since in the
first case the subject ‘Goodness’ does not designate any object accessible to the
senses, Plato would have concluded that this subject must refer to ‘goodness-in-itself’:
the purely intelligible idea of goodness,
existing in an eternal and immutable non-visible realm only accessible to the intellect.
Plato reached his conclusion based on the commonplace grammatical distinction between
subject and predicate found in natural language. Under this assumption, he was likely
to see a statement like (iii) ‘Goodness in itself exists’ as a commonsensical truth.
In fact, according to his doctrine, it should be an a priori truth.
However, we know that with Frege’s introduction
of quantificational logic at the end of the 19th century, it became clear that statements
like (i) should have a deep logical structure that is much more complex than the
subject-predicate structure of (ii). Statement (i) should be analyzed as saying
that all good things are praiseworthy, or (iv) ‘For all x, if x is good, then x is praiseworthy,’ where the supposed proper
name ‘Goodness’ disappears and is replaced by the predicate ‘… is good.’ This new
kind of analysis reduced considerably the pressure to countenance the Platonic doctrine
of ideas.
However, the suggestion that the subject ‘Goodness’
refers to an abstract idea clearly does not belong to modest common sense, and statement
(iii), ‘Goodness in itself exists,’ isn’t even inscribed in our natural language.
It also belongs to ambitious
common sense. Statement (iii) was a speculative extrapolation by a philosopher based
on an implicit appeal to the superficial grammar of natural language, and although
(iii) is probably false, it would be unjust to blame modest common sense and our
ordinary language intuitions on subject-predicate grammar. Finally, it is wise to remember that quantificational
truth-functional logic has not undermined the (commonsensical) grammar of
our natural language; it has only selected and made us conscious of vastly extended
fundamental patterns underlying the representative function of natural language.
What all these examples do is to undermine
the frequently made claim that scientific progress contradicts common sense. Scientific
discoveries only refute speculative extrapolations of common sense and natural language
made by scientists and philosophers, such as the idea that the Sun revolves around
the Earth or that there is a purely intelligible world made up of abstract ideas
like that of Goodness in itself. But nothing of the sort has to do with the explanations
given by modest common sense, the only ones long established by mankind’s shared practical experience down through the ages.
3. Resisting changes
in worldviews
Finally, I wish to consider commonsense
ideas that are challenged by changes in our worldviews. This is, for instance, the
case with the belief that a personal God exists or that we have minds independently
of our bodies. The objection is the following. The overwhelming majority of cultures
accept a God (or gods) and the soul as undeniably real. In Western Civilization, for the last two-thousand years society has even sanctioned
denial of these beliefs with varying degrees of severity, sometimes even resorting
to capital punishment. Although they were once commonsense beliefs, today no one
would say that they are almost universally accepted. On the contrary, few scientifically
educated persons would agree with them. Consequently, it seems that common sense
ideas can change in response to changes in our worldviews...
My reaction to this does not differ very much
from my response to the objection contrasting
common sense with the progress of science. Beliefs regarding our worldviews lack
universality, not really belonging to what could be called modest common sense.
There are entire civilizations, particularly in Asia, where the idea of a personal
God is foreign to the dominant religion. Regarding the soul, I remember a story
told by an anthropologist who once asked a native Brazilian what happens after people
die. The native answered: – ‘They stay around.’ – ‘And later?’ asked the anthropologist.
– ‘They go into some tree.’ – ‘And then?’ – ‘Then they disappear’...[3] The lack of concern was evident.
And the unavoidable conclusion is that belief in a personal God and an eternal soul
do not enjoy the kind of universality that would be expected of modest common sense;
if they are said to belong to common sense, this must be an ambitious form of common sense. In fact, these beliefs seem to
result from the distortion of ordinary views through wishful thinking, which has
happened particularly in Western culture.[4]
Natural language also supports the view that
these beliefs are not chiefly commonsensical: a person holding religious beliefs
usually does not say he knows that he
has a soul independent of his body… He prefers to
claim he believes in these things. And
even this belief has a particular name: ‘faith,’ which is belief not supported by
reason and observation (against faith there are no arguments). On the other hand,
the same person would never deny that he knows
there is an external world and that he knows
this world existed long before he was born… Modest commonsense knowledge is not
a question of wishful thinking or non-rational faith.
What all these arguments suggest is that modestly understood commonsense truths – together
with the very plausible discoveries of real science – can reasonably be said to
form the basis of our rationality, the highest tribunal of reason. Furthermore,
since science itself can only be constructed starting from a foundation of accepted
modest commonsense beliefs, it does not seem possible, even in principle, to deny
modest common sense as a whole on the
authority of science without also having to deny the very foundations of rationality.
Not only do science and changes in our worldview
seem unable to refute modest common sense, even skeptical hypotheses cannot do this
in the highly persuasive way one could expect. Suppose, for instance, that radical
skeptics are right, and you discover that until now you have lived in what was just
an illusory world… Even in this case, you would be unable to say that the world
where you lived until now was unreal in
the most important sense of the word. For that world would still be fully real in
the sense that people perceived it with maximal intensity, and it was independent
of the will, was interpersonally accessible and obeyed natural laws… These are criterial
conditions that when together satisfied create our conventional sense of reality,
a sense in itself indefeasible even by skeptical scenarios (See Ch. VI, sec. 29).
4. Primacy of Established
Knowledge
The upshot of the comparison between
modest common sense and science is that we can see science as not opposed to modest
common sense, but rather as its proper extension, so that both can be mutually
supportive. According to this view, science
is expanded common sense. Contrary to Wilfrid Sellars (1962: 35-78), the so-called
‘scientific image of the world’ did not develop in opposition to or even independently
of the old ‘manifest image of the world,’ for there is no conflict between them.
This conclusion reinforces our confidence that underlying everything we can find
commonsense truths, insofar as they are judiciously identified and understood.
In endorsing this view, I do not claim that
unaided modest commonsense truth can resist philosophical arguments, as philosophers
like Thomas Reid seem to have assumed. One cannot refute Berkeley’s anti-materialism
by kicking a stone or answer Zeno’s paradox of the impossibility of movement by
putting one foot in front of the other. These skeptical arguments must be wrong,
but to disprove them, philosophical arguments are needed to show why they seemingly make sense, again grounding
their rejection at least partially in other domains of common sense if not science,
something reached only by the comprehensiveness of philosophical reasoning. Hence,
what I wish to maintain is that the principles of modest common sense serve as the
most reliable assumptions and that some fundamental modest commonsense principles
will always be needed if we do not wish to lose our footing in everyday reality.
I reject the proposal that a philosophy based
on modest common sense and its effects on natural language intuitions would be sufficient.
It is imperative to develop philosophical views compatible with and complementing
modern science. We must construct philosophy on a foundation of common sense informed by science. That is: insofar as
formal reasoning (logic, mathematics…) and empirical science (physics, biology,
psychology, sociology, neuroscience, linguistics...) can add new extensions and
elements beyond modest commonsense principles, and these extensions and elements
are relevant to philosophy, they should be taken into account. As we saw above,
it was through the findings of predicate calculus that we came to know that the
subject ‘goodness’ in the sentence ‘Goodness is praiseworthy’ should not be logically
interpreted as a subject referring to a Platonic idea, since what this sentence
really means is ‘For all x, if x is good, x is praiseworthy.’
I will use the term established knowledge for the totality that includes modest commonsense
knowledge and all the extensions the scientific community accepts as scientific
knowledge. Any sufficiently well-informed and reasonable person would agree with
this kind of knowledge, insofar as he would be able to properly understand and evaluate
it. It is in this revised sense that we should reinterpret the Heraclitean dictum that we must rely on common knowledge
as a city relies on its walls.
The upshot of these methodological remarks
is that we should judge the plausibility of our philosophical ideas against the
background of established knowledge, that is, comparing them with the results of
scientifically informed common sense. We may call this the principle of the primacy of established knowledge, admonishing
us to make our philosophical theses consistent with it. Philosophical activity,
particularly as descriptive metaphysics,[5] should seek reflexive equilibrium with the widest possible range of established knowledge,
the knowledge mutually supported by both modest common sense and scientific results.
This is the ultimate source of philosophical credibility.
Finally, if we find inconsistencies in challenging
speculative philosophical theories because they seem to debunk much or our established
knowledge, we should treat them as paradoxes of thought, even if they can be very
instructive, and should search for arguments that reconcile these products of philosophical
speculation with established knowledge. Lacking reconciliation, we should treat
philosophical theses only as proposals,
even if they can be sometimes extraordinarily stimulating from a speculative viewpoint,
as is the case of revisionary metaphysics, superbly exemplified by Leibniz, Berkeley and Hume and
in some measure also by most American analytic philosophers since W. V-O. Quine.
This acknowledgment does not mean that their results require acceptance as ‘solid’
discoveries, but rather that they deserve attentive consideration, the sort we grant
to the best cases of expansionist scientism. To proceed otherwise can lead us down
the slippery slope to dogmatism.
5. Philosophizing by
examples
We must complement our methodological
principle of the primacy of established knowledge with what Avrum Stroll called
the method of philosophizing by examples
(1998, x-xi). He himself used this method to construct relevant arguments against
Putnam’s externalism of meaning.
Stroll was a Wittgenstein specialist, and Wittgenstein’s
therapeutic conception of philosophy directly inspired his approach. According to
Wittgenstein, at least one relevant way of doing philosophy is by performing philosophical
therapy. This therapy consists in comparing the speculative use of expressions in
philosophy – which is very often misleading – with a variety of examples, most of
them of their everyday usage – where these expressions earn their proper meanings,
using a method of similarity and contrast to clear up the confusion. He thought this therapy was only possible through meticulous
comparative examination of various real and imaginary concrete examples of
intuitively correct and even incorrect uses of expressions. This would make it possible
to clarify the true meanings of our words so that the hidden absurdities of metaphysics
would become evident... Since contemporary philosophy of language tends to be unduly
metaphysically oriented, and in this way diametrically opposed to the kind of philosophy
practiced by Wittgenstein, a similar critique of language, complemented by theoretical
reflection, is what much of contemporary philosophy needs in order to find its way back to truth.
I intend to show that today’s metaphysics of
reference and meaning suffers from a failure to consider adequately, above all the
subtle nuances of linguistic praxis. It suffers from an accumulation of potentially
obscurantist products of what Wittgenstein called ‘conceptual houses of cards’ resulting
from ‘knots of thought’ – subtle semantic equivocations caused by a pressing desire
for innovation combined with a lack of more careful attention to nuanced distinctions
of meaning that expressions receive in different contexts where they are profitably
used, also because the reason why they might be interesting is that they are by
queer ways magnifying some real insight.
One criticism of Wittgenstein’s therapeutic
view of philosophy is that it would confine philosophy to the limits of the commonplace.
Admittedly, there is no good reason to deny that the value of philosophy resides
largely in its theoretical and systematic dimensions, in its persistent attempt
to make substantive generalizations. I tend to agree with this, since I also believe
that in its proper way philosophy can and should be theoretical, even speculatively
theoretical. Nonetheless, I think we can to a great extent successfully counter
this objection to Wittgenstein’s views, first interpretatively and then systematically.
From the interpretative side, we have reason
to think that the objection misunderstands some subtleties of Wittgenstein’s position.
The most authoritative interpreters of Wittgenstein, G. P. Baker and P. M. S. Hacker,
insisted that he did not reject philosophical theorizing tout court. In rejecting philosophical theorizing,
he was opposing scientism: the kind of
philosophical theorizing that mimics science.
Scientism tries to reduce philosophy itself to science in its procedures, range,
and contents, as he personally saw happening in logical positivism.[6] Instead, he would countenance
a different sort of theorizing, particularly the ‘dynamic,’[7] the ‘organic’ instead of ‘architectonic’
(Wittgenstein 2001: 43) – a distinction he seems to have learned from Schopenhauer
(Hilmy 1987: 208-9). This helps explain why, in a famous passage of Philosophical Investigations, he argued that
it is both possible and even necessary to construct surveillable representations (übersichtliche
Darstellungen). These can show the complex logical-grammatical structure of
the concepts making up the most central domains of understanding. As he wrote:
A main source of our failure to understand is that
we do not command a clear view of the use of our words – Our grammar is lacking
in this sort of surveillability. A surveillable representation produces just that
understanding which consists in ‘seeing connections’; hence the importance of finding
and inventing intermediate cases. The concept of surveillable representation is
of fundamental significance for us. It earmarks the form of account we give, the
way we look at things (Is this a ‘Weltanschauung’?).
(1984c, sec. 122)
Now, in a sense, a surveillable representation must
be theoretical since it must contain generalization,
and this constitutes the ultimate core of what the word ‘they’ means. (Well aware of this, Karl
Popper famously called the statement ‘All swans are white’ a theory, adding that this theory was falsified
by the discovery of black swans in Australia…) If we agree that all generalizations are theoretical, any surveillable representation, as it
must contain generalizations, must also be theoretical.
Moreover, the addition of intermediate connections already existent but not explicitly named by the expressions
of ordinary language justifies our making explicit of previous well-grounded conventions
that serve as links connecting a multitude of cases. It is possible that because
of the generality and function of these links, they never need to emerge in linguistically
expressible forms (consider, for instance, our MD-rule for proper names). Expositions
of these links are properly called ‘descriptive,’ insofar as they are already present
under the surface of language. But it is fully acceptable to call them ‘theoretical’
– in the sense of a description of general principles inherent to natural language
– if they are intended to be the right way to assure the unity in diversity that
our usage of expressions is able to achieve.
The addition of intermediary connections helps to explain why normal language philosophy,
as initially developed by Gilbert Ryle and J. L. Austin gradually transformed itself
into far more liberal and theoretical forms of philosophy inspired by natural language
that we can already find in some works of P. F. Strawson and later in H. P. Grice[8] and John Searle. It also helps
to justify the introduction of new technical
terms to fill the gaps in natural language.
Terms like ‘criterion,’ ‘language-game,’ ‘grammatical sentence,’ ‘forms of
life’ and even ‘surveillable representation’ support this point in Wittgenstein’s
own writings. In fact, even Austin, the chief defender of a quasi-lexicographical
ordinary language analysis didn’t eschew the creation of new technical terms. Expressions
like ‘locutionary act’ (composed of ‘phonetic,’ ‘phatic’ and ‘rhetic acts’), ‘illocutionary
act’ and ‘perlocutionary act’ (1962, Lect. VIII) were created as the only way to
express – guided by reasoning on interactive linguistic activity – fundamental deep
structures totally unexpressed in our normal usage.
Now, from the systematic argumentative side,
we can say that independently of the way we interpret Wittgenstein, there are good
reasons to believe theoretical considerations are indispensable. An important point
is that philosophy can only be therapeutic or critical because its work is inevitably
based on theoretical, that is, generalized assumptions that make possible its therapeutic
efficacy. Usually, Wittgenstein did not explicitly state or develop the assumptions
needed to make his conceptual therapy convincing. He was an intuitive thinker in
the style of Heracleitus or Nietzsche. Because of this, he all too often did not
develop his insights beyond the epigrammatic level. In any case, general assumptions
are inevitable if our aim is expose equivocal views in an efficacious way: The critical
(therapeutic) and the more constructive (theoretical) searches for surveillable
representations can be understood as two complementary sides of the same analytical
coin (Costa 1990: 7 f.). Theoretical assumptions are the indispensable active principle
of logic-conceptual therapeutic potions.
Recapitulating, we have found two main methodological
principles for orienting our research in this book:
A.
The principle of the primacy of established knowledge (our principle of all principles),
according to which modest common sense, complemented by scientific knowledge, constitutes
the highest tribunal of reason in judging the plausibility of philosophical views.
B.
The method of philosophizing
by examples, according to which the best way to orient ourselves in the philosophical
jungle is to test our ideas in all possible opportunities by analyzing a sufficient
number of different examples. If we do not use this method, we risk losing ourselves
in a labyrinth of empty if not fallacious abstractions.
Oriented by the two above-considered
methodological principles, I intend to accomplish several tasks, which are fundamental
if we wish to put philosophy again on the right track.
6. Tacit knowledge
of meaning: traditional explanation
I will assume the practically indisputable
notion that language is a system of signs basically governed by conventionally grounded
rules, including semantic ones. Linguistic conventions are rules obeyed by most
participants in the linguistic community. These participants expect other participants
to comply with similar or complementary rules and vice-versa, even if they aren’t
really aware of them (Cf. Grice 1989,
Ch. 2; Lewis 2002: 42). According to this view, the sufficiently shared character
of language conventions is what makes possible the use of language to communicate
thoughts.
One of the most fundamental assumptions of
the old orthodoxy in philosophy of language is that we lack awareness of the effective structures of semantically relevant
rules governing the uses of our language’s most central conceptual expressions.
We know how to apply the rules, but the rules are not available for explicit examination.
Thus, we are unable to command a clear view of the complex network of tacit agreements
involved. The reason is the way we learn expressions in our language. Wittgenstein
noted that we learn the meaning-rules governing the correct use of our linguistic
expressions not by means of explicit definitions, but by training (Abrichtung), that
is, through informal practice, imitation, and correction by others who already know
how to use them properly. Later analytic philosophers, from Gilbert Ryle to P. F.
