Quem sou eu

Minha foto
If you wish to be acquainted with my groundbreaking work in philosophy, take a look at this blogg. It is the biggest, the broadest, the deepest. It is so deep that I guess that the narrowed focus of your mind eyes will prevent you to see its full deepness.

domingo, 27 de julho de 2025

Claudio Costa: TEXTOS DE FILOSOFIA - PHILOSOPHICAL TEXTS

                   THIS "BLOG" WAS IDEALIZED TO MAKE MY WORK IN PHILOSOPHY MORE ACCESSIBLE. IT CONTAINS MORE THAN 100 WRITINGS, THOUGH USUALLY IN DRAFT FORMS, IN ENGLISH AND/OR PORTUGUESE. THE PAPERS WITH INTEREST FOR THE RESEARCHER WERE MARKED WITH #.

ESSE "BLOG" FOI IDEALIZADO COMO UMA MANEIRA DE TORNAR MEU "FABULOSO" TRABALHO FILOSÓFICO FACILMENTE ACESSÍVEL A PESSOAS LEGITIMAMENTE INTERESSADAS EM FILOSOFIA. ELE CONTÉM MAIS DE 100 ESCRITOS, EM GERAL ESBOÇOS, MUITOS DELES EM PORTUGUÊS. ALGUNS SÃO DIDÁTICOS, OUTROS NÃO. OS TRABALHOS DE INTERESSE PARA PESQUISADORES FORAM MARCADOS COM #



FROM MY CURRICULUM

I was born in Vila Seropedica, near to Rio de Janeiro, Brazil, 1954. After an intellectually boring medicine undergraduate study, I gained my MS in philosophy at the IFCS (Rio de Janeiro) and a Ph.D. in philosophy at the University of Konstanz (Germany). Since 1992, I have worked as a researcher and professor at the UFRN (Natal), secluded in the beautiful Northeast of Brazil, though always in contact with the international philosophical discussion through many grants taken at the universities of Konstanz, Munich, Berkeley, Oxford, Göteborg, and École Normale Supérieure (INS). 

Despite my usual focus on contemporary analytic philosophy, I disagree with mainstream philosophy's lack of comprehensiveness. 

The books I am not ashamed to have written are "The Philosophical Inquiry" (Lanham: UPA, 2002), which develops a thesis on the nature of philosophy, Lines of Thought: Rethinking Philosophical Assumptions" (Cambridge Scholars Publishing, 2014), and "Philosophical Semantics: Reintegrating Theoretical Philosophy" (Cambridge Scholars Publishing, 2018). The book from 2014 is a selection of essays (some of them, in my humble view, really relevant), while the long book from 2018 can be read as a comprehensive analysis of a cluster of concepts regarding philosophical methodology, the idea of meaning, verificationism, and truth, based on the investigations of philosophers of language from Frege to Wittgenstein. The last published book, "How Do Proper Names Really Work?" (De Gruyter 2023), aims to overthrow the old stalemate between the new and the old orthodoxy in the philosophy of language. I believe this book does not revolutionize the field only because its author does not have the proper status function in the community of ideas.

It is essential to say that I have social dyslexia (a light form of autism). Because of this, I have ergonomic limitations at the university where I work. This means almost no contact with the public world. This is good for intellectual independence; I can work diligently... but it makes divulging my ideas very difficult.


SOME BOOKS (ALGUNS LIVROS):



This book completely renews our theories of reference



 





















UNIVERSALYSING TROPES = A SIMPLE WAY

 principia.symposia@gmail.com

 

This is a draft

 

 

UNIVERSALIZING TROPES - A SIMPLE WAY

 

 

Summary:

Donald Williams suggested that universals can be understood as sums or sets of tropes under the assumption of a trope ontology. My goal in this article is to present a less problematic and more convincing approach to the issue. It consists of returning to the root of the problem, namely, the predicative problem of how we can say the same of many. This is undoubtedly the real problem, and my view is that trope theory does not require the resources of universals as sums or sets of tropes to address it. One example of how this kind of problem can be addressed without that resource was Berkeley’s solution to the problem of general ideas using particular ideas in a generally applicable manner. What I propose, in a nutshell, could be seen as the replacement the Berkeleyan imagistic ideas with tropes. All that is needed is to develop a universalizing ability, namely, the ability to follow a rule that enables us to identify precise similarities between tropes used as models and those directly or indirectly given to experience.

