Quem sou eu

Minha foto
If you wish to be acquainted with my groundbreaking work in philosophy, take a look at this blogg. It is the biggest, the broadest, the deepest. It is so deep that I guess that the narrowed focus of your mind eyes will prevent you to see its full deepness.

domingo, 28 de julho de 2019

SKEPTICAL ILUSIONS

This is a draft for the last chapter of the book to be called BASIC EPISTEMOLOGY.



IV
 LIMITS OF KNOWLEDGE


The difficulty is to realize the groundlessness of our believing.
Wittgenstein

Scepticism is doubt regarding the indubitable. Philosophers have constructed arguments that lead us to questioning things we normally consider certain, like knowledge by testimony, existence of other minds, existence of the external world, inductive knowledge, and even the existence of any knowledge – with the exception of their own knowledge that there is no knowledge, of course, in order to save them from self-contradiction. These arguments are important for epistemology, not as much because they seem to be sound, but mainly because they offer a challenge to the epistemologist – and much philosophical progress is dialectically tributary to challenges like these. Moreover, they help us to establish the limits of our meaningful language and knowledge. Answering the sceptics might allow us to distinguish real questions that can be rationally answered from pseudo-questions that only invite us to produce pointless pseudo-answers. They are only apparently meaningful, because they transcend the limits of what can be cognitively questioned and answered. In what follows, I will restrict myself to the discussion of two such cases: scepticism about induction and scepticism about the external world.

1. Scepticism about induction
Scepticism about induction was introduced by David Hume, entangled with his analysis of causation. Since I am interested here in scepticism about induction, I will strongly reconstruct the argument, separating it from his analysis of causation.
   First, you probably know the form of an enumerative inductive argument: we have a thing[1] A that is associated with a thing B on all occasions, for instance, fire is always associated with heat, which serves as the premise for the conclusion that the next time there is a fire it will heat its surroundings, or even for the generalization that fire will always produce heat. Inductive inferences can be not only from the past to the future (as in the case above), but also from a recent past to a distant past (fire has always heated  its surroundings, dinosaurs once inhabited the earth), and from different locations to new ones, actual or not (like fire in Europe, fire in Burma will heat its surroundings, as much as a fire in Kamchatka heated its surroundings during the last Ice Age). There are other important forms of inductive reasoning, like the inference to the best explanation (abduction). We came to the conclusion that the moon is illuminated by the sun, causing its different phases, because we always see the sun on the side of the sky opposed to the illuminated side of the moon. More than any other hypothesis, this is the best explanation for the phases of the moon. Since premises can be true and despite this the conclusion false, this inference is inductive. Moreover, it seems clear that this kind of inductive inference is based on numerous previous enumerative inferences, like the view that rightly placed luminous physical bodies illuminate non-luminous bodies.
   The Humean question was: how do we know that the premises of a strong inductive argument make the conclusion probable? His answer was the appeal to a metaphysical principle of the regularity or uniformity of nature, which concerning the causal relation can be expressed in the statement that the future will be like the past. We can express the argument as follows:

          A
1.    The future will be like the past.[2]
2.    Fire has always heated its surroundings.
3.    The next fire will heat its surroundings.

Since we wish to contemplate the different extensions of induction in time and space, we can state the principle of uniformity more broadly as follows:

PU:  (i) The future must be like its past, (ii) the less recent past must be like its more recent past, (iii) the next location of space must be like the already known ones.[3]

If PU(i) is correct, then the inductive force of the argument is warranted. A first problem with PU(i) is that this principle is not analytic-conceptual. One can deny it without contradiction or incongruency. “The future will not be like its past” is a perfectly meaningful sentence. If it is so, then PU(i) must be a synthetic statement. But this seems to mean that it is based on experience. Reflecting on this, a Humean sceptic could pose against PU(i) the following question: how do we know the principle of uniformity? The answer concerning PU(i) seems to be the following:

1.    All the futures of our pasts were like their own pasts.
2.    Hence (probably) the future (of our present) will be like its past. 

There is, however, a serious problem with this argument: it is an inductive one. That is, we are trying to warrant our inductive arguments by means of a principle based upon induction, and this is circular. We are committing a petitio principii by trying to justify something using what we intend to justify in the justification. The same can be said regarding the two other parts of PU. Concerning PU(ii) we have the following example:

1.    The less recent past must be like its more recent past. (PU(ii))
2.    In the recent past fire has always heated things.
3.    Hence (probably) in the remote past fire also heated things.

Concerning PU(iii) (plus PU(ii)) we have also a similar example:

1.    The next region of space must be like the already known region of space. (PU(iii))
2.    The less recent past must be like its more recent past. (PU(ii))
3.    In the recent past fire has always heated things in all regions of earth.
4.    Hence (probably) fire heated things in Kamchatka during the Ice Age.

Hume’s conclusion, based on an analysis restricted to PU(i), was downright sceptical: we cannot warrant our inductive arguments. And this conclusion must be obviously extended to PU(ii) and PU(iii), since these parts of our version of the principle of uniformity also depend on inductive reasoning to be established.
   The conclusion is that we have no reason to believe that the sun will rise tomorrow or that in the remote past fire heated things or that it heated things in Kamchatka during the last Ice Age… Neither our empirical science nor our common sense knowledge of the world have any rational warrant.
   According to Hume, we have only a psychological disposition to believe in our inductive results, since they form a habit or custom for us: we have the habit to expect that the next fire will heat things or that the sun will rise tomorrow in the same way insects have the instinctive tendency to follow light (1764: 75). However, with the queer exception of Karl Popper, few philosophers have followed Hume on this point.

2. A general answer
There have been many intelligent attempts to solve Hume’s problem of induction, all of them in one way or another disappointing. There is, however, one that seems to me to touch the very heart of the problem, though it has never been sufficiently developed. It is suggested in the words of Jenny Teichman and C. C. Evans (1999), in their short introduction to philosophy:

It would be impossible to say truly that the universe is a chaos, since if the universe were genuinely chaotic there would not be a language to tell it. A language depends on things and qualities having enough persistence in time to be identified by words and this same persistence is a form of uniformity.