Strawson, Michael Dummett, and Ernst Tugendhat, have always insisted that we do
not learn the semantically relevant conventions of our language (i.e., the semantic-cognitive rules determining referential
use of expressions) through verbal definitions, but rather in non-reflexive,
unconscious ways. Tugendhat wrote that we learn many of these rules in childhood
through ostension by means of positive and negative examples given in interpersonal
contexts: other speakers confirm them when correct and disconfirm them when incorrect.
Hence, the final proof that we understand these rules is interpersonal confirmation
of their correct application. (Tugendhat & Wolf 1983: 140) For this reason,
it is often so hard or seemingly impossible to obtain an explicit verbal analysis
of the meaning of an expression that is really able to reveal its meaning-rules.
Using Gilbert Ryle’s terms, with regard to these meaning-rules we have knowing how, i.e., skill, competence, an automatized ability that enables
us to apply them correctly; but this is insufficient to warrant knowing that, namely, the capacity to report what we mean verbally (1990: 28
f.).
This non-reflexive learning of semantic rules
applies particularly to philosophical terms like ‘knowledge,’ ‘consciousness,’ ‘understanding,’
‘perception,’ ‘causality,’ ‘action,’ ‘free will,’ ‘goodness,’ ‘justice,’ ‘beauty,’
which are central to our understanding of the world (Tugendhat 1992: 268). Because
of their more complex conceptual structure and internal relationships with other
central concepts, these concepts are particularly elusive and resistant to analysis,
opening room to the most various intentions. This insight certainly also applies
to conceptual words from philosophy of language, like ‘meaning,’ ‘reference,’ ‘existence’
and ‘truth,’ which will be examined later in this book. Finally, to make things
more complicated, relevant concepts are also in a sense empirically grounded and
not completely immune to additions and changes resulting from the growth of our
knowledge. For instance: before recent advances in neuroscience, bodily movement
was considered essential to the philosophical analysis of the concept of action.
Now, with sensitive devices able to respond to electrical discharges in our motor-cortex,
we are able to move external objects using sheer willpower. Intentions unaided by
bodily movements are now sufficient to produce external physical motions intended
by the agent (See neuroprosthetics and
BCIs).
However, lack of semantic awareness can become
a reason for serious intellectual confusion when philosophers try to explain what
these terms mean. Philosophers are very
often under the pressure of some generalizing purpose extrinsic to that required
by the proper nature of their object of investigation. Consider theistic purposes
in the Middle Ages and scientistic purposes in our time,
which can easily produce startling but erroneous magnifications hinging on minor real findings. Wittgenstein
repeatedly expressed these metaphilosophical
views throughout his entire career. Here are some of his best quotes, in chronological
order, beginning with his Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus
and ending with his Philosophical Investigations:
Natural language is part
of the human organism and not less complicated than it. ... The conventions that
are implicit for the understanding of natural language are enormously complicated.
(1984g, sec. 4.002)
Philosophers constantly
see the method of science before their eyes and are irresistibly tempted to ask
and answer questions the way science does. This tendency is the real source of metaphysics,
and leads the philosopher into complete darkness. (1958: 24)
We can solve the problems
not by giving new information, but by arranging what we have always known. Philosophy
is a battle against the bewitchment of our intellect by language. (1984c sec. 109)
The aspects of things
that are most important for us are hidden because of their simplicity and familiarity.
(One is unable to notice something – because it is always before one’s eyes.) The
real foundations of his inquiry do not strike a person at all. Unless that fact
has at some time struck him. – And this means: we fail to be struck by what, once
seen, is most striking and most powerful. (1984c, sec.129)
Contrary to empirical
statements, rules of grammar describe how we use words in order to both justify
and criticize our particular utterances. But as opposed to grammar book rules, they
are not idealized as an external system to be conformed to. Moreover, they are not
appealed to explicitly in any formulation, but are used in cases of philosophical
perplexity to clarify where language misleads us into false illusions … (A whole
cloud of philosophy is condensed into a drop of grammar.) (1984c, II xi)
Around the mid-twentieth century,
a number of analytical philosophers were in significant ways directly or indirectly
influenced by Wittgenstein views. They believed clarification resulting from the
work of making explicit the tacit conventions that give meaning to our natural language
was a kind of revolutionary procedure: We should identify most if not all philosophical
problems with conceptual problems that could be solved (or dissolved) by means of
conceptual analysis.
Notwithstanding, except for the acquisition
of new formal analytical instruments and a new pragmatic concern leading to more
rigorous and systematic attention to the subtleties of linguistic interaction, there
was nothing truly revolutionary in the philosophy of linguistic analysis and the
critique of language associated with it. Analysis of the meaning of philosophically
relevant terms as an attempt to describe the real structure of our thinking about
the world is no more than the resumption of a project centrally present in the whole
history of Occidental philosophy. Augustine wrote: ‘What,
then, is time? If no one asks me, I know; if I wish to explain it to him who asks,
I know not.’ (2008, lib. XI, Ch. XIV, sec. 17) In fact, we find the same
concern already voiced by Plato. If we examine questions posed in Plato’s Socratic
dialogues, they all have the form ‘What is X?,’ where X takes the place of philosophically relevant conceptual words like
‘temperance,’ ‘justice,’ ‘virtue,’ ‘love,’ ‘knowledge’… What then follows
are attempts to find a definition able to resist objections and counterexamples.
After some real progress, discussion usually ends in an aporetic way due to merciless
conceptual criticism. That is, philosophy based on analysis of conceptual meaning
has always been with us. It is the main foundation of our philosophical tradition,
even when it is hidden behind its most systematic
and speculative forms.[9]
Finally,
by defending the view that philosophy’s main job is to analyze implicit conceptual
knowledge, I am not
claiming that philosophy cannot be about the world, as some have objected (Magee
1999, Ch. 23). Even as an inquiry turned to our conceptual network, philosophy continues
to be about the world, because the concepts analyzed by philosophy are in one way or another about the world. Moreover, in a
systematic philosophical work, central concepts of our understanding of the world are analyzed in their internal relations with other
central concepts, with the same result that philosophy is indirectly also about
the world – about the world as it is synthetically reflected by the central core
of our conceptual network.[10]
Indeed,
even if the philosophical analysis of our conceptual structures does not depend
on empirical experience as such, empirical experience has already in one way or
another entered into the production and change of such
conceptual structures.
7. A very simple model
of a semantic-cognitive rule
We urgently need to clarify the structures of
our semantic-cognitive rules as the concept is used here. However, it is not very helpful if
we begin by attempting to analyze a conceptual rule constitutive of a philosophical
concept-word. Not only are these concept-words usually polysemic, but the structures
of central meaning-rules expressed by them are much more complex and harder to analyze
and in this way to characterize or define. Anyway, although philosophical definitions
can be extremely difficult to achieve, the skeptical conclusion that they are impossible
can well be too hasty.
To get a glimpse into the nature of a semantic-cognitive
rule – in the case an ascription rule[11] – I strategically chose a very
trivial concept-word, since its logical grammar is correspondingly easier to grasp.
Thus, I wish to scrutinize here the standard meaning of the concept-word ‘chair,’
using it as a simple model that can illustrate our approach to investigating the
much more complicated philosophical concepts. We all know the meaning of the word
‘chair,’ though it would not be so easy to give a precise definition if someone
asked for one. Now, following Wittgenstein’s motto, according to which ‘the meaning
of a word is what the explanation of its meaning explains’ (1984g, sec. 32), I offer
a very reasonable definition (explanation) of the meaning of the word ‘chair.’ You
can even find something not far from it in the best dictionaries. This definition
expresses the characterizing ascription rule of this concept-word, which is the
following:
(C) Chair (Df.) = a non-vehicular seat with a backrest,
designed for use by only one person at a time (it usually has four legs, sometimes has armrests, is sometimes upholstered,
etc.).[12]
In this definition, the conditions
stated outside of parentheses are necessary and together sufficient: first a chair must be a non-vehicular seat (since seats
in cars and airplanes… aren’t called chairs); second, a chair must be a seat with
a backrest (since without a backrest it would be only a stool, a sattle seat,
etc.); and third, it must be an artifact designed for a single person to seat
at a time. These criterial conditions form an essential, indispensable condition, also called the definitional or primary criterion for the
applicability of the concept-word, to use Wittgenstein’s terminology.
What follows in parentheses are complementary (dispensable)
secondary criteria or symptoms: usually, a chair has four legs,
often it has armrests, and sometimes it is upholstered. These indications can be
helpful in identifying chairs, even though they are irrelevant if the definitional
criterion isn’t satisfied. A chair need not have armrests, but there cannot be a
chair with armrests but no backrest (this would be a bench). Thus, with (C) we have
an expression of our implicit conventional ascription rule for the general term
‘chair,’ which should belong to the domain of what Frege calls sense (Sinn).[13]
Though I do not think that this definition couldn’t be improved (or
changed), I find it hard to oppose it. Table-chairs, armchairs, easy chairs, rocking
chairs, wheelchairs, beach chairs, electric chairs, thrones… all conform to the
definition (a kneeling chair without backrest is rather a so-called chair). The definition gives the core of the conceptual meaning,
while the different types of chair are recognized as sub-concepts adding to the
core a diversity of sub-conceptual modulations.[14] However, car, bus and airplane seats are not called ‘chairs’ but by
convention seats, only because they are made to bring persons in vehicles from
a place to another. Anyway, we can always imagine borderline cases. There could be a seat whose backrest is only 20 cm.
high (is it a stool or a chair?), a chair with a seat raised only 10 cm. above the
floor (is it even a seat?), a chair whose backrest was removed for some hours (did
it become a backless chair or provisionally a stool?). Suppose we find a tree trunk
in a forest with the form of a chair that, with some minor carving and painting,
is now being used as a chair (it was not manufactured as a chair, but minor changes
turned it into something we could maybe call a real chair, depending on the relevance
of the changes). Nevertheless, our definition is still reasonable despite vague
borderline cases. Empirical concepts all have some degree of vagueness, and one
can even argue that vagueness is a metaphysical property of reality. Indeed, if
our definition of a chair had overly sharp boundaries, it would be inadequate, since
it would not reflect the desired flexibility of application belonging to
our normal word ‘chair,’ tending
to stiffen the extension of the concept.
An often
overlooked point is that language is a pragmatic device: what really justifies a semantic-cognitive rule is its practical applicability
to common cases. That is, what really matters are cases to which we can apply
the ascription rule without much hesitation and not those rare borderline cases
where we cannot know if the ascription rule is definitely applicable, since the
rarity of these cases, so much praised by philosophers, makes them irrelevant from
a practical point of view. Accordingly, the function of a concept-word is far from
being discredited by a few borderline cases where we are at a loss to decide whether
it is still applicable.
Furthermore,
we need to distinguish real chairs from ‘so-called chairs,’ because in such cases
we are making an extended or even a metaphorical use of the word. A child’s toy
chair, like a sculptured chair, is a chair in an extended sense of the word. In
Victor Hugo’s novel Toilers of the Sea,
the main character ends his life by sitting on a ‘chair of rock’ on the seashore,
waiting to be swept away by the tide... But it is clear from our definition that
this use of the word is metaphorical: a real chair must be made by someone since it is an artifact, but the immovable stone chair was only a natural
object accidentally shaped by erosion into the rough form of a chair and then used
as a chair.
There
are also cases that only seem to contradict the definition, but that on closer examination
do not. Consider the following two cases, already presented as supposed counterexamples
(Elbourne 2011, Ch. 1). The first is the case of a possible world where some people
are extremely obese and sedentary. They require chairs that on the Earth would be
wide enough to accommodate two or three average persons. Are they benches? The relevant
difference between a bench and a chair is that chairs are artifacts made for only
one person to sit on, while benches are made wide enough for more than one person
to sit on at a time. Hence, in this possible world what for us look like benches
are in fact chairs, since they are constructed for only one sitter at a time. If
these chairs were ‘beamed’ over to our world, we would say that they remained chairs,
since the makers intended them to be chairs, even if we used them as benches. The
second counterexample is that of a social club with a rule that only one person
at a time can use each bench in its garden. In this case, we would say they continue
to be benches and not chairs, since they are still artifacts designed for more than
one person to sit on, even if they are now limited to single sitters. Elbourne also
asked if a chair must have four legs. The answer is obvious since according to our definition
having four legs isn’t a defining feature: there are chairs with no legs, like an
armchair, chairs with three legs, and we can imagine a chair with a thousand legs.
The property of having four legs is what we have called a symptom or a secondary
criterion of ‘chair-ness,’ only implying that a randomly chosen chair will probably
have four legs.
One can
always imagine new and more problematic cases that do not seem to fit the definition,
but if we look at the definition more closely we discover that the difficulty is
only apparent or that these ‘exceptions’ are borderline cases or that they are extensions
or metaphors. Perhaps the definition indeed deserves some refinement, remembering
that refinement isn’t a mere change to something else.
Finally,
the boundaries of what we call a ‘chair’ can also undergo changes from language
to language and over time; in French an armchair (easy chair) is called a ‘fauteuil’
in contrast to a ‘chaise’ (chair), though a French speaker would agree that it is
a kind of chair. I suspect that thousands of years ago, in most societies one could
not linguistically distinguish a stool from a chair since a seat with a backrest
was a rare piece of furniture until some centuries ago. Finally, the conventional
similarities are here much more impressive than the dissonances, and these similarities
seem to increase with the centrality of our concepts.
8. Criteria versus
symptoms
To make things clearer, it is already worthwhile
to broaden our consideration of Wittgenstein’s distinction between criteria and symptoms. A symptom or a secondary criterion is an entity E that
– assuming it is really given – only makes our cognitive awareness A of E
more or less probable. In contrast, a
definitional or primary criterion is an
entity E (usually appearing as a complex
criterial configuration) that – assuming it is really given – makes our cognitive
awareness A of E beyond reasonable doubt (Wittgenstein 1958: 24; 2001: 28).[15]
For instance,
if I can see four chair legs under a table, this is a symptom of a chair, since
it greatly increases the probability that a chair is behind the table. But if I
perceive that what is visually given to me is ‘a moveable seat with a backrest made for
only one person to sit on,’ this puts my cognitive awareness of a chair beyond doubt.
The definition (C) expresses a definitional
criterion, understood as such because
its assumed satisfaction leaves no possibility to doubt that we can apply the ascription
rule for the concept-word ‘chair.’
I cannot
guarantee with absolute certainty that entity E (criterion or symptom) is ‘really given’ because I accept that the
products of human experience are inevitably fallible. Nonetheless, using this ‘assumed
given-ness’ based on experience and an adequate informational background, we can
establish a subjective degree of probability
when a symptom is satisfied and a practical
certainty when a criterion is satisfied.
In this last case, we might claim there is a probability so close to 1 that we can
ignore the possibility of error in the cognitive awareness A that entity E is given.
(Correspondingly, one could also speak in this sense of a conditional necessity.)
Symptoms
or secondary criteria can help us identify entity E using cognitive awareness A,
even if we cannot regard E as necessary.
However, symptoms are of no use unless definitional criteria are also met. Four
legs and armrests that do not belong to a chair would never make a chair.[16]
Terms like ‘criteria’ and ‘symptoms,’ as much
as ‘conditions’ have so-called process-product
ambiguity. We can see them as (a) dependent
(internal) elements of the rule that identifies what is given, but we can also see
them as (b) something independent
(external) satisfying the rule, which is really given in the world. Our semantic-cognitive
rules are also criterial rules, able with the help of imagination to generate criterial
configurations belonging to them internally as (a). Hence, we could say that definition
(C) is the expression of a semantic-criterial rule with the form: ‘If we accept
that E is really given, we must conclude
A,’ where the conclusion A is our awareness with practical certainty that E is given.
One problem here is to know what this awareness
means. My suggestion will be that we can equate this cognitive awareness with our
acceptance of the existence and applicability of a network of external inferential
relations once a semantic-cognitive rule is satisfied. The conceptual meaning of
‘chair,’ for instance, consists of internal relations expressed by a definitional
rule (C). But our awareness of the application of this conceptual meaning arises
as a maze of external relations resulting from the satisfaction of (C). For example,
if I am aware that a chair exists, I can infer that it has a particular location,
that I can sit on it or ask someone to sit on it, that I could possibly damage it,
borrow it, loan it, etc. I can do this even if I have no real consciousness of the
structure of the rule I applied to identify the chair.
9. Challenges to the
traditional explanation (i):
John McDowell
Supporters of semantic externalism
have challenged the idea that the meanings of expressions consist in our implicit
knowledge of their constitutive rules or conventions. According to their view, the
meanings of expressions are predominantly related to physical and social-behavioral
worlds, depending in this way only on objects of reference and supposedly also on neurobiological processes involving autonomous
causal mechanisms. From this perspective, there is little room for discussing
the conventionality of meaning.