Key Words: trope theory, universals, ontology, Donald Williams.

My goal with this article is to propose a new solution to the problem of universals through the lens of trope theory. I claim that my solution is easier and more effective than Donald Williams’s troublesome solution, thereby considerably advancing the trope theory. In the first section, I explain the basic ideas of trope ontology, as initially introduced by Williams. In section two, I present his solution to the problem of universals employing tropes, showing its shortcomings. In Section Three, I present the original Socratic-Platonic problem that leads to the problem of universals, showing how it can divert us from the real issue. Section four presents my solution to the original problem, inspired by the nominalism of philosophers such as Ockham, Berkeley, and Hume. This solution bypasses the old hipostasizing problem of universals insofar as it shows it as a pseudoproblem. Section five sketches the application of the solution to complex tropes.

 

1. Introducing trope theory

In his classic article “The Alphabet of Being” (1953 I-II), Donald Williams introduced the theory of tropes through a suggestion as brilliant as it is simple. His fundamental metaphysical thesis was that:

 

Any possible world, and hence, of course, this one, is entirely constituted by its tropes, and their connections of location and similarity and any others that may be. (1953 I: 8)

 

This means that for Williams, tropes are the universe-building pebbles. But what are tropes? He defined them as abstract particulars because they can be abstracted from concrete particulars. His example was of lollipops: we can separate the red of a lollipop, its shape, its sweetness, its smoothness, its hardness, its weight... Although this definition is technically correct, a more helpful way to say the same is to define tropes as any spatiotemporally localizable properties. This contrasts sharply with the standard use of the property concept in the philosophical tradition, where it is understood as an abstract entity destituted of spatiotemporal localization.

   Williams’ understanding of the extent of the trope concept is made more evident by the following list that I take from his article:

 

Color, shape, surface, odor, red, size, triangularity... pain, love, sadness, pleasure, emotion, belief, serenity, perception, discrimination, intention, disposition, power, mental processes, sequences of thoughts... a smile, a sneeze... An election, a musical performance, a love affair, a moral decision, an act of contrition, a piece of impudence... the beauty of Mary, Mary being beautiful, the figure of a woman, her complexion, her digestion...

 

This list shows us that tropes can be simple properties (such as a red patch, a twinge of pain, or the whistle of a train) or compound ones (a mental process, a sneeze, or a love affair). They can be external (a smile, the figure of a woman), internal (sadness, serenity, pleasures, dispositions, thoughts), or mixed (an act of contrition, a piece of impudence). They can also be homogeneous (a violin solo) or heterogeneous (the act of contrition, Mary’s digestion).

   Considering that tropes are spatiotemporally localizable properties, it is pretty clear that even vague dependent empirical entities, such as the forces of nature, can also be regarded as tropes, since they are localizable properties, though in a more or less dispersed way. This can be said from the electromagnetism, the gravitation, the strong and the weak forces. Because electromagnetic forces can be separated from atoms in motion, gravity must be seen as the bending of the space-time in the vicinity of massive bodies, strong forces can be drawn from the interaction between quarks and gluons in the atomic nuclei, and weak forces can be separated fromthe interaction between subatomic particles in atoms.[1]

   For Williams, tropes contrast only with concrete particulars, such as, to use his examples, Mary, a church, and a nation. He analyzed concrete particulars as sets of concurrent or compresent tropes in the sense that their members are co-localized and co-temporal (1953: 8). They can be internally organized, like a particular human being or a particular chair, or quite disorganized, as in the case of a particular rock... Although concrete particulars are usually medium-sized dry objects, they can be, as individuals, as small as electrons and atoms, and as large as stars and galaxies.

   As a standard feature to all these concrete particulars, I would point to the rest mass. Rest mass can be seen as a dispositional trope, absent in tropes like color, form, weight, or a force of nature, but present in the set of compresent tropes that make any concrete particular, so that under such and such circumstances, it shows such and such a measurable reaction.

   Finally, although Williams does not mention it, it is worth noting here that we can apply here the Aristotelian criterion for the difference between properties and substance: tropes can be predicatively designated, while concrete particulars cannot.

   William’s metaphysical project of building a world of tropes might be demanding, but does not seem to be impossible.

