Quem sou eu

Minha foto
If you wish to be acquainted with my groundbreaking work in philosophy, take a look at this blogg. It is the biggest, the broadest, the deepest. It is so deep that I guess that the narrowed focus of your mind eyes will prevent you to see its full deepness.

quinta-feira, 4 de julho de 2019

PRESENT RESEARCH



PROPOSAL OF A BOOK


TITLE OF THE BOOK:
Basic Epistemology

AIMS OF THE BOOK
My plan is to write a short book with 200 pages or less. The book is planned as a supplementary textbook, appealing to scholars as well as to students. Its aim is to expose the most fundamental problems of epistemology from perspectives chosen and sometimes to a certain extent developed by the author. They are not to be found in the usual introductory books of epistemology. Some of these views are in my judgment clearly relevant, though not sufficiently discussed, like, for instance, the perspectival definition of knowledge defended by Robert Fogelin, by Michael Williams, and even by myself. Others, like a new answer to the Humean skepticism (once suggested by Keith Campbell) and a new answer to skepticism about the external world (inspired in Carnap’s distinction between internal and external questions of existence) are views that I have developed and published some years ago. In the whole, the book will be what one could call (following D. M. Armstrong) ‘an opinionated introduction.’
In accordance with the usual definition of epistemology as the investigation of the origins, nature, and limits of knowledge, the book will be divided into five loosely interconnected chapters after the preface. They are 1. Origins of Knowledge, 2. Defining Knowledge, 3. Theories of Justification, 4. Limits of Knowledge (skepticism).


CHAPTERS’ SUMMARY

1. SOURCES OF KNOWLEDGE: the general aim of this first chapter is to evaluate the divide between empiricism and rationalism. It begins by considering the sources of knowledge: secondary ones, like memory and testimony, and primary ones, like perceptual (including introspective) experience and reason (or intuition). Perceptual experience and reason justify the divide: the empiricist gives full importance to the experience, while the rationalist gives full importance to the a priori knowledge originated from reason or intuition. The main thesis of the chapter comes from the evolutionary epistemology. Our innate dispositions and capacities to acquire knowledge a priori are the result of natural selection.
   Some cases are considered. One of them is our capacity to understand Euclidian geometry. It seems more intuitive to us, and it is all we need in order to deal with the space around us, even if from the standpoint of the physicists it is not the most precise way of considering space. Another case is that of logical principles, like the principle of non-contradiction. (For instance, no living animal could survive without the capacity of distinguishing its prey from its hunter.) Still other cases would be those of arithmetic knowledge, supposed synthetic a priori knowledge, and conventional definitional knowledge. They are all, if not fully trivial, conditioned by natural evolution, which means that they have at the end of the day empirical sources. From this, some philosophers like Michael Devitt concluded that rationalism is over, as empiricism has tracked the real source of our knowledge.
   I disagree with this. Empiricism, with its theory of mind as a blank slate, cannot show how our knowledge can be constructed and why it is similarly constructed in different minds. Moreover, rationalist philosophers were insightful in grasping the importance of our innate dispositions to react and to the creation of possible views about the world much earlier than the theory of evolution could explain this scientifically. This is the kern-insight of rationalism and not the discovery that innate knowledge is usually fallible or that it was not posed in our minds by God. An actualized form of rationalism (that we can find in Karl Popper, Noam Chomsky, Jean Piaget, and others) is not only compatible but complementary with empiricism. Evolutionary theory has not demolished the distinction but contributed to the dissolution of its traditional polarization.

2. DEFINING KNOWLEDGE: The second chapter concerns analysis of knowledge. After an introductory examination of the different forms of knowledge, I focus on propositional knowledge. The traditional definition of knowledge is exposed together with Gettier’s problem. Some main attempts to solve Gettier problem (like Goldman’s and Nozick attempts) are critically exposed.
   My  central task in this chapter is to bring again to the fore a theory developed by Robert Fogelin,[1] by Michael Williams,[2] and by myself.[3] according to this view, the problem with the traditional definition of knowledge is that it does not show how the condition of justification is linked with the condition of truth in the definition of knowledge as justified true belief. In all counterexamples of Gettier’s kind, the given justification has nothing to do with what makes the proposition true. Consequently, the most natural way to solve the problem is to find the right link between these two conditions. Aiming to warrant this link, Robert Fogelin has suggested a fourth condition, according to which the evidence given by the knowledge-claimer must be able to make the proposition true. Fogelin has also implicitly introduced a third person in the story, which I call the knowledge-evaluator (which can be the knowledge-claimer in a later time…). The knowledge evaluator has an informational set that is wider than that of the knowledge-claimer. Consequently, he or she is able to see that the justifications given by the knowledge-claimer in counterexamples of Gettier kind are unable to make the proposition true.
   My contribution to this perspectival definition of knowledge (the term was proposed to me by John Cottingham) was strengthening Fogelin’s answer by showing the precise formal relationship between the condition of justification and the condition of truth: I have modified the traditional definition in order to show that the given justification must belong to the informational set of justifying evidences accepted or at least acceptable by the knowledge-evaluator in the time of this evaluation as able to make the proposition true. Gettierian counterexamples are never able to do this.[4] I held this as the only proper answer to the problem.