As evidence for the externalist view, we can
adduce our lack of awareness of the structure of semantic rules determining the
linguistic uses of our words. If we lack awareness of senses or meanings, it might
be that they could as meanings be instantiated to a greater or lesser extent in
a non-psychological domain. If this is so, in principle cognitive (also called pre-cognitive)
participation in meaning could be unnecessary. Meaning could result solely from
autonomous causal mechanisms, not recoverable by consciousness. In opposition to
Michael Dummett’s ‘rich’ view of implicit meaning, John McDowell illustrated the
externalist position on the referential mechanism of proper names, observing that:
We can have the ability to say that a seen object is
the owner of a familiar name without having any idea of how we recognize it. The
assumed mechanisms of recognizing can be neural machinery [and not psychological
machinery] – and its operations totally unknown to whoever possesses them. (2001: 178)[17]
Some pages later, McDowell (following
Kripke) asserts that the referential function of proper names would not be explained
by implicit conventionally based identification rules that can be descriptively
recovered, because:
The opinions of speakers on their divergent evidential
susceptibilities regarding names are products of self-observation, as much as this
is accessible, from an external point
of view. They are not intimations coming from the interior, from a normative theory
implicitly known, a receipt for the correct discourse which guides the behaviour
of the competent linguist. (2001: 190)
This view is in direct opposition
to the one I defend in this book, not as much because it can never be justified, but because
it isn’t the usual case. In what follows, I intend to show that usually the implicit
application of internal semantic-cognitive rules based on criteria is indispensable
for the referential function. Moreover, we have already begun to see that to have
a reference, a usually tacit and unconscious cognitive element must be associated
with our expressions and should be instantiated at least in some measure and at
some moment in the language user’s head. For in no case is this clearer than with
McDowell’s main focus: proper names (Cf.
Appendix of Chapter I).
Here is how we could argue against McDowell’s
view. If he were correct, an opinion about the given criterial evidence for the
application of a proper name found through external observation of our referring
behavior should be gradually reinforced by the cumulative consideration of new examples,
that is, inductively. Even repetition
of the same example would be inductively reinforcing! However, this is far from
the case. Consider our characterizing semantic-cognitive rule (C) for applying the
concept-word ‘chair.’ We can see from the start that (C) seems correct. We naturally tend
to agree with (C), even if we have never considered any examples of the word’s application.
And this shows that speakers are indeed only confirming a recipe for the correct
application that comes from inside, as a matter of tacit agreement among speakers…
Admittedly, after we hear this definition, we can test it. Thus, we can imagine
a chair without a backrest but see that it is really a stool, which isn’t properly
a chair. If we try to imagine a chair designed so that more than one person can
sit on it, we will conclude that we should call it a sofa or a garden bench... We
can understand supposed counterexamples only as means to confirm and possibly correct or improve the definition,
thereby discovering its extensional adequacy in a non-inductive way. This
specification of meaning seems to be simply a contemporary formulation of something
Plato identified as reminiscence (anamnesis): the recalling of ideas to mind.
We do not need to go beyond this, imagining all sorts of chairs (rocking chairs,
armchairs, wheelchairs…) in order to reinforce our belief in the basic correctness
of our intuitive definition. But we can do it in order to recognize its more
precise delimitation.
Now consider the same issue from McDowell’s
perspective. Suppose he is right and our knowledge of the meaning of a common name
like ‘chair’ were the result of self-observation from an external viewpoint. We could surely acquire more certainty that chairs
are seats with backrests made for one person to sit on by observing the similarities
among real chairs that we can see, remember or imagine. Inductively, the results
would then be increasingly reinforced by agreement among observers about an increasing
number of examples. As we already noted, even examples of people reaching a shared
agreement by singling out thousands of identical classroom chairs should enable
us to increase our conviction that we have the factually true evidential conditions
for applying the concept-word ‘chair.’ But this makes no sense. Moreover, it is
clear that one does not need much reflection to recognize that the idea is absurd
of definition (C) capturing a neuronal mechanism and not resulting from an implicit
shared agreement. Furthermore, alone the explanation of the implicitly conventional
identification rule for the proper name Aristotle investigated in the Appendix of
the last chapter is sufficient to make this whole discussion idle.
We conclude, therefore, that the ascription
rule made explicit in definition (C) does, in fact, have the function of rescuing
for consciousness the tacit convention governing the referential use of the word
‘chair’ (as with our earlier definition of ‘Aristotle’ in the Appendix of
Chapter I). It seems from the start intuitive and may only require the help of confirmatory,
corrective and improving examples. And what is true for a general term should presumably
also be true for other expressions, as we already saw regarding proper names.
Indeed, if all we have in these cases is a
shared convention, then a psychological element needs to be involved, even if only
in an implicit way, constituting what could be
called a non-reflexive cognitive application of the rule. Definition (C) makes
explicit a convention normally instantiated in our heads as unreflected
tacit application, whenever we make conscious use of the word ‘chair,’ which only
confirms the traditional standard explanation.
10. Challenges to the
traditional explanation (ii):
Gareth Evans
There is another argument against
the claim that we have tacit cognitive access to semantic conventions that govern
our use of expressions. This argument comes from the philosopher Gareth Evans, who
directly influenced McDowell. Evans invites us to contrast a person’s belief that
a substance is poisonous with a mouse’s disposition not to consume it. In the case
of a human being, it is a genuine belief involving propositional knowledge; in the
case of a mouse, it is a simple instinctive disposition to react in a certain way
to a certain smell, not a true belief. Proof of the difference is the fact that:
It is of the essence of a belief state that it be at
the service of many distinct projects, and that its influence on any project is
mediated by other beliefs. (Evans 1985: 337).
If someone believes a certain substance
is poisonous, he can do many different things based on that belief. He can test
his belief by feeding it to a mouse, or if he is depressed, he can try to commit
suicide by swallowing a dose. He can also relate his belief that the substance is
poisonous to a variety of other beliefs. For instance, he might believe he will
become immune to a poison by consuming small amounts every day, gradually increasing
the dose... As our knowledge of semantic rules is not susceptible to such inferences,
thinks Evans, it consists not of actual belief states, but rather of isolated states, not very different from those of the mouse. Therefore, they
are not cognitive (or pre-cognitive) psychological states in a proper sense of the
word. (Evans 1985: 339)
The characterization of belief proposed by
Evans is interesting and in my view correct, but his conclusion does not follow.
Certainly, it agrees with many of our theories of consciousness, according to which
a belief is only conscious if it isn’t insular, while an unconscious belief is insular
– though there are degrees of insularity. But the crucial point is that Evans’ argument
blinds us to the vast gulf between our semantic uses of language and the mouse’s
behavioral disposition to avoid consuming poison.
As a weak but already useful analogy, consider
our knowledge of simple English grammar rules. A child can learn to apply these
rules correctly without any awareness of doing so, and some adults who have never
learned grammar are also able to apply these rules correctly to many different words
in many different contexts. Moreover, even if our knowledge of these grammar rules
is very often unconscious, with sufficiently careful examination we can often bring them to consciousness.
The point becomes still clearer when we consider
our simple example of an implicit semantic-cognitive rule, the criterial rule (C)
for the application of the concept-word ‘chair’ to the identification of chairs.
Certainly, a person can derive many conclusions from this rule. He can predict that
five persons cannot sit side-by-side on a single chair. He knows that one can transform
a chair into a stool simply by cutting off its backrest. He can know the price and
if he could buy a similar chair. He knows that by standing on a chair, he can reach
an overhead ceiling lamp… He knows all this and much more, even without ever having
consciously considered definition (C). And this only means that we can have a belief
state enabling us to identify chairs, putting it at the service of many different
projects mediated by other beliefs without being explicitly aware of the involved
meaning-rule (C).
We can see a continuum, beginning with more
primitive and instinctively determined dispositions and ending with semantic-cognitive
rules of our language and their effects. It includes dispositions like those of
mice, which cannot be cognitive, because they are instinctive (it is utterly implausible
to think that a mouse could be reflexively conscious). There are also more sophisticated
ones, like our unconscious beliefs, thoughts and cognitions, which we can consciously
scan and reflexively access (presumably through metacognitive processes).
If we accept the view that our semantic rules
are usually conventional rules exemplified in the simplest cases by models like
(C), then we must reject the radicalism of positions such as those of Evans and
McDowell. After all, the application of such rules allows us to make many different
inferences and relate them to many other conceptual rules. Rule (C) has greater
proximity to the rules of English grammar than to the innate dispositional regularities
demonstrated by a mouse that instinctively avoids foods with certain odors. Moreover,
it is clear that in such cases, unlike the mouse, for people inferences to other
beliefs are always available. This can be so even
if we admit that our semantic-cognitive rules do not in themselves possess the widest
availability proper to those completely conscious belief states considered
by Evans.[18]
The root of the confusion is that the semantic
rules in question, with and because of their apparent triviality, have not yet been
investigated in a sufficiently systematic way. In an academic milieu dominated by
science, the procedure that leads to their discovery does not seem worthy of careful
investigation. Nevertheless, to proceed more systematically in this seemingly trivial
direction is in fact philosophically invaluable, and this is what I will do in the
remainder of this book.
11. Unreflected semantic
cognitions
I believe contemporary theories
of consciousness support the traditional view according to which we have implicit
knowledge of our meaning-rules. I will begin by appealing to reflexive theories of consciousness. But
first, what are these theories?
In the philosophical tradition, the idea of
reflexive consciousness was already suggested by John Locke with his theory of internal sense (1690, book II, Ch. 1, §19). Reflexive theories of consciousness
were introduced to the contemporary discussion
by D. M. Armstrong (1981: 55-67; 1999: 111 f.). We can summarize Armstrong’s
view as saying there are at least two central meanings of the word ‘consciousness.’
The first is what he calls perceptual consciousness, which consists in the organism being awake, perceiving objects
around it and its own body. This is the simplest sense of consciousness. John
Searle wrote that consciousness consists in those subjective states of sentience or awareness that
begin when one wakes up in the morning after deep, dreamless sleep and continue
throughout the day until one falls asleep at night, or lapses into a coma, or dies
(2002: 7). By this, he meant chiefly perceptual consciousness. This is also a very
wide and consequently not so distinctive
sense of consciousness since less developed species also have it. For instance,
we can say that a hamster sedated with ether loses consciousness because it ceases
to perceive itself and the world around it. We are surely justified to assume that when a
hamster is awake it has some primitive form of cognition of the world around it,
as shown by its behavior. However, this excessive extension of perceptual
consciousness only contributes to its irrelevance. We are aware of the world in
the same way a hamster seems to be conscious of it but in a much more sophisticated, more human sense of the word.
Certainly, a mouse perceives a cat, but it is unlikely to know it is facing its
archenemy. This also holds for inner
feelings.
A snake may be able to feel anger, but we hardly believe a snake is aware of this
anger since it certainly has no reflexive consciousness.
Now, what distinguishes a mouse’s perceptual
awareness and a snake’s anger from our own conscious awareness of things around
us and from our own feelings of anger? The answer is given by a second sense of
the word ‘consciousness’ which Armstrong considers the truly important one. This
is what he termed introspective consciousness and that I prefer (following
Locke) to call reflexive consciousness: This is a form of consciousness that
we can define as the reflexive awareness of
our own mental states.
According to one of Armstrong’s most interesting
hypotheses, reflexive consciousness emerges from the evolutionary need of more
complex systems to gain control of their
own mental processes by means of higher-order mental processing. In other words:
our first-order mental events, like sensations, feelings, desires, thoughts, and
even our perceptual consciousness of the world around us, can become objects of
simultaneous introspections with similar content (D. M. Rosenthal called these metacognitions
higher-order thoughts[19]).
According to this view, only when we achieve
reflexive consciousness of a perceptual state can we say that this state ‘becomes
conscious’ in the strong sense of the word. So, when we say in ordinary speech that
a sensation, a perception, a sentiment or a thought that we have ‘is conscious,’
what we mean is that we have some kind of metacognition
of it. This shows that Armstrong’s perceptual consciousness is actually a kind of
unconscious awareness, while reflexive consciousness – the true form of consciousness
– is probably a faculty possessed only by humans and a few higher primates such
as orangutans.[20]
Now, let us apply this view to our tacit knowledge
of semantic-cognitive rules. It is easy to guess that we usually apply these rules
without having a metacognitive consciousness of them and therefore without making
ourselves able to consciously scrutinize their structure. In other words, we apply
these rules to their objects cognitively[21], and these rules deserved
to be called ‘cognitive’ because they generate awareness of the objects of their
application. But in themselves these rules usually remain unknown, belonging to
what I above called unconscious awareness. Hence, it seems that we need to resort
to some kind of metacognitive scrutiny of our semantic-cognitive rules in order
to gain conscious awareness of their content.
One objection to using this kind of theory
to elucidate tacit knowledge of our rules is that there are a number of interesting
first-order theories of consciousness that do not appeal to the requirement of higher-order
cognition. In my view, we can classify most, if not all, of these apparently competitive
for theories as integrationist theories of consciousness. We can do this
because they share the idea that consciousness of a mental state depends on its
degree of integration with other mental states constituting the system. This is
certainly the case of Daniel Dennett’s theory, according to which consciousness is ‘brain celebrity’: the propagation
of ephemerally fixed contents influencing the whole system (1993, Ch. 5).
This is also the case with Ned Block’s view, according to which consciousness is
the availability of a mental state for use in reasoning and directing action (1995:
227-47). This is likewise the case with Bernard Baars’ theory of consciousness as the transmission of content in
the spotlight of attention to the global workspace of the mind (1997). And it is
also the obvious case of Giulio Tononi’s theory, according to which consciousness
arises from the brain’s incredible capacity to integrate information (2004: 5-42).
These are only some well-known contemporary first-order theories of consciousness
that are historically consonant with Kant’s view, since according to him in
order to be consciously recognized, a mental state must be able to be unified (integrated)
into a single Self. From the perspective of such integrationist theories, an unconscious
mental state would be one that remains to a greater or lesser extent dissociated
from other mental states. And all these views seem to some extent plausible.
The objection, therefore, would be that I am
trying to explain tacit knowledge of language by relying solely on metacognitive
theories of consciousness, ignoring all others. However, I believe there is more
than one way around this objection. My preferred way is the following: we have no
good reason to think integrationist and reflexive views of consciousness are incompatible.
After all, it makes sense to think that a mental state’s property of being the object
of metacognition also seems to be a condition – perhaps even a necessary one – for
the first-order mental state to be more widely available and more easily integrated
with other elements constituting the system. As Robert Van Gulick wrote in the conclusion
of his encyclopedia’s article on consciousness:
There is unlikely to be any theoretical perspective
that suffices for explaining all the features of consciousness that we wish to understand.
Thus, a synthetic and pluralistic approach may provide the best road to future progress.
(2014)
Indeed, we can reinforce our suspicion
by reconsidering a well-known metaphor developed by Baars: A conscious state of
mind is like an actor on stage who becomes visible and therefore influential for
the whole system, because he is illuminated by the spotlight of attention. However,
I think it seems reasonable to think that this could happen only because of the
operation of some sort of searchlight of the will added to some sort of metacognitive
mental state constituting the true spotlight. Hence, one could easily argue that
the first-order mental state is accessible to the rest of the system and hence conscious
due to its privileged selection by some
kind of metacognitive state of attention.
My conclusion is that our awareness of semantic-cognitive
rules and the possibility of scrutinizing them metacognitively would be able to resist
integrationist theories, since they also leave some room for conscious processes
able to be scrutinized by means of reflexive attention. Consequently, assuming some kind of reflexive plus integrationist view, the plausible conclusion remains that we can
have cognitive states that make us conscious of their objects even if such
states are not in themselves proper objects of consciousness. Thus, it seems plausible that only if the
first order cognitive processes are objects of the (reflexive, metacognitive) scrutiny of attention can we subject them to conscious
analysis. And most of our semantic-cognitive rules belong to such cases.
It seems to me that this kind of assumption
could explain why we can have non-conscious or implicit or tacit cognitions when
we consciously follow semantic-cognitive rules without being cognitively aware of
the content of these rules and consequently without being able to analyze them.
They remain implicit because we do not pay attention to these rules when we apply
them and because even when this occurs, they are not there as objects of cognitive
scrutiny. These rules are there, to
use an old metaphor, like spectacles. When
seeing things through them, we are normally unaware of the lenses and their frame.
Assuming this kind of view, we conclude that we can distinguish two forms of cognition:
(i) Non-reflexive cognition: This is the
case with cognitions that are not conscious, because they are not accessed by a
higher-order cognitive process and/or focused on by inner attention, etc. (e.g.,
my perceptual consciousness when I use rule (C) for identifying a chair.)
(ii) Reflexive cognition: This is the case of
cognitions accessed by a higher-order cognitive process and/or focused on by inner
attention, etc., being for this reason able to be the object of conscious access
followed by reflexive scrutiny. Any mental states, sensations, emotions, perceptions,
and thoughts can be called reflexive if they are accompanied by higher-order cognitions
and/or focused on by inner attention. (This is a previous condition needed for the
kind of reflexive scrutiny that can make us aware of the semantic-cognitive rule
(C) for the identification of a chair as requiring a seat with a backrest, designed
for use by only one person at a time.)
Once in possession of this distinction,
we can better understand the implicit or tacit status of the cognitive senses or meaning-rules present in uses we
make of expressions. When we say that the structures of semantic-cognitive rules
determining the references of our expressions are often implicit (as in the case
of the semantic rules defining the words ‘chair’ or ‘Aristotle’), we are not assuming
that they are properly pre-cognitive or definitely non-cognitive, lacking any mentality.