 

2. Williams’ solution to the problem of universals

In addition to trying to solve the question of concrete particulars by resorting to tropes, Williams wanted to do the same with the question of universals. Here is how he introduced it:

 

Speaking again approximately, the set or sum of tropes precisely similar to a trope, say, that red, can, of course, be, or at least formally correspond to, the abstract universal or ‘essence’ which can be said to exemplify a definite sample of red. (1953 I: 9)

 

This convoluted definition can be presented more clearly: a universal (essence) is a set or sum of tropes that are precisely similar (Campbell 1981; sec. 6).  The universal of the color red, for example, is nothing more than the set or sum of tropes precisely similar (i.e., qualitatively identical) to a given trope of red. When I say that red is a color, what I mean is that the set of all tropes of red (the universal essence of red) is contained in the set of tropes of color (the universal essence of color).

   There are problems with Williams’ solution. The most discussed has been that of the infinite regress of tropes of precise similarity (for discussion, see Campbell 1990: 34-37). If the world is made up of its tropes, then it seems that the precise similarity is also a trope. In this case, the precise similarities between the tropes will need to be precisely similar, requiring a new class of precise similarities. However, the tropes of this new class of precise similarities will also need to be precisely similar, requiring a third class of precise similarities, and so on, so that the result is an infinite regress.

   There are several ways to address this objection. Campbell, for example, suggested that identity is an internal relationship between tropes that can only count as a pseudo-addition with no real ontological basis (1990: 37). I prefer not to harbor any prejudice against the thinness of any trope. I like to think that since precise similarity is a relation dependent on the existence of these tropes, it is itself a trope insofar as we tend to say it should be in some way where those tropes are, but surely not as something found on the other side of the universe or nowhere (that nothing exists nowhere is an axiom of trope theory). And the same could be said of precise identity between two precise identities. If these two are somehow localizable, then the precise similarity trope between these precise similarities should also be somehow localizable. The regress, in this case, exists, but it is not vicious because nothing forces us to go forward. It remembers the harmless regress we find when we argue that Plato required second-order ideas of ideas in the formulation of his doctrine of ideas, and that he needed third-order ideas of those second-order ideas to criticize his doctrine in the Parmenides. But this regression didn’t need to go further since it was unnecessary. Similarly, we can stop by saying that a class of precisely similar tropes demands the existence of tropes of precise similarity between its tropes, but that this does not compel us to appeal to a subsequent class of precise similarities between those precise similarities, since this would be devoid of any explanatory function.

   There are other difficulties with Williams’s solution. Here are some of them. We do not know whether the set of precisely similar tropes can be classified as a trope. Moreover, sets have sizes and can increase or decrease, which seems to make them different from universals. Moreover, universals do not appear to have any size, especially if they are seen as essences, or as concepts, as common sense suggests.

   The biggest problem, however, which in my judgment is fatal, is that sets of tropes that are precisely similar to each other are usually too large to fit in our heads. That is, in most cases, indeed in the vast majority of cases, the set of precisely similar tropes is cognitively inaccessible to us. Consider, for example, the set of precisely similar tropes of red: we can claim that it exists, of course, but not that any mind has ever met it. And if it is an essence, then that essence turns to be unknowable to us. It was suggested to me that they could be open sets. However, open sets seem to exist in our minds, not in nature. Also, how many members does this open set have? Can it be an empty set?

 

3. The problem of how we can say the same of many

It is essential to see that the so-called problem of universals arises from another problem: “How can we say the same of many?” or “How can we apply the same predicate to many different things? Here, we have the cognitive question of knowing how it is possible to apply the same general term to a multiplicity of things which are often very different. How is it possible, for example, to apply the general term ‘justice’ to say that Socrates was just, that N. Winton’s, noble action was just, or that the Finnish political system is just enough? The question is not only linguistic. It is also epistemic since it concerns the cognitive identification of unity in multiplicity.[2]

   The first philosophers to come across this question were Socrates and Plato. Socrates wondered about the definition of concepts expressed by general terms of philosophical interest, like justice, beauty, and courage. Plato found a possible answer in his famous doctrine of ideas. As he wrote: “I take it, we are in the habit of positing a single idea or form in the case of the various multiplicities to which we give the same name” (Republic 596a 6-8).

   As is well-known, the idea or form is unique and abstract in that it is non-spatiotemporal, immutable (eternal), and capable of definition; it belongs to an intelligible world that transcends the visible world by being ontologically independent. And as is also well-known, he suggested that by reference to the single idea or form, we can identify the various things in the visible world that contain imperfect copies of them (by mimesis), or that in some way share their being with that idea (by methéxis).