The philosopher Keith Campbell made the same point earlier. As I understand him, he noted that the world must have sufficient order to allow us to reapply a concept, since if our concepts could not be reapplied, they could not be interpersonally checked, and therefore could not be established as concepts (1974: 80-83). Indeed, concepts could not turn out to be intersubjectively granted and consensually associated with conceptual words.
   Although emphasizing language, what these authors grasped is that it doesn’t matter how disorderly a world is, if it is recognizable as a world, it must have enough order (spatial and temporal) to be open to some kind of inductive access. That is, a possible world is only conceivable if it is open to induction. Openness to induction is a condition of possibility for the cognition of any possible world.
   We can order these intuitions about the relationship between world (or universe), and induction in the form of the following argument:

1.    Any possible world must be at least conceivable.
2.    Any conceivable world should have at least some degree of regularity.
3.    Any world that has some degree of regularity is open to some kind of inductive procedure.
4.    (1-3) Any conceivable world must be open to some kind of inductive procedure.
5.    Any world must be conceivable.
6.    (4,5) Hence, any world must be open to some kind of inductive procedure.
7.    Corollary to 6: our world is open to some kind of inductive procedure;

The central idea in this argument is that the existence of a fully chaotic world is impossible, since such a world would be inconceivable and we cannot speak meaningfully of worlds that are inconceivable, that is, in no sense imaginable, since this does not belong to the concept of world (or universe) as we are able to understand it.
   One reason why this idea can meet some resistance is that the literature on the problem of induction is full of references to chaotic worlds which are inaccessible to inductive procedures. This is, however, a tragic mistake, and I am sorry to say that that the person most responsible for this mistake was Hume himself. This mistake arose from his objection against the justifiability of induction restricted to his analysis of causality, which is based on UP(i). Causality is typically what we could call a case of diachronic regularity, which occurs when in a regular way an event A occurs temporally earlier than an event B. This is clear in Hume’s counter-inductive examples, which go from Adam, who seeing a lake for the first time did not know that the water could drown him, to falling snow that unexpectedly burns and flowers that unexpectedly bloom in the middle of winter (1764: 35). If induction were restricted to diachronic regularities, it would suffice to imagine a frozen world – a world without any diachronic regularity – and it would be a world impervious to induction. However, focusing on diachronic regularities leads us to forget another, equally important form of regularity also assumed by UP, namely, synchronic regularity. The state of affairs that Notre Dame is on the Ille de France, the situation that the Tower of Pisa leans and the supposed fact that Cleopatra had a big nose are all synchronic regularities. These synchronic regularities are often called structures. A gothic cathedral has a very complex synchronic structure and has usually existed over a long period of time. Synchronic regularities are, however, objects of induction as much as diachronic regularities, since only induction allows us to foresee that synchronic regularities perceived in the past will endure in the future. Notre Dame will remain on the Ille of France, the Tower of Pisa will continue to lean, Cleopatra supposedly had a big nose until her death, the gothic Cathedrals are expected to preserve their structures through the centuries, all this we believe as result of induction.
   When we realize that our world is made up as much of diachronic regularities as also of synchronic regularities, then it becomes clearly impossible to think that we are able to conceive a world without regularities. Consider, for instance, one among the many attempts to imagine a world so completely chaotic that it would be a world without regularities. We can appeal to ‘complete transformations of the world’ as described in many fictional books. I choose the following passage from Sartre’s novel Nausea. It reminds us of surrealistic art, such as the paintings of Dali:

It can happen any time, perhaps right now: the omens are present. For example, the father of a family might go out for a walk, and, across the street, he’ll see something like a red rag, blown towards him by the wind. And when the rag has gotten close to him, he’ll see that it is a side of rotten meat, grimy with dust, dragging itself along by crawling, skipping, a piece of writhing flesh rolling in the gutter, spasmodically shooting out spurts of blood. Or a mother might look at her child’s cheek and ask him: "What's that – a pimple?" and see the flesh puff out a little, split, open, and at the bottom of the split an eye, a laughing eye might appear. Or they might feel things gently brushing against their bodies, like the caresses of reeds to swimmers in a river. And they will realize that their clothing has become living things. And someone else might feel something scratching in his mouth. He goes to the mirror, opens his mouth: and his tongue is an enormous, live centipede, rubbing its legs together and scraping his palate. He’d like to spit it out, but the centipede is a part of him and he will have to tear it out with his own hands. And a crowd of things will appear for which people will have to find new names—stone-eye, great three-cornered arm, toecrutch, spider-jaw. And someone might be sleeping in his comfortable bed, in his quiet, warm room, and wake up naked on a bluish earth, in a forest of rustling birch trees, rising red and white towards the sky like the smokestacks of Jouxtebouville, with big bumps half-way out of the ground, hairy and bulbous like onions. And birds will fly around these birch trees and pick at them with their beaks and make them bleed. Sperm will flow slowly, gently, from these wounds, sperm mixed with blood, warm and glassy with little bubbles. (…)

At first glance, these changes are extreme. Nonetheless, there is nothing in this report (or in any report of the kind) that makes it really chaotic. Although the living rotten meat crawling to the family father is indeed a strange creature, its unexpected properties are all already well-known. Moreover, even the individuals suffering changes, like the child, an eye, a man, a tongue, birch trees, birds, can be also identified, although their also well-known new properties are unexpected and frightening. The centipede behaves like a centipede and human beings react desperately as expected in the such situations. What Sartre describes is based on a considerable number of well-known synchronic and diachronic regularities combined in unexpected ways, and the only reason why we are able to fully understand the description and react to it is because of our acquaintance with all these well-known regularities. In fact, if all regularities could be erased, the text would lose any intelligibility. The future, at least in proportion to its greater proximity to the present, must maintain sufficient similarity to its past to allow an application of inductive procedures, making us recognize the continuity of the same world we know today, notwithstanding how many unexpected and undesirable changes come to pass.
   We can do some thought-experiments in order to reinforce these conclusions. Imagine a frozen world without any diachronic regularities. This world would still have the regularity of the permanence of its form or structure, once we apply inductive reasoning to foresee that it would remain the same world in the next moment or over the whole period of its existence. Imagine by contrast a world formed by a note of a single pitch or a blinking red light that repeats itself at aleatory intervals. Once it ceases to repeat, this world ceases to exist. But this minimalist world still has the regularity of repetition. Hence, one could inductively expect this repetition.
   One can complain that it may be difficult to apply induction when the regularities are few. But this remark ignores a logical point. Induction is theoretically flexible. The required inductive search can be calibrated in conformity with circumstances. When the probability to find a regularity is lower, we expand the inductive search. Consider, for instance, the wild camels of the Gobi desert. The expanse of the Gobi desert is immense. It includes the north of China and the whole of Mongolia. And these shy camels are rare, supposing they have not yet become extinct. You can visually survey a vast expanse of desert, searching up and down the hills with powerful binoculars until you find a Gobi camel, if you have luck. The pressure of inductive calibration must be very high in this case.
   The general conclusion is that some principle of uniformity must be applicable, insofar as we might assume cognitive access to the world. As we will see, we lack a formulation of this principle that is sufficiently precise and adequate instead of vague and misleading.