Nor that they are completely isolated or dissociated from any other mental states
(in the latter case, we would lack even the ability to choose when to
apply them). What we mean is just that the cognitive instantiations of these conventional
rules are of a non-reflexive type. That is, although consciously used (we know we
are using them), they are not likely to be the subject of some form of reflexive
cognitive attention. Moreover, as already noted, there is a reason for this, since
the structures of these rules are not the focus of our attention when we use the
corresponding concept-word in an utterance. By uttering our sentences our real concern
is much more practical, consisting primarily in the cognitive effects of applying
these rules. As an obvious example: if I say, ‘Please, bring me a chair,’ I don’t
need to explain this by saying, ‘Please, bring me a non-fixed seat with a backrest,
made to be used by only one person at a time.’ This would be discursively obnoxious and pragmatically counterproductive: it would be
almost impossible to communicate efficiently if we had to spell out (or even think
of) all such details each time we applied semantic-cognitive rules. What interests
us is not the tool, but its application – in this case, to inform my hearer that
I would like him to bring me a chair. In linguistic praxis, the meaning isn’t there
to be scrutinized, but instead to be put to work.
A consequence of this view is that in principle
our inner attention must be able to focus on non-reflexive semantic-cognitive rules
involved in normal uses of words and scrutinize them metacognitively by considering
examples of their application or lack of application.
Taking into consideration the variable functions and complexity of our semantic-cognitive
rules enables the philosopher to decompose them analytically into more or less precise
characterizations. It seems it is by this mechanism, mainly helped by examples,
counterexamples, comparisons, and reasoning, that we become aware of the conceptual
structure of our philosophically relevant expressions.
12. Conclusion
Summarizing this chapter, we have
found two main devices for methodological orientation: (A) the primacy of established knowledge and (B) the method of philosophizing
by examples. They will be used as guides in this book. Particularly relevant
in this context is the idea that we can still see philosophy as an analytical search
for non-reductive surveillable representations of our natural language’s central
meaning-rules. It is almost surprising to verify that more than two-thousand years
after Plato we still have reasons to accept the view that solving some of our most
intriguing philosophical problems would require only deeper and better analyzed
explanations of what some central common words truly mean.
Appendix to Chapter II
Modal Illusions:
Against Supra-Epistemic
Metaphysical Identities
Die Probleme, die durch ein Mißdeuten unserer Sprachformen
entstehen, haben den Charakter der Tiefe. Es sind tiefe Beunruhigungen; sie wurzeln
so tief in uns wie die Formen unserer Sprache, und ihre Bedeutung ist so groß wie
die Wichtigkeit unserer Sprache.
[The problems arising
through a misinterpretation of our forms of language have the character of depth.
They are deep disquietudes; they are rooted as deeply in us as the forms of our
language, and their significance is as great as the importance of our language.]
—Wittgenstein
Philosophy unties the
knots in our thinking, which we have tangled up in an absurd way; but to do that,
it must make movements that are just as complicated as the knots.
—Wittgenstein
Although exceedingly original and
thought-provoking, Saul Kripke’s philosophical application of modal logic to problems
of reference is in my view burdened by a disturbing web of confusion. Since many
would disagree, I will give a short justification of my conclusion by critically discussing his
article ‘Identity and Necessity’ (1971), which preceded the more developed views
defended in his book Naming and Necessity (1980), since it takes his central ideas, as it were, directly from the oven. The paragraphs below summarizing Kripke’s article are in
italics, in order to distinguish them from paragraphs containing my own comments.
After my comments on this article, I provide an Addendum containing a series of
brief criticisms of positions taken by Kripke, Hilary Putnam, Gareth Evans, David
Kaplan, Tyler Burge and John Perry, as part of my project of debunking their metaphysics
of reference and meaning.
Kripke begins by considering the
modal argument for the necessity of identity statements. This argument can be summarized
as follows. Given the principle of indiscernibility of the identical, according
to which (x) (y) ((x = y) → (Fx → Fy)), and given the principle of identity, according
to which (x) □(x = x), we can conclude that if
the property F must necessarily be applied
to x, then y must also have this property. That is, it is necessary that y equals x. In symbolic notation, (x) (y) (x = y) → (□(x = x) → □(x = y)), namely: (x)
(y) (x = y) → □(x = y).
This apparently inconsequential formal result
leads Kripke to the bold conclusion that identities between proper names are necessary.
We know this by universal instantiation □(x = y) → □ (a = b). That is, if a and b are real names and a = b is a true identity, then this identity is
necessarily true. This would concern identities like ‘Hesperus is (the same as)
Phosphorus’ and ‘Cicero is (the same as) Tulli’: they must necessarily be identical.
Further, if F and G are theoretical predicates, defined as essential
designators of properties, if they form a true theoretical identity of the form
(x) (Fx = Gx), then this identity is also necessarily true. That is why identities
like ‘Heat is (the same as) molecular motion’ and ‘A state of mind is (the same
as) a physical state,’ if true, are necessary.
Kripke recognizes that identities between
names and between theoretical identities have generally been considered contingent.
There seem to be good reasons for this. Consider the statement ‘Hesperus is Phosphorus.’
Since Hesperus is Venus seen at dusk (evening star), and Phosphorus is Venus seen
at dawn (morning star), it was an important astronomical discovery that they are
actually the same planet, as Frege pointed out. Therefore, this seems not
to be a necessary, but rather a contingent empirical truth. The same applies
to theoretical identities such as ‘Heat is molecular motion.’ This identity resulted
from scientific discovery and could be false because if caloric theory (the theory that heat consists of a self-repellent
fluid called caloric) were correct,
heat would not be molecular motion. This seems to be a contingent statement since
it clearly could be otherwise.
Kripke’s thesis, however, is that contrary
to appearances, all these identities, despite having been discovered a posteriori,
are necessary,
even if they do not seem to be: they are necessary
a posteriori identities. To reinforce his thesis he introduces a famous distinction
between the rigid designator, here defined as a term
that refers to the same object in any possible world where this object exists or
would exist,[22]
and the non-rigid or accidental
designator, which can refer to different objects in distinct possible worlds
(1971: 146). Proper names and terms of natural species are rigid designators
referring to the same object in different
possible worlds. Most definite descriptions, by contrast, are accidental designators, designating different objects in different
possible worlds. An example of an accidental
designator would be the definite description ‘the inventor of bifocals,’ which in
our world refers to Benjamin Franklin, but in some possible worlds could refer to
any other person or even to no person. In contrast, the proper name ‘Benjamin Franklin’
always refers to the same person in any possible world where Benjamin Franklin exists.
Thus, if we have an identity in which the
identity symbol is flanked by proper names, this identity is necessarily true if true at all, considering that these proper
names, being rigid, must have the same bearers in all possible worlds where their bearers exist.
It is clear that a mathematical
term can be seen as a rigid designator, insofar as its application does not depend
on how the world is. But is it really impossible for proper names to be other than
rigid designators? In an attempt to show that Kripke is wrong and that sometimes
they could be accidental designators, we can imagine the following. Suppose it were
discovered that shortly after G. W. Bush’s childhood an extra-terrestrial being
took possession of his body, assumed his identity and impersonated him from then
on, subsequently being elected president of the United States and performing all
the actions attributed to him. In this case, wouldn’t the proper name ‘G. W. Bush’
be unwittingly used to refer to this extra-terrestrial being instead of to the son
of Barbara and George Bush, who was born on 6.7.1946, becoming in this way an accidental
designator?
The idea that a proper name is a rigid designator
could easily withstand objections like that. According to Kripke, the reference
of a proper name is due to an act of baptism
followed by a causal-historical chain. But this only means that the true G. W. Bush,
as the bearer of the rigid designator ‘G. W. Bush,’ would long since have ceased
to exist. On the other hand, the embodied extra-terrestrial being, whose true name
was, say, Gkw9, would have had its proper first baptism in some remote place and
time. Hence, the name G. W. Bush (in fact here a mere alias of Gkw9) would apply
to this same extra-terrestrial being in any possible world where he existed, serving
here as a homonymous rigid designator. With the same symbolic form
(G. W. Bush), we have in fact two contextually distinguishable proper names that are
two different rigid designators with different bearers and nothing more.
It is important to remark that if we applied the neodescriptivist theory of
proper names summarized in the Appendix of Chapter I, the results would be the same.
Accordingly, the proper name’s bearer is the object that satisfies its identification
rule. What this identification rule requires is that this object sufficiently and
better than any other satisfies the inclusive disjunction of the fundamental description-rules,
which are the localizing and the characterizing rules. Regarding the adult G. W.
Bush (as Gkw9), for instance, the localizing description includes his earlier spatiotemporal
career on another planet before his embodiment on Earth, and after that his service
as President
in Washington and his subsequent life. On the other hand, the characterizing description would include his main accomplishments,
including his election as 43rd president of the USA, leading the country after 9/11,
beginning wars in Iraq and Afghanistan, together with his earlier accomplishments
on a distant planet as Gkw9... In every possible world where the identification
rule is adequately satisfied, G. W. Bush (as Gkw9) would exist. Hence, the identification
rule for the name is also a rigid designator. Something of the kind could also be
easily established for the child really baptized G. W. Bush, born on the Earth on
6.7.1946 who had that tragic fate… also making this name a rigid designator of another
bearer by satisfying its own identification rule.
In addition, Kripke expects us to believe he
has warranted the necessity of the identity between proper names by having discovered
some radical metaphysical difference between proper names, on the one hand, and
definite descriptions, on the other. What his words suggest is that a proper name
could be attached to its reference without
intermediaries by means of a direct (in my view mystical) relation instituted by
the act of baptism. For him, this act does not really depend on any properties of
the object, even if we are helped by their descriptions to identify it. Notwithstanding,
he believes that this baptism allows the post-baptismal production of external causal-historical
chains between speakers and hearers. These chains ultimately enable any speaker
uttering the name as the last link of a chain to refer to the name’s bearer.[23] A definite description, in
contrast, is only an accidental designator. It
would refer to different objects in different possible worlds, presumably
because it would have a completely different reference mechanism, based on what
John Stuart Mill called a ‘connotation,’ defined by him as ‘the description’s implication
of an attribute that the object may have’ (1881, I, Ch. 2).
As I already noted, Kripke’s explanation for
this modal dichotomy, suggesting a difference in the nature of each referring process,
is as illusory as it is dispensable. The only
way to explain the modal dichotomy seems to be by appealing to the already exposed
meta-descriptivist theory of proper names, which gives a really plausible justification
for the contrast between the rigidity of proper
names and the accidental character of their associated definite descriptions (See
Appendix of Chapter I, sec. 7, 8). As we saw, the application of meta-descriptivist
theory shows that descriptions are rigid only insofar as we compare them to the
reference of the proper names they are associated with, which means that definite
descriptions lacking an associated proper name are rigid. After such explanations,
the idea of a rigid designator, at first seemingly so profound, turns out to be
nothing but a technical formulation of an in the end much more trivial idea. It
is the idea that if we assume the existence
of a proper’s name bearer (that is, if we consider any possible world where this bearer exists) this proper
name must be able to refer to it. But
no one would disagree with this!
Furthermore, unlike Kripke’s view, the necessity
of the rigid designator is here the product of de dicto conventions. I say this in agreement with John Searle’s brilliant
demystifying analysis of the de dicto/de re
distinction (1983: 208-220). According to him, so-called de re beliefs are only a sub-class
of de dicto beliefs, so that there can
be no irreducible de re beliefs, as Kripke
supposed. As Searle notes, beliefs are de
re only in the sense that they are intended to refer to real objects, not that
they harpoon real objects. Although there is a class of beliefs whose explanation
depends on contextual characteristics, one should not equivocally conclude that
such characteristics cannot be entirely
represented as part of the intentional (mental) content! Under this assumption,
the true difference between beliefs called de
dicto and ones called de re,
turns out to be a mere difference between reports.
In a de dicto belief like ‘Ralf believes that the man with the brown hat is
a spy,’ we commit ourselves only to the report of Ralf’s belief. In a de re
belief like ‘About the man with the brown hat, Ralf believes he is a spy,’ we also
commit ourselves to the existence of the man with a brown hat. Hence, there is no
reason why both beliefs at bottom should not be de dicto beliefs. Now, if we reject irreducible de re beliefs, we feel ourselves free to
reject the supra-epistemic metaphysical de
re necessities assumed by Kripke.
As it was noted in the Appendix of Chapter
I (sec. 6), my proposed metadescriptivist view of proper names makes them rigid
designators because in any possible world where the proper name has a bearer, at
least one combination of fundamental descriptions that allows its reference in accordance
with its identification rule must be sufficiently and majoritarily satisfied. However,
the reason for this rigidity is not metaphysical. It is simply because the identification
rule is what defines what any bearer of the
proper name can be. Now, considering identity between different proper names
in statements of the form a = b and
assumed the proposed metadescriptivist theory of proper names, we may have two
clearly different cases. The first is the following:
(A)
Two different proper names of the same object
have two different identification rules that identify their bearer under
different guises, under different modes of presentation, simply because they take into consideration
different perspectives in which different descriptions or groups of
descriptions are satisfied. In this case, even being in themselves rigid
designators, identifying the same object in all possible worlds as their own
objects, we cannot without additional information conclude that they in fact
refer to the same object in any possible world. Here it is an empirical matter
to decide. We still do not know whether the identification rules of two names
could be part of a common, wider identification rule and a new rigid designator
having these rules as guises since we still do not have established this last
rule. Consequently, in a first moment the empirical finding of an identity
statement of the kind a = b would be seen as contingent a posteriori. The modal form of this identity would be ◊
(a = b). This was the case before astronomy showed beyond reasonable doubt that
the morning star is the evening star, for instance, when for the first time
someone observed the evening star in the sky all through the night and realized
that it seems to be always the same as the morning star. (Venus cannot be
tracked each night; it disappears for earthly observers during part of the
year, when it passes behind the Sun, what must have given place for doubts).
The second case is the
following:
(B)
Often,
after many and varied empirical experiences we have no reasonable doubt that a
= b. In this situation, we establish a new
convention – a rule according to which the different modes of presentation
a and b, the two different identification
rules, are blended into a single identification rule with two different guises,
each of them emphasizing a different aspect or mode of presentation of the same
object. In this case, however, what we ultimately have is a single rigid designator able
to identify the same object in any possible world, even if under at least two
different guises. The identity resulting from the newly established convention
is then considered necessary a priori.
Its modal form is □ (a = b) or □ (a[b] = b[a]). This is the case today, when we
identify the morning star with the evening star, having as a conditional background
our modern knowledge of astronomy. It is important to notice that at no point
in this process do we need to resort to a Kripkean necessary a posteriori identity, unless we confuse the a
posteriority of case (A) with the necessity of case (B).
Summarizing: The two initially independent identification rules are made constituents of only one
more complex identification rule that includes both anterior rules. One could write
this identity as ‘Morning star [-evening star] = evening star [-morning star],’
differing only by different emphases on each side of the identity sign. Anyway,
the names ‘morning star [-evening star]’ and ‘evening star [-morning star]’ are
used here as rigid designators for the same object, the planet Venus. Moreover,
they are conventionally assumed to be de dicto
rigid designators. Whether they are also metaphysically de re rigid designators, above
and beyond any convention, is something that, it seems, no human being has the power
to know.
Kripke also considers the problem
of apriority. A priori truths are ones we can know without appealing to experience.
Many consider the necessary and the a priori
to be equivalent. However, for him, the
concept of necessity is metaphysical
– about how the world must
be – while the concept of a priori is epistemic – about
how we know the world. Kripke thinks
the two classes are not equivalent. Consider, he writes, Goldbach’s conjecture that
any natural number is the sum of two primes. This may be a necessary truth without
the possibility of our knowing it a priori. In this case, it would have metaphysical necessity.
The claim that necessity is metaphysical
while apriority is epistemological seems to me not fully mistaken, but requires
better specification. I reject this distinction in Kripke’s formulation. His understanding
would be justified only if we could discover real metaphysical de re necessities,
since a de dicto necessity follows from
a more trivial, conventionally established apriority, even if rooted in experience.
Moreover, it seems to me that the awareness of the existence of metaphysical de re necessities in Kripke’s sense is something
that goes far beyond what our cognitive faculties could reach, simply because our
empirical knowledge is inherently fallible
– a point that has been consistently emphasized by philosophers of science from
C. S. Peirce (1991, Ch. 7) to Karl Popper (1989, Ch. 10). From this perspective,
the most we can do is to postulate as natural laws those empirical regularities
that are not only strongly inductively grounded, but also the most
deeply entrenched ones, in the sense that they are strongly inferentially integrated with our most
plausible system of scientific and modest commonsense beliefs.[24] We cannot speak of a natural law’s
necessity going beyond this well-grounded postulation, since to prove this metaphysical
necessity we would need absolute knowledge – something our epistemic fallibility
precludes. Therefore, the so-called necessity of natural laws and what follows from
them is simply a result of a well-grounded decision to treat them as necessary, and since this conventional decision is well
grounded by deep entrenchment, we have a right to expect (pace Armstrong[25]) that they will resist counter-factual situations. These assumed necessities are
necessities in a secondary sense of the word, of course, since they can possibly
be denied without contradiction. However, once we postulate these necessities, we
have a right to treat them as what we have made of them: rules of our own conceptual
system. This explains why we constantly use derived statements of necessity like
‘It is necessary to have fire to light
a candle.’ Such natural necessities should be epistemically identified with practical
certainties, once we see that they can be treated as certainties, insofar as we can grant them a sufficiently
high degree of probability to put
them beyond reasonable doubt.