1. THEORIES OF JUSTIFICATION: The dispute between coherentialism and foundationalism are also central in epistemology. My aim in this chapter is to show that a form of modest foundationalism that gives to coherence its due role as organizer and transmitter of beliefs without severing our web of beliefs from the external world is the most plausible theory of justification.
   This chapter must be linked with the last one, since according to the perspectival definition of knowledge what justifies the true belief (satisfying the conditions of justification) and what makes the belief true (satisfying the condition of truth) must be sufficiently parallel justifying evidences. My suggestion will be that the modest foundationalist theory of justification (which includes coherence) must be parallel to a form of correspondence theory of truth (which also includes coherence). The real difference here is that the foundationalist theory of justification is applied by the knowledge-claimer, while the correspondence theory of truth is applied by the knowledge-evaluator (often representing the epistemic community). For this reason, the belief sustained by a piece of justifying evidence can more easily be proved to be false. In the case I succeed in doing this, we will be able to show how the opposition coerentialism versus foundationalism in theory of justification is related to the opposition coerentialism versus correnspondentialism in theory of truth. They are both parallel procedures differing only in their different positions in the social process of constructing knowledge.

5. LIMITS OF KNOWLEDGE: In this chapter, I introduce and develop answers to two main kinds of skepticism: (i) skepticism on induction (Humean) and (ii) skepticism about the external world.
   Regarding the first one, I extend a plausible but forgotten answer that can be found in Keith Campbell.[5] According to him, our world must be intrinsically open to induction, since in order to apply a concept we need to be able to reapply it, what means that our world must contain enough regularity to allow this reapplication and therefore induction. This structural permanence of things alluded by Campbell is what I would call synchronic uniformities. These uniformities are very different from the uniformities that sustain the causal relations focused on Hume’s analyses, which can be called diachronic uniformities. It seems, in fact, impossible to conceive a world without any diachronic and any synchronic uniformity. Even stories of the destruction of our world, like St. John’s Book of Revelations remain full of at least synchronic uniformities of confused but identifiable things in order to preserve its intelligibility. I suggest that an improved reading of Hume’s principle of uniformity of the universe understood as a principle that demands increasing accumulation of uniformities that finds their limits in the present, when both, future and past uniformities, must be the identical. This principle seems to be able to replace Hume’s metaphysical principle as a kind of analytic-conceptual principle that cannot be denied without contradiction.[6]
   Concerning skepticism about the external world, I expose first the ‘argument of ignorance,’ according to which we cannot know any trivial proposition since we cannot know that the skeptical hypothesis is false, followed by its contrapositive moorean anti-skeptical ‘argument of knowledge.’ Although I intend to review some main solutions, like relevant alternatives and contextualism, and show their limitations, I concentrate on a solution that I find the most plausible. This solution was inspired by Carnap’s distinction between internal and external questions of existence and I have developed it in some articles.[7] Although it is impossible to summarize this solution in a few words, the main steps are the following: (1) I suggest that in the non-skeptical, normal context, we are committed with what I call inherent sense of external reality (or existence), which is based on the sum of the traditional criteria of reality attribution (like maximal perceptual intensity, possible intersubjectivity, independence of will, the allowance to natural laws), while in the skeptical context we are committed with what I call an adherent sense of external reality, which has very different criteria of application, based on coherence criteria (like how it would be if someone would turn conscious of his or her past brain-in-a-vat existence?). (2) Because of this difference of meaning, the argument of ignorance (as much as the Moorean argument of knowledge), when formulated in a totally explicit way shows different senses of external reality contextually committed in their different statements, what makes both arguments equivocal and consequently fallacious. (I am aware that in this compressed form these arguments cannot sound clear enough, but I am sure that in the book they will be understood by anyone with basic training in analytic philosophy.[8])



[1] Robert Fogelin, Pyrronian Reflections on Knowledge and Justification (Oxford University Press, 1994), ch. 1. The point was clearly diagnosed much earlier, for instance, in D. J. O’Connor & Brian Carr’s An Introduction to the Theory of Knowledge (The Harvester Press, 1982) pp. 80-82.
[2] Michael Williams follows the same argumentative line in his book Problems of Knowledge: A Critical Introduction to Epistemology, Oxford University Press, 2001), ch. 1.
[3] Claudio F. Costa, “A Perspectival Definition of Knowledge”, Ratio 23 (2), 2010, 151-157. A revised version of this paper was published as the chapter 5 of the book Lines of Thought: Rethinking Philosophical Assumptions (2014), which I am sending attached.
[4] See chapter 5 of my book Lines of Thought: Rethinking Philosophical Assumptions.
[5] Campbell, K., “One form of Skepticism about Induction”, in R. Swinburne, The Justification of induction (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1974)
[6] The essentials of this view were already presented in the appendix of chapter 5 of my book Lines of Thought: Rethinking Philosophical Assumptions (CSP, 2018).
[7] Claudio Costa, “The Skeptical Deal with our Concept of External Reality”, Abstracta  5 : 1, pp. 43 – 76, 2009. An edited version of the paper has been published as the chapter 6 of the book Lines of Thought: Rethinking Philosophical Assumptions (CSP, 2014).
[8] They are clear enough in the papers I have published exposing them, mainly in chapter 6 of the book Lines of Thought: Rethinking Philosophical Assumptions (CSP, 2014). I am sending the texts for the case in which the referee wishes to check the paper.



Nenhum comentário:

Postar um comentário