3. Searching for more appropriate answers
When we more carefully consider the temporal dimensions (i) and (ii) and the spatial dimension (iii) of PU, within which we apply inductive reasoning, we see that much more must be taken into consideration.[4] Consider PU(i): the principle that the future will be like its past. What is meant with PU(i) is vague. Suppose we take it literally (like Hume) and deny this by saying that the future will not be like its past. This denial does not seem to contain any contradiction, which means that PU(i) is not analytical. This is not desirable, since PU(i) cannot be synthetic a posteriori or empirical, and since we do not wish to accept a principle of uniformity that is synthetic a priori; such a principle would go against the very plausible view according to which all (or almost all) our empirical knowledge is fallible. Moreover, the literal reading of PU(i) as telling us that all of the future will be similar to its past is obviously wrong. Not only does nothing prevent great unexpected changes (a great meteor collides with the earth, etc.), but considering the infinitude of time, the distant future can be utterly different from our past. Suppose, for instance, you could observe the world some micro-seconds after the big-bang. The future in which there would be myriads of galaxies with stars and planets, some of them with life and consciousness like we find on the earth, would be utterly different from what was going on at that moment.
   However, there is something analytically right in PU(i). Although the future can be different from its past, it cannot be completely different from its past, or at least the near future cannot be. For in this case, how could we identify a future as the future of its own past? We must interpret PU(i) as saying that the future, insofar as it approaches the present, must be sufficiently similar to its past in order to be the future of its own past. Call the future of our world FW0. It must, at least insofar as it approaches the present, be more like its past, in order to be identified with the future of the past W0 or PW0. If it were not so, it could be identified with the past of any possible future world, say, of FW1, FW2, FW3… and we would lose the proper way of distinguishing it. (Moreover, this related transition from past to future must be spatially located: imagine, for instance, that the near past of a sunny day in London is suddenly replaced by the near future on Calisto, a satellite of Jupiter.)
   If we wish to warrant induction, we must read the principle that the future must be like its past in a more precise and adequate way. We must refine PU(i) so that it shows itself as something analytic-conceptual and a priori in this harmless sense. In order to show that such a reading is possible, consider the following example:

Presently, at time T0, there is a piece of wax. This piece of wax is warmed and in T1 it changes from a solid to a liquid state. Until now, most things have remained the same, not only the atomic constitution of the wax, but also the molecular constitution that makes up what we commonly call wax. Then, in T2 the wax is warmed much more, so that what remains are only ashes. The chemical constitution of the wax is now lost, the atoms of oxygen have disappeared, only the atoms of carbon are still there. Now, suppose that the process of heating continues and that the carbon ash is heated by hundreds of millions of degrees, so that in T3 the atoms disintegrate and all that remains is a plasma of sub-atomic particles.

It is easy to understand what this progression shows: the nearer the future is to the present, the more properties it still has in common with the present, until the point of junction of the future and the past – which is the present – a point of complete identity, where all properties are the same. The same rule is valid considering the relation between the present and its past. Furthermore, the example with the piece of wax can be generalized. It can be applied to any domain of our world. On any level, this same pattern repeats itself: Natura non facit saltus. For instance, the industrial revolution began in the second half of the XVIIIth century. But if we consider the changes in a short period of time, such as from 1760 to 1800, we can find only a few changes, like the introduction of mechanized weaving machines in England and a small rural exodus in England. Large-scale iron and steel production, steam power, steamships, locomotives and railways, the great rural exodus and serious social tensions… had to wait until the next century. Certainly, there are anomalous progressions in which a near future can for a while be more different from the present than a more distant future, but in this case, you can consider only the nearest future, or you can consider a broader interval that includes this kind of anomaly but makes it irrelevant. To give an analogy, consider the following anomalous progression: {1, 2, 3, 2, 3, 4, 3, 4, 5…}. The fact that some numbers are unexpectedly nearer to 1 does not change the fact that this is a positive numerical progression, and many variants, also anomic ones, can be added. Looking for a real empirical example, consider the continued economic development of a country, with all its booms and busts.
   Using the word ‘tendency’ to discard possible anomalies, the principle that the future will be similar to its past can be improved as follows:

UP(i)* Tendentially, the nearer the future is to its point of junction with its past (i.e., the present), the more similarities will be held with its past, being both the same at the point of junction.

I would understand this reading of UP(i) as analytic-conceptual. We cannot deny it without saying something incongruent, if not contradictory. We cannot deny that there is a tendency to the annulation of the differences between future and past the nearer they approximate to the present. Now we can warrant inductive probability by means of an analytic-conceptual (a priori) principle:

1.    Tendentially, the nearer the future is to its own past, the more similarities it will have with its past.
2.    In the past fire always heated things.
3.    The next fire will (probably) heat things.

This seems to me sufficient to inductively warrant that the next fire will probably heat things.
   Consider now the other sub-principles of uniformity. Sub-principle UP(ii) represents no problem, since it is UP(i) projected onto the past. But sub-principle (iii) still requires some explanation. The principle that one region of space must be like another, taken strictly, is certainly false. The region of the Côte d’Azur must be very different from the region of a black hole. We are in fact speaking of proximal regions. Thinking in this way we can state the principle of spatial uniformity in a way that is analogous to the above principles of temporal uniformity:

UP(iii)*: Tendentially, the nearer one spatial region is to the spatial region we have already considered, the more similar this spatial region will be to the spatial region we are considering, both being the same in their point of junction (i.e., the spatial limit).

For instance: suppose that we can see part of a checkerboard surface. You can be fairly sure that the next segment we see of the same surface will also have a checkerboard pattern. We expect based on experience that unknown space will preserve regularities in the same way as time. UP(iii)* is also analytic-conceptual: you cannot deny this tendency without contradiction.[5] Indeed, if this principle is constitutive of the way we are able to access any possible world in its temporal dimension, it cannot be logico-conceptually refuted.
   Outflanked, the sceptic could appeal to a drastic objection. Even if we concede that a world, in order to be a world, must have enough uniformity to make possible the use of inductive procedures, there is nothing that absolutely warrants the continuity of anything. Suppose that our whole world disappears five seconds from now. Nothing in our principle of uniformity PU(i)* would prevent this possibility! To this consideration one has the inclination to answer in the affirmative, admitting that there is nothing to warrant the permanence of our world. Hume was, after all, right!
   Nonetheless, when we think about this sceptical objection more carefully, we see that the true answer is a different one. The truth is that this sceptical objection makes no sense, because it requires a completely unverifiable answer. If the universe disappears in five seconds, there will be no one to verify this disappearance.[6] In this regard, it makes no sense to speak about what you logically cannot know. The situation seems to be possible because we can imagine the world disappearing with us as if we could be transcendent observers of this dissolution.[7] In other words, we have arrived at the limits of what we can meaningfully think and know. The sentence “We and our whole world could disappear in the next five seconds” is like the sentence “The whole world doubled its size last night”. It might be dizzying, but it has only a grammatical sense and an emotional effect – not a cognitive sense.