Finally, we must ask what remains of the empirical
root, the seemingly unknowable real objective
essences responsible for ‘metaphysical necessity.’ One possibility is
that it still has a function in a sense that recalls what Kant called an idea of reason. It seems that we have a directive
idea (whose supposed reference is cognitively impossible to find), constructed only
to offer a horizon able to measure and pragmatically motivate our investigation.
This would be only a directive idea of a metaphysically de re necessity, which could justify our search for
generalizations, as approximations of a mere ideal of an absolute, unquestionably necessary empirical knowledge.
This ideal seems to serve as an in fact unreachable target, able to make
possible the comparison between our approximations, allowing us to establish comparative
degrees of assurance between our judgments. In this context, ideas like that of
a real essence serve as heuristic tools, even if they cannot be true objects
of reference. We proceed as if something
achieved were objectively necessary. And in a similar way, we also proceed as
if we knew ultimate truth and as if we had ultimate knowledge, at least until
we discover that we have made a mistake.
Summarizing the profession of faith of the
apparently old fashioned empiricist that I am: I admit that necessity might be a
metaphysically loaded concept. However, it works for us as a conventional de dicto necessity which we can only believe
to be rooted in some de re necessity,
in a way similar to the way we can only believe that a nominal essence is rooted
in some real essence. Anyway, it is not a de
re necessity that can be epistemologically spelled out in the forms of a priori
knowledge usually expressed.
If this approach to necessity is accepted,
one could go ahead in suggesting a very broad distinction between two main kinds
of necessity, both of them conventional and with essentially epistemic (and only
ideally metaphysical) import:
(A)Unconditioned necessities. These are the formal necessities that we find
in logic and mathematics, along with linguistic conventions. Their statements are
clearly analytic and their negations are, regarding
the system of signs to which they belong, contradictory
or inconsistent.
(B) Conditioned
necessities. These are necessities
arrived at a posteriori, depending on empirical experience to be achieved.
Because of this, they are not necessities in the strict sense of the word intended
by Kripke when he speaks of metaphysical necessities because after being inductively
or hypothetically-deductively reached, they are simply conventionally postulated and assumed as necessities. This is a very
common sense of the term, though a weaker one, insofar as it is circumstantial,
presupposing something like the truth of a theory or system or cluster of empirical
beliefs sustaining it, e.g. the nomological necessity expressed in a statement such
as ‘Necessarily V = ∆D/∆t [assuming traditional kinematics].’
Although diversely defined, these
two general kinds of necessity have a long tradition in philosophy that began with
Aristotle. For him (A) was absolute necessity, the necessity in the
fundamental sense, understood as the cause of itself, as in the case of the principle
of non-contradiction (1984, vol. 2, Met. 1015b10).
On the other hand, (B) would be a hypothetical
necessity, a derived form, a
necessity due to an external cause, like the necessity of water for sustaining
life (1984, vol. 1, Phys. 2, 9,
200-230). The first was a necessity in the
proper sense, since the opposite of it would imply a contradiction. The second,
so-called hypothetical necessity, is such that its opposite does not imply a contradiction,
or implies a contradiction only under a given
condition, like the assumption of
a belief-system or a linguistic praxis. Both A and B are conventionalized
in the innocuous sense that they depend on conventions with varying degrees of arbitrariness.[26] Although I do not intend to
elaborate this point here, my impression is that Kripke tends to oversee the
distinction between A and B, treating weakened conditioned necessities as if
they were unconditioned.
As for Goldbach’s conjecture, the fact that
it may be a necessary truth without our being aware of it does not mean that in
this case its suggestion that any natural number is the sum of two primes is not
an a priori truth, since it can also be an a priori truth without our being aware
of it, insofar as we see an a priori truth as a truth that can be known without experience. It might also be necessary but unknown, insofar as it can be also a priori
but unknown, presently being for us only possibly necessary and only possibly a
priori. If it happens that we never discover its truth a priori, we will also never
discover its necessity. And it is not impossible that someone will find a
proof of this conjecture, finally giving it its cognitive status of a theorem with a priori necessity. Indeed, it is because mathematicians maintain the heuristic
rule that it is possible to reach such an a priori necessity that they still insist
on searching for proofs.
The most striking and revealing
example of a necessary a posteriori statement introduced
by Kripke is that of the wooden lectern in front of him. He starts with the question:
could this lectern have consisted, since the beginning of its existence, of ice
from the Thames? Certainly not: It would be a different object. Thus, the statement
‘This lectern, if it exists, cannot be made of ice,’ is a necessary truth known
a posteriori. Lecterns are usually not made of ice. This lectern seems to be made
of wood, and it is not cold. Hence, it is probably not made of ice. Of course, this
could be an illusion. It could actually be made of ice. But that’s not the point,
writes Kripke. The point is that given the fact that the lectern is not made
of ice, but of wood, one cannot imagine that it could be made of ice. Given
the fact that it is not made of ice, he concludes, it is necessary that it
is not made of ice. More precisely: being P = ‘This lectern is not made of ice,’ and considering that we
know both the a priori truth that ‘If P then □P’ and, from empirical research, that P is
true... Kripke constructs the following argument, applying a modus ponens:
(A)
1 P → □P
2 P
3 □P
It is, therefore, necessary that
the lectern is not made of ice, although this is only known
a posteriori, through empirical research. The statement ‘This lectern is not
made of ice’ is a striking example of a necessary a posteriori!
Unfortunately, there is a well-hidden
mistake in Kripke’s argument. It concerns the epistemological status of P (‘This lectern is not made
of ice’) in the second premise. In this premise, the truth of P is affirmed in complete
disregard for the fact (earlier confusingly introduced by him) that P, like any
empirical statement, can only be known to be true by inevitably fallible epistemic subjects. However, if
this is so, then P can in principle be false. In order to show my point clearly,
I first need to define a statement as practically
certain if it is so
likely to be true that we
can ignore the probability of its being false. This is usually the
case when we can assign a statement a probability
of being true very close to 1.[27] On the other hand, I define
a statement as absolutely certain, if it logically cannot be false, having a probability 1 of being true, which makes
it obviously necessary.[28] Considering this, we can instead
say that statement P of the second premise should more precisely be written as (2’):
‘It is practically certain (that is, it has a probability very near
1 of being true) that P.’ Indeed, (2’) must be true, because we know this. However,
only God – the infallible and omniscient epistemic subject – could know with absolute
certainty the truth of statement
P (that is, God would be able to assign it the probability 1), warranting the factual existence of P. He would in this
way give the state of affairs described by P a truly metaphysically de re
necessity. Unfortunately, we cannot appeal to God in this matter… All we can know
is that P is practically certain in the already stated sense. If we assume
that all available information is true, then it is sufficiently likely that we can accept it as true. This
must be so if we accept the fallibility of our empirical knowledge, its lack of
absoluteness. (Not impossible is a radically skeptical scenario in which Kripke
believes he knows that he is standing before a hard wooden lectern, which
is supported by all available testimony and possible empirical tests, and, nevertheless,
the lectern is really made of ice.[29])
Assuming this, consider Kripke’s premises again.
First, it is fully acceptable that given the
fact that P, P follows by necessity.[30] So, what P → □P says is, ‘If it is really the case that
P, then it is necessary that P,’ and this, I concede, is a logical truth. However,
what the antecedent of P → □P
requires is that P implies □P only
if P is really the case, which demands that our knowledge of P must be absolutely certain, with a probability of
1 and not just an assertion that a fallible knower ‘holds to be true.’ Only when
P has a sheer probability 1 of being true is it an unconditioned necessary truth.
In other words, only an absolutely certain
truth would warrant the necessity of the consequent, which would require an infallible being as its knower. Hence,
the most complete analysis of premise (1) must be (1’): ‘If it is absolutely certain
that P is the case (if P has the probability 1), then it is necessary that P.’ Surely,
premise (1) could not be analyzed as (1’’) ‘If it is practically certain that P
is the case (that is, if P has a probability close to 1), then P is necessary,’
because the mere probability of P, no matter how high, as it is less than 1, would
not warrant the necessity of P. Once we admit the change of premises (1) to (1’)
and (2) to (2’), Kripke’s argument can be made completely explicit as saying:
(B)
1’ If it is absolutely certain (with probability
1) that P, then it is necessary that P.
2’ It is practically certain (with a probability
close to 1) that P.
3’ It is necessary that P.
Obviously, argument (B) is not valid, since the modus ponens
cannot be applied to (1’) and (2’) to give us (3’). The reason is that the antecedent
of (1’) does not mean precisely the same thing as (2’), which makes the argument
equivocal, hence fallacious. I conclude that under more careful scrutiny Kripke’s
argument is clearly flawed and consequently insufficient to convince us that the
utterance ‘This lectern is not made of ice’ is a metaphysically necessary a posteriori truth.
Now we can easily see a reason for Kripke’s
misleading claim that the conclusion of his argument must be necessary a posteriori. He ignores the fine semantic differences made explicit
in version (B) of his argument, and in doing so he jumps to a conclusion that unduly
joins the necessity of his argument’s first premise with the aposteriority of its
second premise, interpreting the flawed conclusion (3) as a necessary a posteriori truth, in which ‘necessity’
is used in the unconditioned sense.
Kripke then goes on to the analysis
of identities between proper names such as ‘Hesperus is Phosphorus’ and ‘Cicero
is Tulli.’ These empirical identities were traditionally seen as contingent. However,
for Kripke they are identities between rigid designators, which makes them necessary
identities, since in the most diverse possible worlds these names will refer to
the same object, which would not be possible if Hesperus weren’t Phosphorus or if
Cicero weren’t Tulli. We could, he says, have identified Hesperus and Phosphorus
with two different celestial bodies, but in this case the sentence ‘Hesperus is
Phosphorus’ would have a different meaning…
In order to demonstrate that the
statement ‘Hesperus is (the same as) Phosphorus’ cannot be necessary a posteriori,
here we can produce an argument analogous to the argument applied by Kripke to the
indexical predicative case of the wooden lectern. Calling Hesperus h and Phosphorus p, we can construct the following Kripkean modus ponens:
(h = p) → □ (h
= p)
h = p
□ (h =
p)
The Kripkean conclusion of this
argument is that ‘Hesperus is Phosphorus’ would be an (unconditioned) necessary
identity that has been reached a posteriori.
Nonetheless, here as well the modus
ponens does not apply because although the first premise is true, the second
premise would only conjoin with the first one to reach the conclusion ‘□ (h = p)’ if it were able to give us an absolute certainty
that ‘h = p.’ However, empirically this cannot be the case. In order to obtain absolute
certainty (probability 1) that ‘h = p’ is the case, which enables us to reach the
conclusion of the conditional, this truth must be discovered, not by inevitably
fallible human epistemic subjects only capable of practical certainty, but again
only by God, the omniscient and infallible epistemic subject.[31] Because of this, ‘h = p’ can
be seen here as merely an empirically reached fallible conclusion, stating that
it is practically certain (sufficiently probable) that ‘h = p,’ which is still far
from absolute certainty or probability 1. The following reformulation demonstrates
the argument’s hidden flaw:
If it is absolutely certain (with
probability 1) that h = p,
then □ (h = p).
It is practically certain (with
a probability close to 1) that h = p.
□ (h = p)
Since we cannot have the absolute
certainty required by the identity of the antecedent of the first premise with the
second premise, the equivocal character of the argument becomes clear. We cannot
use the modus ponens to derive the a posteriori necessity of h = p.
In this interpretation, the statement ‘Hesperus
is Phosphorus’ is contingent a posteriori.
It cannot be metaphysically necessary, because since this identity is only highly
probable, it will always be possible that Hesperus is not Phosphorus. For instance,
although extremely unlikely, it isn’t logically impossible that the gods have until
now maintained an incredibly complex illusion of knowledge in human minds, and that
the planets are nothing more than a swarm of fireflies that assemble every night
to decorate the celestial Vault. In this case, when seen by the naked eye, Hesperus
would have a different location than Phosphorus, but it would appear identical to
Phosphorus when viewed through a telescope – not because it is the same planet or
even a planet at all, but as an effect of witchcraft. (The identity would be falsified,
but together with it as well our whole astronomical system of beliefs. This once more shows that we can defend a conditional natural
necessity regarding an identity statement, since by assuming its grounding system
its opposite is made inconsistent.)
Kripke’s second example is very different,
and one should not confuse it with the first one. It concerns the utterance ‘Cicero
is Tulli.’ Assuming my proposed neodescriptivist theory of proper names, the localizing
description for his identification is (concisely) ‘the person born in Greece on
March 1, 106 BC and deceased in Rome on July 12, 43 BC,’ while the characterizing
description is (concisely) ‘the most famous Roman orator, also a statesman, jurist,
and philosopher.’ His whole name was ‘Marcus Tullius Cicero.’ Since the proper name
is not a fundamental description, but rather an auxiliary one (he could easily be
given another name in a different possible world), Kripke is only relying on the
fact that not all speakers know that Cicero and Tullius are parts of the same proper
name, as a convention in our own world. The statement informs the hearer that the
same bearer of the fundamental descriptions implied by each term flanking the identity
sign is referred to by only part of the same person’s whole name.
The result is that the statement’s aim turns
out to be a trivial one, namely, to communicate to the hearer a convention regarding
the auxiliary description ‘the person whose name was “Marcus Tullius Cicero”.’ Hence,
the right answer is that ‘Cicero is Tullius’ only communicates part of a necessary a priori linguistic convention,
once the convention that the whole name is ‘Marcus Tullius Cicero’ is decided a
priori, just as is the convention that a triangle is a trilateral figure. Moreover,
to say that the statement ‘Cicero is Tullius’ is a posteriori would be to confuse
its belonging to a definition in our actual world – which is a question of being
informed about conventions – with the possible names that the same reference could
have been given in different counter-factual situations. Indeed, it is possible that Cicero could have been given
the name ‘Marcus Titus Cicero’ in a different possible world and even in ours, making
the identity ‘Cicero is Tullius’ false. However, this is as trivial as to say that
in a very different language (or world) people use a different name for ‘triangle,’
for instance, ‘colmio.’[32] Consider the statement found
in a bilingual dictionary, ‘triangle means colmio.’ It is not, say, an a posteriori
inductive result of experience. It is the obvious expression of a necessary a priori identity regarding conventions.
The next of Kripke’s examples concerns
the identity between kinds of things, as in the
already discussed statement ‘Heat is molecular motion.’ Many think
that this identity, being the result of empirical research, expresses an a posteriori
truth. However, for Kripke this is a necessary a posteriori identity because
the heat (in a gas) cannot be anything other than molecular kinetic energy,
since the terms ‘heat’ and ‘molecular motion’ are rigid designators. It may be,
he says, that the Earth could at some time have been inhabited by beings who feel
cold where we feel hot and vice versa, so that for them heat would not be identical
with molecular motion. However, this would not be the case, since we understand
heat as the sensations caused in us by this molecular motion.
The fact that the two nominal terms
flanking the identity sign are rigid designators does not warrant that they are
rigid designators of the same bearer,
picking up the same object in the same possible worlds, since any identity can be
false (e.g., ‘8 = 8’ is true, ‘8 = 9’ is false, though these numbers are all rigid
designators). Thus, the claim of identity alone warrants nothing.
On the other hand, as noted in the Appendix
to Chapter I, since we have ways to translate rigidity in descriptive terms for
proper names, we have reasons to guess that the same can be done with general terms.
That is, we could link the two ascription rules for heat in gas and kinetic molecular
energy to create a unified ascription rule that has two different guises – two different
but interchangeable main designative criteria, producing a necessary a priori identity.
On the other hand, assuming the independence
of the identification rules, we can employ the same strategy used above in order
to discredit Kripke’s view that ‘Heat is molecular motion’ is a case of a necessary a posteriori. Thus, considering
heat in gas and kinetic molecular energy as rigid designators that necessarily designate
one essence, we could construct the following Kripkean argument calling heat in
gas H and kinetic molecular energy M:
(x)
((Hx = Mx) → □ (Hx = Mx))
(x) (Hx = Mx)
(x)
□ (Hx = Mx)
Clearly, the same problem reappears.
The first premise says only that given that
(or if) the identity (x) (Hx
= Mx) is really the case, then it is necessarily
the case that all heat is molecular motion. Or, in the epistemic parlance, if it
is absolutely certain that all heat in gas is kinetic molecular energy, then it is
necessary that all heat in
gas is kinetic molecular energy. However, since the identity affirmed in the second
premise, being empirical, is inevitably fallible, the following paraphrase of the
above argument is inescapable:
(x) If it is absolutely certain (with probability
1) that (Hx = Mx),
then □(Hx = Mx).
(x) It is practically certain (with a probability close
to 1) that (Hx = Mx).
(x) □(Hx = Mx)
Here again, the more explicit formulation
shows an equivocal and consequently fallacious argument for the same reason given
in the above cases. It is thus clear that we cannot in this way conclude that the
statement ‘Heat (in gas) is the same as molecular motion’ is a Kripkean necessary a posteriori truth. Thought of
in this way, it is a contingent a posteriori
truth.
The last of Kripke’s examples should
be the most important one. It is intended as a refutation of identity theories of
the mind-body relation, according to which ‘Pain is (the same as) such and such
a brain state’ would be a contingent a posteriori scientific discovery that has
not been made. But, as Kripke writes, ‘pain’ and ‘such and such a brain state’ are
rigid designators here, for they refer to essential properties. However, if this
is the case, the identity theorist is in trouble, because this identity should be
necessary, which frontally clashes with the fact
that whenever you feel pain you do have pain, while no one is denying that
it is possible to conceive that we feel pain without having the corresponding brain
states. For a theistic philosopher like Kripke this makes identity theory implausible.
I find this argument puzzling.
First, as a matter of fact, one can feel pain without there being an identifiable
physical cause, for instance,
in the case of hypnotized subjects who feel imaginary pains, and in many other cases. However, even if
we ignore this, admitting that we cannot consciously feel legitimate physical pain
without having some qualitative subjective state of pain, the fact that we can conceive of pain without a corresponding
brain state does not prove anything. Similarly, the fact that Descartes could imagine
his mind existing without his body could not prove that a mind can exist without
a body.[33] Why does this force us to think
that a future neuroscience might not be able to show us that by speaking of such
and such a brain state we make a rigid reference to exactly the same thing we experience
as a state of pain, so that this identity would then be established as conditionally necessary, in a way similar to the case of heat as molecular kinetic energy?
It is true that feeling pain isn’t the same
as detecting heat outside us by feeling hot inside. Only the feeling of being hot inside is subjective and immediate
like pain. But in the same way that a Martian might feel cold when we feel hot,
a Martian might feel a tingling sensation when we feel pain. And we can similarly
imagine that feelings of pain, like those of heat, could in some way be interpersonally
identified in the brain using suitable
technical
procedures (Cf. Ch. III, sec. 13). Hence,
the only real difference that remains between the two cases is that kinetic molecular
energy in gas is located externally, outside of a person’s head, while such and
such a brain state is located internally, within a person’s head. But why should
it be relevant to show that pain isn’t
the same as neuronal behavior, and even necessarily the same in a conditioned, non-metaphysical
sense of the word?
Kripke concludes his argument by saying: ‘...heat is picked out by the contingent
property of being felt in a certain way; pain, on the other hand, is picked out
by an essential property’ (1971, note 18). However, even in the case of pain there
is no certainty that the feeling of pain, if it is put into words, picks out the real essential property
of pain, just as there is no guarantee
that a discovered general neuronal pattern of pain picks out the real essential
property of pain, beyond a new kind of nominal essence. The identity can be stated
as real only from the hypothetical perspective of a conditionally established necessity.
To see this, imagine a world where most people’s pain is imaginary and it is extremely easy to mistake imaginary
for real physical pain; worse than this, try to imagine a tribe a people whose pain is always imaginary,
but so well justified that we all mistakenly believe their pain to be real.
As I see it, in
most cases Kripke confuses the a posteriori
element of a contingent a posteriori
discovered identity with its well-grounded conventional establishment as something
necessary a priori – a de dicto necessary truth. This leads him to believe in a supra-epistemic de re metaphysical necessity which is
discovered a posteriori. In doing
so, he assigns to ontologically unknowable identities the same status of epistemologically
assumed identities. He proceeds as if we could assert ontological (metaphysical)
truths without considering our epistemic capabilities and their intrinsic fallibility.
He refuses to accept that we can never completely separate the epistemic from the
ontic; and in so doing, he denies an insight that marks the foundation of
modern philosophy by Descartes, namely, that we lack access to supra-epistemic truths.
Addendum: disposing
of externalism
A great variety of arguments developed
by Kripke and other externalist philosophers merit closer examination. In what follows,
I will limit myself to a few comments, since a more detailed analysis would far
exceed the scope of this book.
1. There are a variety of supposed
examples of necessary a posteriori truths
that were later proposed by Kripke and others. I will consider as example (i) ‘Cats
are animals’ (Kripke 1980: 181-2) because unlike the above examples, it is no identity statement. For Kripke this is a necessary statement since
we cannot conceive of a cat that is not an animal; but it is also a posteriori,
since it was discovered by means of empirical experience. Therefore, it is a necessary a posteriori truth.
Now, for me, this is all wrong. Statement (i)
can be interpreted in two ways, depending on the context.
Here they are:
(a) Contingent
a posteriori: a primitive tribe
that sees a cat for the first time might easily suppose, based on its aspect and
behavior, that it is an animal like others. The tribe arrives at this knowledge
a posteriori, because it is based on experience, and contingently, because it is
liable to revision since, for them, it could be that the cat is, in fact, a legendary forest spirit, that merely chooses to assume the
form of an animal.
(b) Necessary
a priori: Zoologists, accepting the truth of our contemporary taxonomy, according
to which the cat is classified as an organism belonging to the Animalia kingdom, assume that the statement
(i) is
necessary a priori.
So interpreted, the statement is necessary in the conditioned or hypothetical sense
of the word, and it is a priori (analytic) because it abbreviates tautology (ii)
‘Animals called cats are animals.’
One can only arrive at the necessary a posteriori
by confusing the conditioned necessity of interpretation (b) with the a posteriori
character of interpretation (a).
2. Another form of necessary a posteriori later suggested by
Kripke concerns origins. For him, rigidity
makes true parenthood necessary. He considers the case of Queen Elizabeth II (1980:
112 f.). Indeed, she would not be Queen were she not the daughter of Albert, Duke
of York, and his wife, Lady Elizabeth Bowes-Lyon.
This is a suggestive, but biased example, since
in the case of a queen the ovum origin acquires maximal importance, which we would
easily analyze as a case of contamination of the identification rule by descriptions
of origins (Cf. Appendix to Ch. I, sec.
9 (v)). Suggestiveness and biased concrete examples work here as a way to confuse
things and mimic a false sort of relevance. In the case, Elizabeth became Queen
of England because her uncle abdicated the throne, making Elizabeth’s biological
father the new King, thereby establishing her as the biological heir to the throne.
A similar case is the necessity of the origin of the species homo-sapiens as a result of evolution from such and such previous species of hominids (McGinn 1976)
– an empirical discovery that can achieve definitional status. But from another
perspective, precisely identical exemplars of homo-sapiens fabricated in a future
biological laboratory could be
devoid of any proper necessity of origin, due to the
indirectness
and irrelevance of a possible link between such clones and our
ancestors. Anyway,
there is no reason to see the association of natural necessities with proper names
as more than a well-grounded de dicto necessity established by us.
By
contrast, consider the statement (i) ‘Ishmael Lowenstein is the son of Abel and
Berta Lowenstein.’ According to a Kripkean philosopher, this statement should be
necessary a posteriori, because even if
it is known a posteriori, an adult with different parents stemming from a different
ovum and a different sperm cell would not be Ishmael Lowenstein.
However,
suppose that the adult Ishmael makes the shocking discovery that his parents are
not his biological parents. He was mistaken for a different infant in the hospital
where he was born, and a subsequent DNA analysis showed that he was actually the
son of Amanda and Mario Belinzoni, whose supposed son was baptized with the name
Carlos. Of course, this is no reason to think that Ishmael thereby ceases to be
Ishmael or should be renamed Carlos. This name is even printed on his birth certificate
and driver’s license.
If asked, he could insist on answering that his name is Ishmael Lowenstein, certainly
with the agreement of others who know him. This is consistent with our identification
rule, since Ishmael still satisfies the localizing and characterizing conditions
sufficiently better than does any other person.
Nevertheless,
our conclusion might also be less straightforward. Consider again the complete statement (i) ‘Ishmael is the son of Abel
and Berta Lowenstein,’ addressing the question of parenthood.[34] One could use as a criterion
of parenthood those who cared for the child and raised him with loving care until
adulthood. In this case, we can regard the statement ‘Ishmael is the son of Abel
and Berta Lowenstein’ as true, even though he was conceived from Mario’s sperm cell
and Amanda’s ovum. So understood, the statement ‘Ishmael is the son of Abel and
Berta Lowenstein’ could be better seen as contingent
a posteriori. Contingent because it could be false that they cared for and nurtured
him; a posteriori because knowledge of this kind is acquired through experience.
Notwithstanding,
it is not difficult to imagine a situation in which Kripke’s view would apply. Suppose
we were in Nazi Germany, the Lowensteins were Jewish, and the Nazis had arrested
the family. For the Nazis the criterion of parenthood was clearly biological. In
this case, if the Nazis were well informed about the mix-up of babies, Ishmael Lowenstein
would be considered the son of Mario and Amanda Belinzoni, while Carlos would be
considered the true son of Abel and Berta Lowenstein, and as such should be arrested
and sent to a concentration camp… With regard to the proper name, however, the matter
isn’t so simple. Nonetheless, it is conceivable that the Nazis decided to establish
a rule according to which a person’s true and legal name must be the name linked
to his biological origin so that they would replace the name of Ishmael Lowenstein
with Mario Belinzoni, and the unfortunate young man called Mario Belinzoni would become Ishmael Lowenstein.
In this case, the statement (ii) ‘Carlos Belinzoni (Ishmael Lowenstein) is the son
of Mario and Amanda Belinzoni’ isn’t a necessary
a posteriori truth. It could be seen (a) as a very probable contingent a posteriori
discovery, insofar as one emphasizes the fact
that the name Carlos Belinzoni (= Ishmael) should now mean the same thing as the
son of Mario and Amanda as an (a posteriori)
discovered truth and a (contingent) conclusion reached inductively. On the
other hand, it could be seen (b) as emphasizing the stipulated decision to treat
‘Carlos Belinzoni’ (= Ishmael), as an abbreviation of ‘the son of Mario and Amanda
Belinzoni…’ making this an essential part of his identification rule, so that statement (ii) would be
seen as a conditioned necessary a priori.
I guess
that Kripke would answer these objections by noticing that what we discover about
parents doesn’t matter. What matters is that if one were born to parents x and y, then one could not have been born to
any other parents (1980:
113). But so understood, this is a trivial a
priori statement like ‘If a woman is wearing a hat, she must have something
on her head.’ The problem is that any attempt to give a concrete example will lose
its supposed character of metaphysical necessity, since it will be based upon unavoidably
limited empirical experience, being therefore in principle fallible. Indeed, there
is only one way in which a given origin would generate a necessary a posteriori, namely when viewed by an infallible knower.
God would discern that Ishmael is definitely the son of Mario and Amanda Belinzoni,
giving this the probability 1 of necessity independently of experience, and he would know it as a de re metaphysical necessity. He would know
this as the only being able to achieve supra-epistemic knowledge. We, as fallible
knowers, do not possess this gift. By using concrete examples, Kripke gives the
impression of having made a metaphysical discovery about the world when he is really
only saying something that is either trivial or contains an anticipation of what
can be easily derived from the already proposed neodescriptivist view of proper
names.
3. Worse than the necessary
a posteriori is Kripke’s later invention, the contingent a priori (Kripke 1980: 54-56). It uses a case involving the
platinum rod stored in Paris, once designated as the standard metric unit of length.
According to Kripke, analysis of meaning is something different from definition;
the first is necessary, the second is not (although he gives no satisfactory justification
for this). Then he claims that the definition of ‘one meter’ as ‘the length of S at t0’ is not necessary a priori, but contingent
a priori! The reason is that the term ‘one meter’ is a rigid designator, while
‘the length of S at t0,’ being a definite description, is an accidental designator, only helping
to fix the reference. The
accidental designator can change its reference. For example, in different possible worlds the length
of S at t0 could be
greater or less than a meter on Earth, for reasons such as heating or cooling. Thus,
in another possible world (in a contra-factual situation) one meter could be a length different
from ‘the length of S at t0.’ Consequently, the statement ‘the Paris platinum rod is one meter long
(has the length S),’ although established a priori, is contingent.
This
argument could be adequate if we accept the existence of some metaphysical reason for the distinction
between names as rigid designators and descriptions as accidental designators. However, the
real reasons for the distinction are non-metaphysical, as I think I made clear enough in the Appendix of
Chapter I (sec. 8-9): definite descriptions are only accidental when dependent on
proper names, but
not when they make proper names depend on them, as in the present case. Consequently,
we have reason to doubt Kripke’s affirmation that after being established definitions are neither
meaning-giving nor necessary. For it seems clear that the definition of a meter
as ‘the length of S during ∆t’[35] is a stipulative definition made
to establish the proper meaning of one meter. Thus, why cannot ‘one meter’ have
been chosen as a mere abbreviation of ‘the length of S during ∆t,’ whatever this length is? Why cannot ‘the
length of S during ∆t’ be a rigid designator, no less than is ‘average kinetic molecular energy’? Assuming
this, our intuitive reasoning would be to think that whether the length of the standard
meter changes or not, in its function as a standard of measurement, the meter remains
the same, since the standard meter is defined
as being necessarily whatever length S has in the ∆t when it is used as a standard.
This means that in any possible world where the standard meter exists, the length
of this meter will continue to be considered the same, no matter what its cross-world
comparative length may be.
It is
only for practical reasons that, wishing to preserve the comparative function of
measuring length, it is better for us to use the most rigid and most unchangeable possible standard meter.
Suppose, by contrast, that
the standard meter were a kind of very elastic rubber rod, continually changing
its length. It would remain the same standard meter, of course, but it would be
quite impractical as a model for measurement. Using this elastic standard in accordance with the given
definition, we could be forced to accept the absurd conclusion that a woman who two hours ago was 1.67 m tall is
now 2.24 m tall; or that objects with very different sizes could be the same size
if we measured at different times…
The
point is that if you accept that the statement ‘A meter = the length of S during
∆t, whatever length it has when measured’ is the actual definition of a standard
meter – and it really is – this definition given by the definite description ‘the
length of…’ isn’t contingent, but necessary,
since it is a convention that cannot be falsified in any possible world where it
holds. Moreover, this definition is a
priori, for we do not need to have any
experience in order to know its truth. Consequently, the following identity can
be considered the right definition of a meter:
One meter (Df.) = the length of the standard rod S during any moment of ∆t, disregarding
the possible world-circumstance in which its length is permitted to be effectively considered.
The definiendum
‘one meter’ is nothing but an abbreviation of the definiens. Like any stipulative definition, this identity is necessary and a priori. The description that
constitutes the definiens is rigid because
we have established it as applicable in any possible world where the standard rod
S exists, and the name ‘one meter’ is rigid because it abbreviates the
characterization rule established by the definiens.
4. Another attempt to exemplify the contingent a priori could come from Gareth
Evans’ example using the
name ‘Julius,’ which he arbitrarily stipulates as naming ‘the inventor of the zipper’ (1982: 31). According to
some authors, the statement (i) ‘Julius was the inventor of the zipper,’ is contingent a priori. It is a priori because
we do not need experience to know this; but it is also contingent, since it is possible
that ‘Julius’ e.g., sustained brain injuries when very young and grew up too retarded
to invent the zipper (Papineau 2012: 61).
Concerning
statement (i), we again find a dual reading:
(a) On the one hand, it is contingent a posteriori. It is contingent
because in a counter-factual
situation it could be that the zipper was not invented by anyone or that it was
invented by several persons… but it is also a posteriori, because its truth depends on experience
to be discovered.
(b) On the other hand, we could paraphrase
‘Julius invented the zipper’ as (ii) ‘Assuming
that the zipper was invented and that only one person invented the zipper, we have
decided to call this person “Julius”.’ However, this paraphrase of (i) is not contingent
a priori, but necessary a priori. It is
a conditioned necessary harmless stipulation that is a priori because it
is established independently of
experience.
We conclude that neither in case (a) nor in case
(b) do we have a contingent a priori.
5. A curious attempt in the same direction was given
by the following utterance: ‘I am here now,’ proposed by David Kaplan (1989: 509).
This would also be a contingent a priori truth.
It is said to be a priori because each of its terms directly refers respectively
to the agent, the place and the time of a given context of utterance. This excludes the possibility
of its falsity. However, since we can imagine counter-factual circumstances in which I would not be here,
this utterance is only contingently true.
This
example is also deceptive. Even ‘I am here now’ can be a false statement in our
real world. I remember a case related by Dr. Oliver Sacks of a patient who had a
seriously deranged perception of temporal continuity. Because of this, her daily
life was a succession of time-lapses: she could think ‘I am here now,’ imagining that she was still in her bedroom, when in fact she
was already in her kitchen. Thus, in this case, ‘I am here now’ is intuitively felt by us as empirically false! This shows that the statement ‘I am here now’ can be in fact
contingent a posteriori, since it is falsifiable
and since we need to know the real context of the experience to determine its truth.
6. I also disagree with Hilary Putnam’s view, according
to which the meaning of the word ‘water’ must fundamentally be outside our heads.[36]
This
is perhaps the most influential argument for semantic externalism. According to
Putnam’s Twin-Earth fantasy, in 1750 Oscar1 on the Earth and his Doppelgänger Oscar2 on Twin-Earth – two almost
identical planets with the same history – both simultaneously saw water and called what they saw ‘water.’ Since the chemical structure
of water wasn’t yet known in 1750, all that Oscar1 and Oscar2 could have had
in their heads was the idea of a watery fluid (a
substance that at room temperature is liquid, transparent, odorless, tasteless…).