4. Scepticism about the external world
The second famous sceptical argument aims to show that we cannot know the existence of the external world. I call it the argument for ignorance about the external world. This argument makes use of sceptical hypotheses about the external world. Hence, in order to explain it I begin by giving three examples of this kind of sceptical hypotheses:

h1: The external world is a dream.
h2: I am a soul being deceived by a malign genie that produces in me the coherent hallucination of an external world.
h3: I am a brain-in-a-vat with all afferent and efferent neuronal bundles linked to a supercomputer on the planet Omega; the program of this supercomputer makes me believe that I am living a normal life on the planet earth.

The argument for ignorance is based on the fact that it seems impossible to prove that the sceptical hypotheses are false. This might seem strange, but it is at least logically possible, a possibility that is explored in science fiction films like Matrix or The Real Thing. Now, applying hypothesis h3[8], the sceptic can argue as follows. If I cannot know that I am a brain-in-a-vat, then I cannot know that I really have two hands or that I am typing on a real computer keyboard; hence, since I cannot know that I am not a brain-in-a-vat, I cannot know that I have two hands or that I am typing… Putting this argument in conventional form we have the following modus ponens:

        Instance of AI:
1.    I do not know that I am not a brain-in-a-vat.
2.    Since I do not know that I am not a brain-in-a-vat, I cannot know that I have two hands.
3.    Hence, I cannot know that I have two hands. (MP 1, 2)

Indeed, if I cannot know whether or not I am a brain-in-a-vat, then I cannot know if I have two hands, since a brain-in-a-vat does not have two hands (but only imagines having them). Hence, if I do not know that I am not a brain-in-a-vat, I cannot know that I have two hands.
   Now, replacing any trivial proposition about the external world by p, and using K as a knowledge-operator applied by some epistemic subject a, we can symbolize in a generalized form the argument for ignorance, aiming to show that in fact we know nothing about the external world:

         AI:
1.    ~a(K~h)
2.    ~a(K~h) → ~aKp
3.    ~aKp (MP 1, 2)

The argument of ignorance seems to show that since we cannot know that the sceptical hypothesis is false, we cannot acquire any substantive knowledge about the external world. This shares with other sceptical arguments a property noted by Hume: they do not admit of answers and do not produce conviction (1748: 155).
   There is a contrapositive to this argument, made famous in an article by the English philosopher G. E. Moore. His approach was to begin by acknowledging that we at least know with certainty that many trivial things around us do exist. As he wrote:

I can prove that two human hands exist. How? Raising my two hands and making a certain gesture with my right hand: “Here is a hand”. And then making the same gesture with the left: “Here is another hand”. (1939)

We can modify Moore’s statements a bit, from an argument to prove the existence of the world to an anti-sceptical argument – call it the argument for knowledge regarding the external world. The conventional form of this argument will be the following modus ponens:

   Instance of AC:
1.    I know that I have two hands.
2.    If I know that I have two hands, then I know that I am not a brain-in-a-vat.
3.    I know that I am not a brain-in-a-vat. (MP 1, 2)

Or, in a generalized symbolic form:

        AC:
1.    aKp
2.    aKp → ~a(K~h)
3.    ~a(K~h)

The two arguments seem to have the same force. The question, however, persists, since it is contradictory that we have two equally powerful arguments leading us to opposite results.

5. Some attempted ways of answering
There are many attempts to answer the argument of ignorance about the external world. Hilary Putnam’s answer, for instance, would be that we cannot be brains in vats because according to his externalist theory of meaning we would need to have causal experience of things in the world in order to know their meaning. Now, if we can imagine that we are brains in vats seeing trees, then we must have had the experience of real external things like trees and vats and even brains, which means that we cannot be brains-in-vats. In the end, all that the brain-in-a-vat causally experiences are electrical patterns of trees, or images he may produce of vats, which are also originated from electrical patterns produced by the supercomputer. One could answer that at least the people who manufactured the supercomputer and created its programs had the causal experience of trees and vats and brains. In this case, they would be caused by these things to create the programs that indirectly caused our pattern images and our false idea that we could be brains-in-vats. Putnam’s answer to this would be that the brain-in-a-vat and the supercomputer could be created by a mere cosmic accident, without any living beings producing the brain, the computer and its program!
   There are several objections to Putnam’s argument. One is that it only works against the brain-in-a-vat sceptical hypothesis; one could instead use the dream hypothesis. Another is that one can accept Putnam’s argument, but retain the hypothesis by considering recently envatted brains (these brains would already have causally experienced our world) (DeRose 1999). A third objection is that Putnam disregards the flexibility of language. If it is possible that the cosmic accident produces a brain-in-a-vat powered by the program of a supercomputer, then it is also possible that the electrical pattern that causes the vision of the tree and the idea that we are brains in vats are, by pure coincidence, the same patterns that cause in us the illusion that we are seeing a tree and the ideas that we are brains-in-vats, while we really are brains-in-vats. Why not?
   A different answer to the sceptical problem consists in denial of the so-called principle of closure. According to this principle, if person a knows p and also knows that p entails q, then a also knows q. Symbolically, we can state the principle of closure as:

[aKp & aK(p → q)] → aKq

This principle is very intuitive, except in cases where the conclusion is a shortcut for many intermediary steps (say, [aKp & aK(p → p1 → … →pn→q)] → aKn), which we might leave out of consideration.
  However, objecting to the sceptic, one can say that according to the context the principle can be flawed. This is the case of answers appealing to the principle of relevant alternatives. According to them, one alternative possibility should only respect closure when it is sufficiently relevant. For instance, suppose you are in a zoo and you see a zebra. Then a sceptic comes to you and says that you cannot really know that you are seeing a zebra, since it is possible that it is only a donkey cleverly painted in a way that makes it seem to be a zebra. However, the context of a serious zoo would make it almost impossible that people would paint donkeys so that they would seem to be zebras. (Dretske 1970) According to this view, “I am seeing a zebra” does not entail “This is not a donkey cleverly painted in order to be mistakenly regarded as a zebra” and does not need to entail this. Here the principle of closure does not work.
   The problem with this argument is that it is not clear that I cannot apply the closure principle. If I know that this is a zebra, and I know that if it is a zebra then it is not a donkey, then I know that it is not a donkey. Indeed, I know that it is not a donkey because I am supported by contextual information: I know that this is a serious zoo and not a circus. I know that because it is a zebra the proposed irrelevant alternative is false.
   With the help of his argument, the defender of the relevant alternatives answer to the sceptic usually argues that it is very implausible to think that the statement “I cannot know that I am not a brain-in-a-vat” would entail something so distant from this as “I cannot know that I have two hands”. The context that would allow this possibility is too strange and remote. The answer that could be given is that we cannot make such kinds of considerations. The hypothesis that I am a brain-in-a-vat is not improbable in comparison with the hypothesis that I have two hands. We simply do not have means to attest to its probability or improbability.
   Another attempt to deal with the sceptical argument is contextualism. As we have already noted, according to contextualism the word ‘knowledge’ can be used with different degrees of precision when placed in different contexts. With this idea at hand, the contextualist will say that in the context of daily life standards of knowledge are very low, which means that we can claim knowledge of things around us, like our hands. But in sceptical contexts we cannot say that we know that we have two hands, since the standards of knowledge are too high. Consequently, both are right, the sceptical and the anti-sceptical views, since they claim different things.
   A first problem with this argument is that it is not clear that the sceptical view does demand very high standards of knowledge. Clearer is that the sceptical hypothesis cannot be probabilistically approached. It is only a logical possibility.   
   A second problem with this argument resides in the contextualist thesis. It is not clear that contextually different knowledge-claims really demand different standards of empirical precision. Repeating the objection that I made in chapter II, if I buy the ticket for a plane flight, I can say that I know my aircraft will not crash, because the probability of this occurrence is very low (1 in 5.4 million). But if I buy a lottery ticket, I am not allowed to say that I know I will not win, even if the probability of winning a lottery is much lower than the probability that my aircraft will crash (1 in 13 million for the lottery). Why don’t I say I know I will not win a lottery prize? The contextualist answer is that in the lottery context the demands of probability are much higher.
   Nevertheless, it seems to me that a better answer would be that the linguistic expression of thought is often too inexplicit, although the thought is what the sentence really means, and the sentence is the truth-bearer of the thought. In the first case, what is demanded is practical certainty, while in the second case what is demanded is logical certainty. What really changes is the thought, which is too vaguely expressed by the declarative sentence. The thought expressed in the first case is: “I know [with practical certainty] that my aircraft will not crash”, while in the second case the thought must be expressed as “I do not know [with probability 1] that I will not win the lottery”, since it is a statistic inference that demands formal certainty.

6. A more convincing answer
The solution I will propose takes as its assumption the notion that problems and their solutions are more complex than they seem at first view. Consequently, the above suggested answers, despite their originality, do not really solve the problems, since their formulations contribute to hiding complexities invisible on the argumentative surface.
   Now, the solution I intend to present is based upon a demonstration that the two arguments – for ignorance and for knowledge – implicitly contain two different concepts of external reality. These concepts, however, change their meaning from the premises to the conclusion, which makes both arguments equivocal and consequently fallacious. This solution is motivated by Rudolph Carnap’s distinction between internal and external questions of existence. According to him, internal questions are those regarding elements of a system and are answered by placing the elements adequately within the system. For example: “Is there a number 2?” is internal regarding the system of natural numbers. “Are there physical objects?” is internal regarding the system of physical things (the Thing-World). These questions are legitimate. External questions are ones regarding the existence of systems in themselves. These questions only allow pragmatic answers. We decide to accept the system of natural numbers. We decide to accept the system of physical things. These decisions arise from a pragmatic fiat. Philosophers such as P. F. Strawson (1974) and Barry Stroud (1984) have with reason criticized Carnap on the grounds that our decision of accepting a system, in particular the system of physical things, obviously does not arise from a pragmatic decision. The external world simply imposes itself on us, independently of any wish or advantage its acceptance gives us. The analysis I will propose circumvents this kind of objection, though maintaining that there are two kinds of attributions of external existence or reality.
   The first thing to do in order to reach our goal is to show that the arguments for ignorance and knowledge have implicit commitments to attributions and disattributions of reality. This is easy to show. Comcerning the argument for ignorance, we can give the following paraphrase:

   Instance of AI:
1.    I do not know that I am not in reality a brain-in-a-vat.
2.    Since I do not know that I am not in reality a brain-in-a-vat, I cannot know that I have two real hands.
3.    Hence, I cannot know that I have two real hands. (MP 1, 2)

While with the argument for knowledge the paraphrase is:

    Instance of AC:
1.    I know that I have two real hands.
2.    If I know that I have two real hands, then I know that I am not in reality a brain-in-a-vat.
3.    I know that I am not in reality a brain-in-a-vat. (MP 1, 2)

There is no doubt about this: any statement concerning an external world contains a commitment to the assumption of the external reality for what it affirms or the assumption of a lack of external reality for what it denies.
   What should be noted, however, is that the expression ‘external reality’ in our most common uses has a sense very different from the expression ‘external reality’ as used in sceptical scenarios. To show this, all we need is to note that after being liberated from a life as a brain-in-a-vat, a person will presumably not say that her earlier world was not real. She will probably say that in a sense her earlier world was very real for her or “had a perfect degree of reality” for her at the time, although in another sense it was indeed not the ultimately real world, as she subsequently discovered. This means that the person is using the word ‘real’ in two very different senses: in the first one she affirms the existence of the previous real world of the supercomputer, in the second she denies its existence. I call the first the inherent sense of external reality, a sense that allows the attribution of external reality to the contents of experience of the brain-in-a-vat when it still was a brain-in-a-vat, while the second I call the adherent sense of external reality, a sense that does not allow the attribution of external reality to the contents of experience of the brain-in-a-vat when it still was a brain-in-a-vat. In order to make the distinction clear I will separately examine the criteria of application constitutive of each of these senses of ‘external reality’. After all, by knowing the criteria of application of these words, we can better understand their meanings. Or, as Wittgenstein once said, criteria “give our words their common meaning” (1958: 57).
   Consider, first, the inherent sense of external reality. It is the usual sense which is applied when we attribute/disattribute external existence in everyday life. For instance, when we ask about the existence or reality of something we are looking for. This sense is made by a group of criteria that ordinarily must be experienced together, and it was frequently and in various ways considered by modern philosophers like Descartes, Locke, Berkeley, Hume, and even by analytic philosophers like Frege. G. E. Moore wrote an article about these criteria, summarizing them in the following sentence:

The real is something independent of the mind that is verifiable by others, continuously connected with other things, and in this way has certain causes, effects and accompaniments (I would say that it ‘displays regularities’) with the highest degree of reality. (1953)

I think I can summarize the most fundamental criteria as follows:

a.     The sensory experience of them has the greatest intensity (normally this experience is co-sensorial),
b.    They are independent of our will (typically),
c.     They are interpersonally checkable by anyone in the right position,
d.    They display regularities imposed by natural laws (on various different levels).