However, in the hypothetical case, they were actually referring to very different compounds, Oscar1 to H2O, while Oscar2
was referring to XYZ. Water on Twin-Earth (in the example) has a very different chemical composition,
summarized by Putnam as XYZ, even though it has the same appearance and properties
of water on our Earth. For Putnam this proves that the meaning of water – a word that for him essentially refers to quantities of molecules with the same
microstructure of H2O – could not have been
in the Oscars’ heads, since in their heads they had the same
state of mind, namely, the idea of a watery
fluid and nothing more. Putnam’s slangy comment is the most famous externalist statement: ‘Meaning
just ain’t in the head.’(1975: 227) As he summarizes in a central passage:
Oscar1 and Oscar2 understood the term ‘water’ differently in
1750, although they had the same psychological state, and although, given the state
of development of Science in their epoch, the scientific community would need to
take circa 50 years to discover that they understood
the term ‘water’ differently. Hence, the extension
of the term ‘water’ (and, in fact, its meaning
in the pre-analytic intuitive use of the term isn’t a function of the speaker’s
psychological state). (1975: 224; my italics.)
That our understanding and meanings are not in our heads is a shocking
conclusion, later radicalized by John McDowell’s inference that even the mind must be external to the head because
it is the locus of our manipulation of meanings (1992: 36).
My neodescriptivist
answer is that Putnam’s result is due to his overlooking the fact that ‘water’
has two descriptive nuclei of meaning:
a popular and a scientific one.[37] First, there is an old popular nucleus of meaning of the word ‘water.’ This nucleus is phenomenal and also
dispositional and can be summarized by the expression ‘watery fluid.’ It is a substance
that at normal temperatures is a transparent, odorless liquid that quenches thirst,
can be used to wash things, is a universal solvent, extinguishes many kinds of fire,
falls from the sky as rain, forms rivers, lakes and oceans, freezes when cooled
below 0 degrees C, evaporates when heated above 100 degrees C, has high surface
tension, etc. This was the well-known meaning until the end of the eighteenth century.
Then a great semantic upheaval occurred. A new dimension of meaning was increasingly
added: the scientific nucleus, which can be summarized as ‘quantities of H2O.’
Water was discovered to
be a chemical substance
that results from combining hydrogen and oxygen, as summarized in the formula 2H2
+ O2 = 2H2O, which can be shown by burning hydrogen mixed
with oxygen and by electrolysis. Moreover, inter-molecular hydrogen bonds are responsible for water’s high surface tension, liquid state at
room temperature, etc. Both nuclei
of meaning are intrinsically inferential.
Nonetheless, they are also obviously objects of descriptions (since in opposition to anti-descriptivist bias, the domain
of what can be described is much wider than a merely perceptual domain, containing
descriptions of dispositions, micro-structures, etc.), which can be confirmed by
consulting any good dictionary.[38] We use the word ‘water’ on an everyday
basis in accordance with what we know from the inferential semantic rules of these
two nuclei. Meaning is not a question of all and nothing.[39] Furthermore, it is easy to see that
depending on contextual
factors, one of these two
clusters of meaning tends to come to the fore.
This
summary already allows the following plausible internalist explanation of the Twin-Earth
fantasy. First, in 1750 the two Oscars had in their heads only the nucleus of meaning
expressed by ‘watery fluid,’ so that the extension and meaning of the word water
were the same for both Oscars. However, when Putnam considers what is happening,
he is overvaluing and unconsciously projecting the scientific nucleus of meaning
of the word ‘water’ into the two Oscars’ utterances, as if it were the only semantically
relevant one. What he does then is simply to treat the two Oscars as mere indexical devices for the projection
of the new scientific nucleus of meaning, whose true locus is in fact our own heads/minds
(i.e., those of Putnam and his readers), based on our knowledge that Oscar1
is pointing to H2O, while Oscar2 is pointing to XYZ. Consequently, the
different scientific meanings of the word ‘water’ are not in the world and outside
of our heads, as Putnam believes. They are in Putnam’s head when he thinks his thought-experiment, and in our heads when we read
his texts. Today we all have some general knowledge about the scientific nucleus
of meaning (summarized as H2O) and may guess that a different scientific
nucleus with similar effects (XYZ) would perhaps not be completely impossible. Finally,
since Putnam and his readers have different
scientific meaning-descriptions in their heads (H2O and XYZ) when unconsciously
projecting them (respectively) onto Oscar1 and Oscar2 by using them as indexical
devices, these different meanings obviously remain, as they should, internal properties
of minds. This also explains why (again helped by our instrumental referential devices
called ‘Oscars’) we give them different extensions.
The neodescriptivist
view suggested above leads us to see that the meaning of ‘water’ receives
variations of emphasis according to with what we could call the context of interest in which a word is used, that is, the context of
its circumstantial utility. In this case, there is a popular and a scientific context
of interest leading to different interpretations as follows:
(a) In a popular context of interest (e.g.,
of fishermen who use water for cooking, drinking, and washing) the sense that is
emphasized in the statement ‘Water is H2O’ is that of a watery fluid.
In this case, ‘Water is H2O’ means above all (i) ‘Watery fluid = fluid
consisting of H2O.’ Taken at face value, this is a contingent a posteriori statement. Contingent
because, at least in principle (though very improbably), it could be proved false;
a posteriori because the conclusion is based on experience. Its modal form, though
possessing a high level
of probability, is still ◊ (a = b).
(b) In a scientific context of interest (e.g., in a chemist’s laboratory) the
scientific nucleus of meaning is emphasized. Here ‘Water is H2O’ means
above all (ii) ‘Water as dihydrogen oxide = H2O.’ As expected, (ii) is
a conditioned necessary a priori statement
with the modal form □ (a = b), more conspicuously, □ (a[b] = b[a]), assuming
the truth of basic chemie. In this context, even if water were not a watery fluid, but rather something
like a black oily fluid, it could still be called ‘water,’ insofar as it had the
right microstructure.
Conclusion: the Kripkean classification of the statement
‘Water is H2O’ as a necessary a
posteriori statement results from a confusion between the a posteriori nature
of statement (a) and the (conditioned) necessity of the similar statement (b). Since
both senses are components of the whole meaning of ‘water’ and may alternatively
come to the fore, it is easy to fall into a confusion resulting from lack of attention
to the pragmatics of natural language, since Putnam and Kripke overvalued the scientific
nucleus. We will deal with these kinds of confusion when we examine Wittgenstein’s
account of transgressing the internal limits of language. In this case, the confusion
is a matter of equivocity resulting from
the ill-fated attempt to import popular into scientific usage (Cf. Ch. III, sec. 11).
7. There are two other examples of Putnam trying
to show that meaning is not only located in the external physical world, but also in society. In the first one, he assumes that
aluminum and molybdenum are only distinguishable by metalworkers and that Twin-Earth
is rich in molybdenum, used to manufacture pots and pans. In addition, he imagines
that the inhabitants of Twin-Earth call molybdenum ‘aluminum’ and aluminum ‘molybdenum.’
In this case, he writes, the word ‘aluminum’ said by Oscar1 will have an extension
different from that of the word ‘aluminum’ said by Oscar2, so that they mean different
things with the word. However, as they are not metalworkers, they have the same psychological states. Hence, the meaning
of these words is external to what happens in their heads, depending on their societies.
Our answer
is the following. Consider how Oscar1 and Oscar2 use the words ‘aluminum’ and ‘molybdenum.’
They are not metalworkers, and what they have in their minds is indeed the same
thing. It is as much so as the extension that they are able to give to their
concepts of aluminum and molybdenum, which in the example includes both. For the
metalworkers of Earth and Twin-Earth, on the other hand, aluminum on the Earth and the molybdenum of
Twin-Earth (called by their inhabitants ‘aluminum’) have very different constituent
properties, which means that metalworkers would have something very different in
their heads. The Oscars may confuse both things, but only because they do not really
know the intrinsic properties of these things and they are using the words in an
incomplete, subsidiary sense. However, since we know the differences between the amounts
of these metals on both planets, we can consider the aluminum and the molybdenum
respectively observed by Oscar1 and Oscar2 and unconsciously take both persons as referential devices for the different meanings
we have in our heads. In this case, we would say that Oscar2 is referring to
what his linguistic community calls aluminum, but which in our linguistic community
is called molybdenum, while Oscar-1 is indeed referring to what we and our linguistic
community call aluminum.
That
people should use the words in accordance with the conventions of their linguistic
community does not make the meaning external. It only makes it dependent on implicit
or explicit agreements of members of their communities. In the two Oscars case,
this agreement concerns only superficial properties. In the metalworkers’ case,
this agreement also concerns intrinsic properties. These agreements are always located
in individual heads, even if differently distributed in heads belonging to a social
network.
In his second example, Putnam considers differences
between elm and beech trees. Most of us do not
know how to distinguish between the two. However,
we are able to guess correctly that these words are not synonymous, having
different extensions, even without knowing the meanings of the two words. Hence,
according to him the difference in meaning is not in our heads, but in society.
In response to Putnam, the important point
to be noted is that most of us really do lack sufficient knowledge of the meanings of the words ‘elm’ and ‘beech.’
However, we already know something very generic about them: we surely know that
they are trees, and we consider it probable (though not certain) that these two
names refer to distinct kinds of trees.[40] With the help of these
convergent descriptions (Cf. Appendix
to Chapter I, sec. 5), we are able to insert these words into a sufficiently vague
discourse. Moreover, we often do this while waiting for the suspected distinguishing
information to be offered by specialists – those privileged speakers with sufficient knowledge of the meanings of these words. They are the only persons
really able to identify examples of these different kinds of trees, so that without
them these words would have no specific usage. The point is that meaning – sufficient
or not – is always in the heads of speakers, even if (as I also agree) this meaning
is located within many heads that make up the communicative network of a socio-linguistic
community.[41]
Concerning these two cases, Putnam appeals
to a division of linguistic labor in order
to account for the variety of meaning dimensions that may be possessed by different
speakers. As he writes:
We may summarize this
discussion by pointing out that there are two sorts of tools in the world: there
are tools like a hammer or a screwdriver, which can be used by one person; and there
are tools like a steamship, which require the cooperative activity of a number of
persons to use. Words have been thought of too much on the model of the first sort
of tool. (1975, p. 229)
This is an important suggestion.
However, it is far to confirm an externalist view of meaning. It is rather neutral.
After all, the idea of a division of labor in language has already been suggested
by internalist philosophers, from John Locke to C. S. Peirce (Smith 2005: 70-73).
The former philosopher championed a theory of meaning as something consisting
of internal psychological ideas. In effect, the division of labor is perfectly compatible
with the fact that, even if socially shared, meaning remains in the heads of speakers,
specialists or not, in different dimensions and degrees. In none of the above cases
does meaning need to be located outside of heads.
Finally, to be fair, Putnam expresses himself
much more cautiously in a later text (1988, Ch. 2), e.g., by suggesting that ‘reference
[as meaning] is fixed by the environment
itself,’ calling it ‘the contribution of the environment’ (1988: 32). However, we
can read the word ‘fixed’ in two ways. In the first, we understand ‘fixed’ in the
sense in which the external physical and social world is what ultimately produces
referential meanings in our minds or heads. This is an obvious truism – something
that a weak internalist (= a very weak externalist) like myself would be proud
to agree. In the second way, which Putnam must intend to suggest, what he means
with the word ‘fixed’ remains a too subtle metaphor to be intelligibly rescued,
except by confessing that he is speaking about reference and not really about meaning. But one does not need to be
a philosopher to know that references are in these cases obviously external, since
belonging to the external world. Putnam’s externalism is an imaginatively brilliant
philosophical effort that ends either in triviality or in confusion.
8. Now, I wish to reinforce my
anti-externalist arguments discussing Tyler Burge’s social externalism of thought,
which in some ways complements Putnam’s argument (Burge 1979). What Burge’s text
supports is the view that the proper contents of thought or belief and propositional attitudes
are external.
I will first summarize Burge’s argument and
then show that it is easy to find a much more plausible weak internalist explanation
of what happens, simply by elaborating
a point already made by John Searle (2004: 284-6). In order to make it as clear
as possible, instead of following Burge’s counter-factual mental experiment, I will follow Searle’s version.
Suppose that a man named Oscar, residing in region A, feels pain in his thigh and
therefore goes to see a certain Dr. Fugly, whom he tells:
(i) I think I have arthritis in
my thigh.
Since arthritis is a painful inflammation
of the joints, the doctor regards this belief as obviously false, since one cannot have arthritis in the thigh. Suppose that Oscar
afterward travels to the very remote region B of his country and visits a certain
Doctor Enoc because of the same health issue. But although in region A arthritis
has its usual conventional meaning, in the remote region B people use the word ‘arthritis’
in a much broader sense, as referring to any kind of inflammation. Suppose that
having forgotten his visit to the first doctor, Oscar once more tells this new doctor that he has arthritis
in his thigh, having in mind exactly the same thing as previously. Now, in region
B, as expected, the new doctor will confirm his suspicion, agreeing with Oscar’s
unquestionably true belief.
Based on a similar example, Burge’s reasoning
goes as follows. Without doubt, when Oscar claims he has arthritis in his thigh
in both the first and second regions, his psychological states are exactly the same,
just as his behaviors are the same. But the thought-contents expressed in the two utterances must be
different, since thought-contents are truth-bearers, and the thought expressed in
the first utterance is false, while the thought expressed in the second is true.
However, the same thought cannot be both true and false! Moreover, in the second
region the word ‘arthritis’ receives a new meaning, called by Burge ‘tharthritis.’ His conclusion is that the
contents of the thoughts cannot be merely psychological. These contents must also
belong to the outside world, to the social communities where the speakers live.
(Burge 1976: 106)
Against this conclusion, it is not hard to
find a commonsense internalist-descriptivist
explanation for what happens. For a healthy weak internalism (that is, a minimalist
externalism that admits that our mental subjectivity unavoidably depends on external
inputs), in region B the concept-word ‘arthritis’ is the expression of an ascription
rule constitutive of a meaning that is more general, designating any kind of inflammation.
According to this rule, ‘an inflammation that occurs in the thigh’ serves as a criterial
condition and belongs to the sense affixed to the word ‘arthritis’ in the linguistic
community of region B. Thus, although the thought expressed in the sentence ‘I think
I have arthritis in my thigh’ spoken by Oscar is precisely the same in the two linguistic
communities, there is a fundamental difference that John Searle rightly identified
as follows:
Our use of language is presumed to conform to the other members of our community, otherwise we
could not intend to communicate with them by using a common language. (2004, 184-5;
my italics)
That is, when Oscar says to Doctor
Fugly, ‘I believe I have arthritis in my thigh,’ he must assume that his ascription
rule for the predicate ‘arthritis’ conventionally belongs to the language that other
competent speakers of the language conventionally apply. The whole of what Oscar
has in his mind (first actually and then dispositionally) in his utterance in the
linguistic community of region A is:
(a) I have arthritis in my thigh… (and I am assuming
that pain and inflammation in my thigh are accepted as a usual symptom of arthritis
by the linguistic community of region A, to which my present interlocutor, Dr. Fugly,
belongs).
This is false because the second sentence of the conjunction is false. Let’s
now see what is (first actually and then dispositionally) meant when Oscar tells
the second doctor he has arthritis in his thigh:
(b) I have arthritis in my thigh… (and I am assuming
that pain and inflammation in my thigh are accepted as a usual symptom of arthritis
by the linguistic community of region B, to which my present interlocutor, Dr. Enoc,
belongs).
Now statement (b) is true. Although the statement ‘I have arthritis
in my thigh’ says the same thing, it has a
hidden indexical content that differs from (a) to (b). However, this hidden
indexical meaning still belongs to Oscar’s
mind. Thus, it is true that if we confine ourselves to the content expressed
by Oscar’s thoughts when making the same utterance in both places, we see the statements
as identical. However, there is an overall difference in what the hearers
have in their minds (that is, in their heads) when hearing each utterance. It is
different because Oscar wrongly assumed he was following conventions accepted by
Doctor Fugly in the first linguistic community, while he later correctly assumes
he is following conventions accepted by Doctor Enoc in the second linguistic community.
When he speaks with the doctor from community
A, Oscar infringes on the principle that in order to achieve truth, verifiability
rules constituting the content of thoughts should be in consonance with the conventions
assumed by the linguistic community where the thoughts are expressed. But the correlative
assumption isn’t infringed on in community B, when Oscar speaks with Doctor Enoc.
The conventional truthmakers given to members of the two social communities of speakers
are different, although the semantic assumptions related to them by Oscar remain
the same.
To be fair to Burge, we need to remember that
he called attention to something important: the truth or falsehood of utterances
depends on their conformity with linguistic conventions adopted by the speaker’s
community. This is already a relevant point, although it does not touch the claim
that anything involved in thought-contents or beliefs (understood as senses or
meanings of sentences) is outside the internal psychological realm, as it were in
some mysterious way dispersed throughout the external socio-physical environment,
as a strong externalist would like us to believe.
A final and more important point is the following:
The given explanation allows us to make a healthy internalist paraphrase of the
well-known distinction between narrow
content and wide content. For the externalist
point of view, narrow content is what is in the speaker’s mind, while wide content
is in some way external. A healthy internalist analysis of Burge’s example allows
us to propose that the narrow content
of a thought restricts itself to the semantic-cognitive
verifiability rule that constitutes it. This rule is expressed by the statement
‘I think I have arthritis in my thigh.’ On the other hand, the wide content of a thought is what is indexically assumed in the speaker’s
mind as the adequate social convention that
he expects to be satisfied by the narrow content.
8. Finally, one word about John
Perry’s argument for the essential indexical (1979). I will be brief since I
am repeating an argument I presented in more detail in another text (Costa 2014,
Ch. 4). Contrary to Frege, Perry’s view is that the senses of indexicals are inevitably
linked with the external circumstances of utterances, which can be proved by the
fact that one cannot translate them into eternal sentences without any loss of meaning.
The upshot is that, regarding indexicals, externalism of meaning is unavoidable.
In Perry’s main example, he is pushing his
shopping cart through a supermarket and notices that there is a trail of sugar on the floor. He begins
to search for the source of the mess only to realize that he himself is the one who is spilling sugar on the
floor. This leads him to say: (i) ‘I am making a mess,’ and as a result, he changes his behavior. Now, suppose
we translate his statement into a non-indexical statement like (ii) ‘Perry is making
a mess.’ This (almost) non-indexical statement cannot preserve exactly the same
meaning. He could, for instance, be suffering from Alzheimer’s disease, so that he has forgotten his
name is Perry. In this case, he would know the truth of (i), but not the truth of
(ii). The conclusion is externalist: no non-indexical statement is able to rescue
the whole content of an indexical utterance. Some semantic content must unavoidably
belong to the world.
However, I think there is, in fact, a way to
preserve the whole content of the indexical, detaching it entirely from its indexical
context. It is a technique I call transplanting:
if you need to change the location of a plant, you almost never take the plant alone,
but the plant together with the necessary amount of earth in which it is rooted…
By analogy, here is how Perry’s example appears after transplanting:
(iii) At 10:23 a.m.
on March 26, 1968, in the confectionery supplies section of Fleuty Supermarket in the city of Berkeley, CA, after
noticing a sugar trail leading away from his shopping cart, Perry says that he is making a mess (or: ‘I
am making a mess’).
What counts now is the truth of
this eternal sentence[42] (iii) in which the
indexical subordinate sentence is presented after a that-clause. Although containing
indexical elements (‘he’ plus present tense), statement (iii) does not refer to
the indexical context, since the indexical subordinate clause refers indirectly. It refers to what Frege called the thought (the belief-content)
expressed by Perry in the subordinate clause that follows (a that-clause) or in
the sentence with quotation marks (1892: 28). Thus, protected by its surrounding
description (the ‘volume of earth’ offered by the eternal sentence), the Fregean sense of ‘I am making a mess’ is here integrally
transplanted without loss into the non-indexical context of a thought-content with
a much wider reference.[43] What this argument
shows is that the so-called essential indexical is not essential at all, since we
can explicitly internalize its apparently external components.
[1] This is a statement like that by
Heraclitus of Ephesus, who noted that ‘The sun is the width of a human foot.’
As an interpreter wrote, we need only lie on the ground and hold up a foot against
the sun to see that this is true.
[2] I am unable to find real exceptions.
Under normal circumstances, fire has always burned. Some say that the idea that
trees draw energy from the earth was once a commonsense truth until photosynthesis
was discovered… But this idea wasn’t a very basic or modest commonsense truth since
it could easily be refuted by the well-known fact that trees do not grow in complete
darkness. The idea that a new sun crosses
the sky each new day is surely absurd – but is it a commonsense idea? In fact, it
was suggested by a philosopher, Heracleitus, going beyond the humble intentions
of modest common sense. Modest, humble common sense is not interested in answering
such questions, which have no relationship to ordinary life concerns.
[3] Roberto DaMatta, in an interview.
(A more forceful example is the obstinate rejection of any kind of theism of the
Pirahã tribe in the Amazon rainforest studied by Daniel L. Everett).
[4] It was certainly much easier to
believe in the existence of a personal God and an eternal soul independent of the
body a thousand years ago, before the steady accumulation of divergent knowledge
discovered by the natural and human sciences.
[5] The expression ‘descriptive metaphysics’
was introduced by P. F. Strawson in contrast to ‘revisionary metaphysics.’ It aims
to describe the most general features of our actual conceptual schema, while revisionary
metaphysics attempts to provide a new schema to understand the world. Strawson,
Aristotle, and Kant developed descriptive metaphysics, while Leibniz and Berkeley
developed revisionary metaphysics (Strawson 1991: 9-10).
[6] As these interpreters wrote: ‘Wittgenstein’s
objection to “theorizing” in philosophy is an objection to assimilating philosophy,
whether in method or product, to a theoretical (super-physical) science. But if
thoroughgoing refutation of idealism, solipsism or behaviorism involves a theoretical
endeavor, Wittgenstein engages in it.’ (Baker & Hacker 1980: 489) Anthony Kenny
(1986) preferred to think that Wittgenstein actually held two competing views on
the nature of philosophy – therapeutic and theoretical. But the here proposed unified
interpretation seems more charitable.
[7] As he writes, ‘We have now a theory,
a “dynamic” theory (Freud speaks of a “dynamic” theory of dreams) of the sentence,
of the language, but it appears to us not as a theory.’ (Zettel 1983b: 444).
[8] Paul Grice’s sophisticated and ingenious work contains
an influential (albeit qualified) criticism of ordinary language philosophy as practiced
by Ryle, Austin and Strawson (1989, Chs. 1, 2, 10, 15, 17). According to him, these
philosophers often confused ordinary uses of statements resulting from conversational
implicatures with their literal meaning. When implicature failed, they mistakenly
concluded that these statements had no meaning. This would be the case of statements
like ‘This flag looks like red’ (supposedly understood by Austin as showing that
sense-data do not exist because this statement is devoid of sense), ‘The present
King of France is wise’ (understood by Strawson as a statement without truth-value)
and ‘If green is yellow then 2 + 2 = 5’ (understood by him as showing the odd character
of material implication). I agree with Grice’s rejection of all these ordinary language
philosophers’ conclusions, even if I remain suspicious regarding his own explanations.
Material implication, for instance, still belongs to our practice of truth-functional
reasoning, which makes explicit a basic general layer subsumed under our more informative
factual language. In this sense, it also provides wide intermediate connections.
That is, under sufficiently critical scrutiny, natural language intuitions still
provide a valuable guide – a point with which Grice would certainly agree.
[9] Philosophers like Berkeley, Leibniz and Hegel can be seen
as doing revisionary conceptual analysis,
refuting and replacing ambitious interpretations
of common sense by new ones.
[10] Rudolf Carnap’s formal
mode of speech (1937, part 5, sec. A, § 79) instead of material mode of speech, and particularly W. V-O. Quine’s broader semantic ascent (1960, Ch. 7, § 56) point
to this same fact, namely, that by means of conceptual analysis we emphasize
linguistic forms only in order to have a clearer sight of them.
[11] A good glimpse into the nature of identification rules
was already provided in the Appendix of Chapter I.
[12] If you wish to avoid the word ‘seat,’
you can also define a chair as ‘a moveable piece of furniture with a raised surface
and a backrest, made for only one person at a time to sit on.’
[13] As will be frequently recalled,
I do not deny that referential meanings include things that cannot be really captured
by descriptive conventions, unlike case (C) – things like perceptual images, memory-images,
feelings, smells. However, they belong much more to the semantic level called by
Frege illuminations (Beleuchtungen), based on natural regularities more than on conventions.
[14] You can continue using the word ‘chair’ when pointing to
a wheelchair, but even this semantic flexibility is already definitionally sustained,
insofar as you are allowed to identify a chair with wheels as a chair. The sub-conceptual
semantic modulation here is nothing but an addition to the definition of a
chair. There are well-known cases like (i) ‘cut’ (Df.): using a sharp-edged or another device to separate something into
parts, (ii) ‘love’ (Df.): an intense feeling
of affection, (iii) ‘game’ (Df.): an activity
with rules intended to be used as a means of entertainment (pace Wittgenstein), and (iv) ‘abuse’ (Df.): damaging use of something. These
definitions, even if incomplete, express meaning-giving conventional cores that
can receive conventional sub-conceptual supplements by the addition of words in
expressions such as for (i) ‘cut the cake,’ ‘cut the grass,’ for (ii) ‘love a woman,’
‘love a child’ (‘loving chocolate’ is already an extended, metaphorical use), for
(iii) ‘play chess,’ ‘play tennis,’ ‘play solitaire,’ and for (iv) ‘abuse a drug,’
‘abuse a child.’ Such sub-conceptual modulations can also be made without a
subsidiary word, by the context alone. Contemporary philosophy has in my view an
insufficiently justified bias against
definitions. (For a somewhat different view, see Recanati 2010: 29 f.)
[15] The correct interpretation of this
distinction is a controversial issue that does not concern us here; I give what
seems to me the most plausible and useful version.
[16] At first view, it seems that these
logico-conceptual remarks appeal to old-fashioned
semantic definitions leading us to the
rejection of findings of modern empirical psychology (Cf. E. Margolis & S. Laurence, 1999, Ch. 1). But this is only appearance.
Consider Eleanor Rosch’s important results. She
has shown that we are able to categorize under a concept-word much more easily and
quickly by appealing to prototypical cases (Cf. Rosch, 1999: 189-206). For
example, we can more easily recognize a sparrow as a bird than an ostrich or a penguin.
In the same way, an ordinary chair with four legs can be recognized as a chair more
easily and quickly than can a wheelchair or a throne. However, this does not conflict
with our definition, since for us the psychological mechanism of recognition responsible
for the performance is not in question, but rather the leading structure subjacent
to it. We can often appeal to symptoms as the most usual ways to identify things.
For instance, we identify human beings first by their faces and penguins first by
their appearance, even if human faces and a penguin’s appearance are only symptoms
of what will be then confirmed by expected behavior, memories, genetic makeup, etc.
Hence, the ultimate criterion remains dependent on a definition. (In one wildlife
film fake penguins outfitted with cameras deceived real penguins. The trouble with
these moronic birds is that they are
overly dependent on innate, instinctive principles of categorization.)
[17] The expression in brackets appears
in the author’s footnote on this passage. In Dummett’s more orthodox position, McDowell
sees a relapse into the psychologism justifiably rejected by Frege.
[18] Freud distinguished (i) unconscious
representation able to associate itself with others in processes of unconscious
thought from (ii) unconscious representation that remains truly isolated, not associated with other representations, which for him would
only occur in psychotic states and whose repression mechanism he called exclusion
(Verwerfung). Evans treats the relative insularity of our non-reflexive awareness
of semantic rules in a way that suggests Freud’s concept of exclusion.
[19] Cf. Rosenthal 2005. In this summary, I will ignore the dispute between
theories of higher-order perception (Armstrong, Lycan) and higher-order thought
(Rosenthal), and still others. In my view, David Rosenthal is right in noting that
Armstrong’s perceptual ‘introspectionist’ model suggests the treatment of cognitions
of a higher-order as if they contained qualia and that it is implausible
that higher-order processes have phenomenal qualities. Armstrong, on his side, seems
to be right in assigning a causal controlling role to higher-order
introspection, since for him consciousness arises from the evolutionary necessity to maintain unified control over
more complex
mental systems. Aside from that, although Armstrong doesn’t use the word ‘thought,’
he would certainly agree that there is some kind of higher-order cognitive element in the introspection of
first-order mental states, an element that interests us here. I prefer the term
metacognition for these higher-order
cognitions since I believe that not only Rosenthal but also Armstrong would agree
that introspection is a cognitive phenomenon.
[20] I will pass over the traditional
idea that of themselves first-order mental states automatically generate metacognitions.
This view would make it impossible to have perceptual consciousness without introspective
consciousness. However, this view not only seems to lack a convincing intuitive
basis; it also makes the existence of unconscious thoughts incomprehensible.
[21] Some use the term ‘pre-cognitive’
for what is implicitly known. I use the word ‘cognitive’ in a broader sense, including
the cognition of what is implicitly, unconsciously known.
[22] Later he generalized, writing that a rigid designator ‘in
every possible world designates the same object,’ which includes worlds where the
object does not exist (1070: 48). However, this last view directly contradicts the
meaning of the verb ‘to refer,’ which can only be rightly applied when the referred
to object exists (Cf. Searle 1969: 77;
Plantinga 1974: 80).
[23] Rejecting the view of a particular
as a bundle of abstract properties, Kripke concludes: ‘What I do deny is that a
particular is nothing but a “bundle of qualities,” whatever that may mean’ (1980:
52). He was certainly unaware of the then only recently introduced trope theory.
(See Appendix of Chapter III)
[24] This high level of entrenchment
seems to me the relevant reason we distinguish between regularities that have
the ‘necessity’ of natural laws and those that are merely coincidental. This entrenchment
creates the impression that our knowledge of natural law is of something that exists
by logical necessity. (For similar approaches, see Tugendhat & Wolf 1983: 253;
See also Mackie 1974.)
[25] D. M. Armstrong defended the view
that scientific laws are necessary because they are relations between universals,
which explains their resistance to counter-factual examples (2010,
Ch. 5). However, the ontological price of this view seems simply too high.
[26] I think that Wittgenstein
would classify as (B) conditioned necessities those implicit conventions that
he called ‘grammatical rules,’ grounding useful linguistic practices (1984a).
Here is his suggestion, in which I read the word ‘rule’ as a conventional (a
priori) conditional necessary proposition: ‘Every empirical proposition can serve as a rule if it is fixed as the immovable
part of a mechanism, in such a way that the entire representation revolves
around it, making it part of a system of coordinates independent of the facts.’
(1984e, part VII: 437)
[27] The concept is relevant for
those who accept that (empirical) knowledge is justified true belief, because then they will need practical
certainty regarding the conditions of truth and, consequently, knowledge
itself. (Cf. Costa 2014, Ch. 5).
[28] I assume that ‘P is necessary’
means the same as ‘P has probability 1.’ Seen as a probability, the idea of a necessity
without any epistemic import appears to be nothing but an empty fetishism of necessity.
[29] For a discussion of skeptical hypotheses,
see Ch. VI, sec. 30.
[30] This works well and trivially with formal necessities. If P were 5 > 3, one
could argue (1) ‘If it is the case that 5 > 3, then it is necessary that 5 >
3. (2) It is the case that 5 > 3. (3) Therefore, it is necessary that 5 >
3.
[31] God would be the only being able
to know created things in their metaphysical necessities de re, perhaps because he knows them by sustaining them in their existence.
[32] ‘Colmio’ means triangle in Finnish.
[33] In the last case, this is because
‘imagine,’ like ‘doubt’ and ‘conceive,’ are verbs of propositional attitudes, which
do not allow extensional inferences.
[34] Today there are at least five competing
theories of parenthood (genetic, labor-based, intentional, causal and pluralistic
ones), and there is no consensus on the right cluster of criteria (Cf. Brake & Millum 2016, sec. 4).
[35] The symbol ‘∆t’ is more
correct. The rod served as a standard not only at t0, but rather during the entire period
in which it was conventionally designated to have its function.
[36] I say ‘fundamentally,’
because Putnam admits that surface descriptions (stereotypes) and classifications
(semantic markers) are internal secondary mental features of meaning (1975: 269).
[37] For a more detailed
argument, including a more careful neodescriptivist analysis of the meanings of
‘water,’ see Costa 2014, Ch. 3.
[38] For instance, the main
definition in a Merriam Webster dictionary
contains elements of both popular and
scientific nuclei of meaning. It is the following: water = the liquid that descends
from the clouds as rain, forms streams, lakes, and seas, and is a major constituent
of all living matter and that when pure is an odorless, tasteless, very slightly
compressible liquid oxide of hydrogen, H2O, which appears bluish in thick layers, freezes at 0°C and boils at 100°C, has a maximum density at 4°C and a high specific heat, is weakly
ionized to hydrogen and hydroxyl ions, and is a poor conductor of electricity and
a good solvent. (On the descriptive relevance of the dispositional and scientific
properties of water and their presentation in dictionaries, see Avrum Stroll, 1996:
71).
[39] We need to know only
the most common descriptions, and this is enough for our adequate use of the word
in more or less vague contexts. We do not need to know all the descriptions of water;
even chemists do not know all of them. Did you know, for instance, that when water
is cooled to near absolute zero (-273.15° C.), it changes again from a solid to a liquid state?
[40] In a later text (1988:
29), Putnam notes that if I know that a beech tree isn’t an elm, I also know that an elm isn’t a beech tree, which means that
my knowledge is symmetrical, so that the
representations are the same; furthermore, the words ‘beech’ and ‘elm’ are only
phonetic shapes without meaning (1988: 27). But the semantic element here is just
that we have reasons to believe that with these two names privileged speakers mean
different kinds of trees, being able
to detail the differences. Thus, that the description ‘A beech tree is a tree that
is different from an elm tree’ is sufficient to allow us to insert these words in
discourse as probably referring to different kinds of trees that after correction
by others will be asymmetrically classified.
[41] We can also find the
right information in books, the internet, etc., but in order to be there, it must first in some way or measure be located in the
human minds inside our heads...
[42] This might not be a
perfect eternal sentence, but this does not change our conclusions since it is questionable
if a statement without any kind of indirect indexical dimension is possible. If
I say, ‘The Earth is round,’ I am already localizing the subject in our solar system.
In this sense, all our empirical statements are indexicals.
[43] Phenomenal elements
are obviously lost, but they do not belong to the conventionally grounded meaning.
For a reconstruction of Frege’s indirect reference in subordinate clauses, see the
Appendix of Chapter IV, sec. 5 (iv).
Nenhum comentário:
Postar um comentário