Separately, these conditions are not sufficient for the attribution of inherent reality to objects outside us. (Laurence Bonjour was right when he wrote that Locke’s criteria were insufficient to warrant external reality (2002: 130-35)). However, my point is that if you join together all those criteria, they are sufficient to confer inherent reality on what they apply to during the time when they are applicable. They are sufficient for a simple reason: they define what we all understand by external reality in the inherent sense of the word.
   Consider, for example, my computer. I can see it, touch it, and hear it with the maximum expected intensity, differently from the images I can form in my mind when I close my eyes. Moreover, its existence and properties are not directly dependent on my will (my mental image of it is directly dependent on my will). My hand-held computer can be an object of interpersonal experience: others can come to me, see it, and agree about its existence and properties. Finally, my computer obeys the laws of nature. It needs electrical energy to work, to respond to my commands, it will break if it is dropped from a high place, etc. If we join these four criteria of external reality together, it is impossible to imagine a situation where we cannot say that the object of experience is (inherently) real. Even if I were a brain-in-a-vat or if I were subjected to a very highly developed experience of artificial reality, my hand-computer would be very real in this sense of the word.
   What about things too small or too distant to be presently observed by us? Could we say that they are real in the inherent sense? Yes, of course, and by means of a very common mechanism of semantic extension of the three above given criteria. In an indirect way, a thing that is too small is said to be real because it is causally related to other things with which we can have sensory-perceptual contact (like tracks left by electrons in a cloud chamber). Things that are too far distant, either because they were once objects of perception and are retained in our memories (like my great-father’s house), or that were once objects of sensory perception by others (like Angkor Wat, a religious site I have never visited), satisfy the four criteria considered above, because we know that these things would satisfy those criteria to us, given the right circumstances of access. Finally, since we have always experienced new things in such ways, we inductively expect that we will continue to have new experiences of new things (the world is open). We can even join all these things in order to produce a proof of the external world as a whole, insofar as we understand it as possessing inherent reality. Indeed, this is in my view the long sought proof of the external world’s existence! This is the reason why people say that only philosophers and madman deny that our world exists. They all have implicitly made such inferences, and what they mean is that the external world is nothing but the sum of all these implicit extensions of applications of the concept of inherent reality.
   These inherent attributions/disatributions of reality are the usual ones: without perceiving this we apply them all the time. But there is another attribution/disatribution of reality that is sometimes made, which concerns what I called the adherent sense of reality or existence. This is the sense of reality that we attribute/disattribute to things like fictional reality and sceptical scenarios. We can say that the sense is different because the criteria of application have nothing to do with the four criteria of inherent reality considered above. Suppose, for a moment, that the world is a dream or that you are a brain-in-a-vat. In this case, the world continues to exist for you in the inherent sense of the word. If you fall from a tree and break a leg, your pain is as real as any other, and the leg is really broken and in need of immediate medical attention. All things appear to you with maximum sensory intensity, interpersonally and following the laws of nature (since the supercomputer program is the best on the market), which warrants the inherent existence of things around you. But in some other sense, these things are not real, and this sense is that of adherent reality. Although the world of the dreamer or the brain-in-a-vat has no adherent reality, in the inherent sense it continues to be perfectly real.
   The question now is about criteria for adherent reality. How can one know that a world is adherently unreal? The answer is: comparatively and by reasons of coherence. The concept of adherent reality is a comparative (or relative) one. A comparative concept changes its applicability in conformity with the context. For instance, the words ‘small’ and ‘big’: a baby elephant is small compared with an adult elephant; however, it is a big animal compared with a mouse (Copi). Now, suppose that you have lived your whole life as a brain-in-a-vat and that now you are liberated. Your brain was inserted in the head of a person on the planet Omega and you awake in your new world, meeting other people who resemble you as you now appear. They reveal that the experiment was motivated by the desire to create cultural diversity on the planet. Moreover, they show you the empty vat and the supercomputer, together with other fellow brains-in-vats being nourished and formatted. Surely, if all this does not drive you mad, you will compare and see that the world where you lived was a kind of sub-product of the truly real world, the world of the planet Omega, since this is the best way you have to make the information you have received until now seem coherent.
   Knowledge of adherent reality is, I think, only comparative. Before you were liberated from the vat, it would have made no sense to ask if you were a brain-in-a-vat or not. The same is true concerning ourselves and our world. To question its adherent reality makes no sense without the advent of a sceptical scenario that endows us with the expected comparative criteria. Furthermore, the comparative sense of the adherent attributions/ disattributions of reality is defeasible. You cannot be sure that the new world of the planet Omega is the ultimate one: there is no criteria for this. It is even possible that you are once more being deceived. It is possible that they only changed the program. As you awoke, the program running in the supercomputer was “being awakened from a brain-in-a-vat experiment”.
   I believe it is important to see that there is no absolute sense for adherent reality, but only a comparative one. Because of this, the question “Is our world adherently real? – is it the ultimate world?” is strictly considered meaningless if taken in a literal sense, since the comparative criteria are not at our disposal. What the question “Is our world adherently real?” means is to ask whether our world is the ultimately real one, but this is a pseudo-question that can only work as a metaphysical trap that could have and has often led to many pseudo-answers. It sounds like the question, “Why (for what reason) does the world exist?”, which has a grammatical sense and an emotive effect, but lacks cognitive sense, as much as any attempt to answer it. Then, why does it seem to make sense? Well, because we confuse it with another question that lurks in our imagination, namely: “Could our world in opposition to a sceptical scenario be comparatively classified as the adherently non-real one?”, and this question makes full sense. For this reason, “I know that our world is adherently real” is a senseless pseudo-affirmation, unless it is understood as “If I were liberated in a sceptical scenario, I would (comparatively) know that the actual world is the adherently real one”. Wittgenstein considered claims of knowledge that make no sense, for instance, if in the presence of another person one suddenly says, “I know that you are in front of me” without any purpose (1984a), and I think we have such a case here. With pseudo-questions like “Can we know if our world is real?”, intending to use the word ‘real’ in an adherent absolute sense – whích philosophers have often meant – we have already transgressed the limits of what can be meaningfully known.
   Now, having understood the two senses of the word ‘external reality’ (or ‘existence’), we are prepared to see why both the sceptical argument of ignorance and the anti-sceptical argument of knowledge are equivocal and consequently fallacious. It is because in both cases we imperceptibly pass from a commitment to one sense of ‘external reality’ to a commitment to the other sense of ‘external reality’. In order to make the point clear, definitely breaking down the arguments, all we need to do is to make explicit the commitments to reality/non-reality implicit in each argument.
   The first sentence of the argument of ignorance will be as follows:

   Instance of AI:
1.    I cannot know that I am not an adherently real brain-in-a-vat.
2.    Since I cannot know that I am not an adherently real brain-in-a-vat, I cannot know that I have two adherently real hands.
3.    Hence, I cannot know that I have two inherently real hands. (MP 1, 2)

This is the most natural way to interpret the argument, choosing the sense of reality in accordance with the statements’ semantic context. In the first two sentences we have a sceptical scenario, and the senses of external reality contextually suggested are adherent ones. In the conclusion, however, the sceptical wish is to convince us that we cannot attribute inherent reality to anything. The sceptic intends to give us the comforting sense that our hands, like all other external things, are ethereal objects like ghosts in haze and that we are living in a fictive world without material reality. If the conclusion were, “Hence, I cannot know that I have two adherently real hands,” the argument would be sound, but trivial. Indeed, this we cannot know, since outside the sceptical comparative scenario we have no way to use comparative attributions of reality or non-reality. Obviously, this result can be extended to the generalized formal version of the argument of ignorance.
   Curiously, a similar fallacy plagues the argument of knowledge. Once we expose the implicit assumptions of reality, it looks like this:

      Instance of AC:
1.    I know I have two inherently real hands.[9]
2.    If I know that I have two adherently real hands, then I know that I am not an adherently real brain-in-a-vat.
3.    Hence, I know that I am not an adherently real brain-in-a-vat. (MP 1, 2)

The anti-sceptic makes an equivocal step from the first to the second premise of the argument in his attempt to prove that he knows that this is our ultimate world, resistant to sceptical doubts. But his equivocal conclusion lies beyond the limits of our knowledge. It makes no sense to ask for something that lacks any verifying criteria, since the statement requires an absolute attribution of adherent reality.
   In conclusion, scepticism about induction and scepticism about the external world have something in common. Both are fallacious arguments based on disregard for the limits of our knowledge, which is reflected in the limitations of meaningful language and thought.
















BIBLIOGRAPHY



Almeder, Robert F. 1974. “Truth and Evidence”. Philosophical Quarterly, 24, pp. 365-68.
Alston, William P., 1989. Epistemic Justification: Essays in the Theory of Knowledge. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Armstrong, David, 1973. Belief, Truth, and Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Attwood, Thomas. 2007. A Complete Guide to Asperger’s Syndrome. London: Jessica Kingsley Publishers.
Audi, Robert. 1998. Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction to the Theory of Knowledge. London: Routledge.
Audi, Robert. 1993. The Structure of Justification. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Ayer, A. J. 1956. The Problem of Knowledge (London: Macmillan).
Boghossian, Paul. (2006) Fear of Knowledge: Against Relativism and Constructivism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Bonjour, Laurence & Ernest Sosa. 2003. Epistemic Justification: Internalism vs. Externalism, Foundations vs. Virtues. Oxford: Blackwell.
BonJour, L. (2002). Epistemology: Classic Problems and Contemporary Responses. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Bonjour, Laurence. 1998. In Defense of Pure Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- 1985. The Structure of Empirical Knowledge. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Bosanquet, Bernard. 1920. Implication and Linear Inference. London: McMillan.
Casullo, Albert. 2003. A Priori Justification. New York: Oxford University Press.
Chisholm, Roderick M. (1977). Theory of Knowledge. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Chomsky, Noam. 1965. Aspects of the Theory of Syntax. Cambridge: MIT-Press.
Clark, H. I. 1963. “Knowledge on Grounds: A Comment on Mr. Gettier’s Paper”. Analysis 24, 46-8.
Costa, Claudio. 2018. Philosophical Semantics: Reintegrating Theoretical Philosophy. Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing.
Costa, Claudio. 2014. Lines of Thought: Rethinking Philosophical Assumptions, Chap. 5, Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing. First published as “A Perspectival Definition of Knowledge”, in Ratio 23, 2010, 151-167.
Cottingham, J. 1984. Rationalism. Paladi/Granada.
Dancy, Jonathan. 1995. Introduction to Contemporary Epistemology. Oxford: Blackwell.
DeRose, Keith. 2018. The Appearance of Ignorance: Knowledge, Skepticism, and Context. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Dretske, Fred. 1981. Knowledge and the Flow of Information. Cambridge: MIT Press.
- 1970. “Epistemic Operators.” The Journal of Philosophy, 67: 1007-23.
- 1971. “Conclusive Reasons.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 49: 1-22.
De Rose, Keith., and Warfield, Ted., 1999. Skepticism: A Contemporary Reader. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Dennett, Daniel. 2018. From Bacteria to Bach and Back. W. W. Norton & Company.
Dennett, Daniel. 1984. Elbow Room: The Varieties of Free Will Worth Wanting. Cambridge: MIT Press.
DeRose, K. 2005. “The Ordinary Language Basis for Contextualism, and the New Invariantism”. The Philosophical Quarterly, 55, 172-98.
DeRose, Keith & Ted A. Warfield. 1999. Skepticism: A Contemporary Reader. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Devitt, M. 2010. “No Place for the A Priori”. In Putting Metaphysics First: Essays on Metaphysics and Epistemology, chap. 13. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Feldman, R. 2003. Epistemology. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Feldman, R. Earl Conee. 1985. “Philosophical Studies”, 48, 15-34.
Feldman, Richard. 1974. “An Alleged Defect in Gettier’s Counter-Examples”. The Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 52, pp. 68-9.
Fogelin, R. J. 1994. Pirrhonian Reflections on Knowledge and Justification. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gettier, E. L., 1963. “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?” Analysis 23; 121-3.
Ginet, Carl. 1975. Knowledge, Perception, and Memory. Dordrecht and Boston: Reidel Pub. Co.
Goldman, Alan H. 1988. Empirical Knowledge. Berkeley & Los Angeles: University of California Press.
Goldman, Alvin I., 1986. Epistemology and Cognition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Goldman, A. I., 1979. “What is Justified Belief?” In Justification and Knowledge, ed. George S. Pappas. Dordrecht: Reidel.
Goldman, A. I. 1976. “Discrimination and Perceptual Knowledge”. Journal of Philosophy 73: 771-91.
Goldman, A. I. 1967. “A Causal Theory of Knowing”. Journal of Philosophy 64: 357-72.
Goldman, A. I. & Matthew McGrath: Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Haack, Susan. 1993. Evidence and Inquiry. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Habermas, Jürgen. 1976. ‘Was heißt Universal Pragmatik?’ in K. O. Apel (ed.), Sprachpragmatik und Philosophie. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.
Harman, Gilbert. 1968. “Knowledge, Inference and Explanation”, American Philosophical Quarterly, 5, 164-173.
Hume, David. 1955 (1748). Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding. Ed. Charles W. Hendel, Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill.
Hume, David. 1739-1740. A Treatise of Human Nature.
Kant, Immanuel. 1929 (1787). Critique of Pure Reason. Translated by Norman Kemp Smith, London: Macmillan.
Lehrer, Keith. 1990. Theory of Knowledge. London: Routledge.
Lehrer, Keith & Thomas Paxon. 1969. “Knowledge: Undefeated Justified  True Belief”. The Journal of Philosophy 66, pp. 225-37.
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 1981 (1704). New Essays on Human Understanding. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Lewis, C. I. 1946. An Analysis of Knowledge and Evaluation. LaSalle, IL: Open Court.
Lewis, C. I. 1995 (1923). “A Pragmatic Conception of the A Priori”. Rep. in P. Lewis, David, 1996. Elusive Knowledge”. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74, pp. 549-567.
K. Moser, Arnold van der Nat, Human Knowledge: Classical and Contemporary Approaches. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Lockard, R. B., American Psychologist 1971, 26, 168-179.
Locke, John. 1975 (1689). An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Ed. P. H. Nidditch. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Martin, R. M. 2010. Epistemology. London: Oneworld.
Markie, Peter. 2017. “Rationalism vs. Empiricism”. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Edward N. Zalta.
Moser, Paul K. 1985. Empirical Justification. Dordrecht and Boston: Reidel.
Mellor, D. H. 1971. The Matter of Chance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Mittag, D. M. “Evidentialism”. The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy (internet resources).
Moore, G. E. 1953. “The Meaning of Real”, in his Some Main Problems of Philosophy. London: George Allen & Unwin.
Moore, G. E. 1939. “Proof of an External World”. Proceedings of the British Academy 25, pp. 273-300.
Nagel, Jennifer. 2014. Knowledge: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Nietzsche, Friedrich 2009 (1889). Twilight of the Idols: How to Philosophize with a Hammer. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Nozick, Robert 1981. Philosophical Explanations. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
O’Connor, D. J. and Brian Carr. 1984. Introduction to the Theory of Knowledge (Brighton, UK: The Harvester Press).
Pappineau, David. 2012. Philosophical Devices: Proofs, Probabilities, Possibilities, and Sets. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Plato. 1997. Plato: Complete Works, ed. John M. Cooper (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing).
Pollock, John L. 1987. Contemporary Theories of Knowledge. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Popper, Karl. 1994. The Myth of the Framework. London: Routledge.
Popper, Karl. 1974. Objective Knowledge. London: Oxford University Press.
Popper, Karl. 1963. Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge. London: Routledge.
Putnam, Hilary. 1984. Reason, Truth, and History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- 1975. ‘The Meaning of ‘Meaning’’, in Mind, Language, and Reality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Quine, W. V. O. 1969. From a Logical Point of View. 2nd ed. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Radford, Collin. 1966. “Knowledge – by Examples”. Analysis 27, 1-11.
Russell, Bertrand. 2016 (1912). The Problems of Philosophy. CreateSpace.
Russell, Bruce. 2017. “A Priori Justification and Epistemology”. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Edward N. Zalta.
Sacks, Oliver. 30 August 2010. “Prosopagnosia: The Science Behind Face Blindness”. The New Yorker.
Sosa, Ernest. 1980. “The Raft and the Pyramid: Coherence versus Foundations in the Theory of Knowledge”. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 5, 3-26.
Shope, R. K. 1983. The Analysis of Knowing: A Decade of Research. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Stanley, Jason. 2005. Knowledge and Practical Interest, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Strawson, P. F. 1974. Freedom and Resentment and other Essays. London: Methuen.
Stroud, Barry. 1984. The Significance of Philosophical Skepticism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Teichman, J., C. C. Evans. 1999. Philosophy: A Beginners Guide. Oxford: Willey-Blackwell.
Shor, Eran, Simchai, Dalit. 2009. “Incest Avoidance, the Incest Taboo, and Social Cohesion: Revisiting Westermark and the Case of the Israeli Kibbutzim”. American Journal of Sociology. 114 (6), 1803-1842.
Steup, M. Ernst Sosa. 2005. Contemporary Debates in Philosophy. Oxford: Willey Blackwell.
Williams, Michael. 2001. Problems of Knowledge: A Critical Introduction to Epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Williams, Michael. 1999. Groundless Belief. Princeton: Princeton University Press (first published 1977).
Williamson, Timothy. 2005. Contextualism, Subject-sensitive Invariantism and Knowledge of Knowledge.
Wuketits, Franz M.  2010. Evolutionary Epistemology. Albany: State University of New York Press.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1984. Über Gewissheit (On Certainty) Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1984. Philosophische Untersuchungen (Philosoph­ical Investigations). Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1958. The Blue and the Brown Books. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1984. Tractatus Logico Philosophicus. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.




[1] Hume used the word ‘object’; most authors use the word ‘event’. I prefer to use the word ‘thing’ in a wide sense for reasons that will be made clear later. 
[2] By reasons of simplicity of exposition, I am abbreviating what should be rather said: “The conjunctions of things found in the past must be approximately like the conjunctions of things to be found in the future”.
[3]  For reasons of simplicity of exposition, I am also using abbreviated language in PU(ii) and PU(iii). What I mean is rather “The conjunctions of things in the recent past must be like the conjunctions of things in the more recent past” (PU(ii)), and “The conjunctions of things in a next location in space must be like the conjunctions of things in the already known space” (PU(iii)).
[4] I always keep in mind a sufficiently unified system of reference. I need to say this because relativity theory has shown that present, past and future vary according to systems of reference moving at great speeds in relation to each other.
[5] What we could do is to search for a still more precise treatment. It seems plausible to think that the approximation of future and past tends to have a form of two opposed exponential curves that touch at the point called the present, etc.
[6] One could object that the principle of verification was long since been debunked, first by the positivists of the Vienna Circle and then by philosophers like W. V-O. Quine and even Saul Kripke. One can, however, maintain Wittgenstein’s earlier suggestion that the (cognitive) meaning of a statement is in some way given by the group of procedures we use to verify it, some more central, others not. (For a detailed rebuttal of straw man objections to semantic verificationism, see Costa 2018, Ch. V.)
[7] In On Certainty Wittgenstein gives several examples of how our imagination can betray us, making us see meaning where there is none.
[8] For an answer to Hilary Putnam’s argument against h3, see the next section.
[9] Note that I cannot interpret 1 as “I know that I have two adherently real hands”, since this cannot be true.