   What is important to notice is that Plato should be answering the question of how we can say the same of many, which can be resumed as the question of predication,[3] However, he moved from an epistemological-linguistic problem to an ontological-metaphysical solution.[4] As a result of this move, the traditional problem of universals arose. Since the idea or form is the universal, the problem of universals emerges as that of knowing “that which by its nature is predicated of a number of things” (Aristotle 1984: 17a 38). This means the problem of the ontological nature of something objective that, by itself, makes us capable of saying the same of many. For realist philosophers such as Plato and Aristotle (under one plausible interpretation of the latter), universals are abstract, immaterial entities, even if, in Aristotle’s case, they are generally dependent on the existence of the things constituting the visible world (Metaphysics:1034a 5-8).[5]

   Notwithstanding, there were not only realist philosophers who moved from the epistemological-linguistic problem to an ontological-metaphysical hypostazising solution. Some nominalist philosophers have followed a similar path. This was the case of Peter Abelard, from whom the general term has as reference the collection of things to which it applies (Abelard 1994; 34; Wolterstorff 1970; 173). And this is also the case of class nominalists for whom a general term must refer to its extension as the class of objects to which it refers (Armstrong 1978: ch. 4; 1989: ch. 1). Thus, a class nominalist might say that the class of all red objects must answer for the applicability of a general term like ‘red.’ And D. K. Lewis (1986: 50 ff.), a sophisticated class nominalist, would solve the problem of different general terms with the same denotation but different connotations by appealing to their application to the class of objects that encompasses all possible worlds since, in that case, these classes would no longer need to coincide...

  Now, the whole point of this digression is that it seems pretty plausible that some form of collection or class nominalism inspired Williams to propose his solution to the problem of universals as classes of tropes precisely similar to each other. What he made was to replace things, concrete particulars, with tropes as members of the class, which he treated as a kind of “ersatz-universal.”

   I call the solution to the problem of how we can say the same of many by resorting to universals, beginning with Plato, and ending with class nominalism, the “traditional solution.” And I tend to believe this solution was a mistake that compromised more than two thousand years of metaphysical research without substantial results, namely: the error of offering an unnecessary ontological-metaphysical (hypostazising) solution to a linguistic-epistemic problem. And I tend to think this move also infests class nominalism as a bet on a class as a kind of “ersatz-universal”. As Plato made this mistake in the beginning, it gave rise to a tradition of investigating universals so ingrained that its linguistic-epistemic origin was often forgotten, becomming a challenging work to dislodge it from the minds of philosophers.

   Not all philosophers, it is true, have fallen into this trap. William of Ockham suggested that all we need is to develop the mental capacity to recognize the right similarities in many different things (1995: 43-45), and to speak of universals is to speak of this capacity. And throught their particularism, Berkeley (1710: Intr.) and Hume (1740: I, I, VII) were also honorable exceptions. According to Berkeley’s immaterialism, as is well known, the whole world (except for the Spirits) is constituted of particular ideas of purely mental (and not Platonic) nature. The things of the so-called external world are nothing more than more intense and organized ideas that impose themselves on us (Berkeley 1710: I, sec. 30). One idea can be general in the sense that it applies to many different things. But for him, they are never abstract, which means that they never have the function of Platonic universals or anything other than their purely mental nature. As he wrote:

 

It seems that a word becomes general by being made the sign, not of a general abstract idea, but of several particular ideas, any one of them indifferently suggested to the mind (Berkeley 1710: Intr. Sec. 11)

 

That is: a general term is associated with mental ideas; for example, the general term triangle is related to images of several particular triangles, equiangles, rectangles, obtuse... On this basis, we are able, whenever we have access to a given triangle in the external world (that is, to an “external” idea of a triangle), to compare it with an idea of the ideas that we have associated with the general term, applying this term to the given triangle in the so-called external world. To explain this operation, Berkeley does not needed to resort to reyfied universals at any time. He only compared the idea given in the experience with ideas he has in mind that he associated with some general term. Then, when he perceived their similarity, he applied the same general term to the idea given in the experience. David Hume added to Berkeley’s proposal a number of diferent but approximated ideas a same general term (1740: 17).

   I can anticipate that my strategy will be structurally analogous to those of Berkeley and Hume, for what I wish to do here is essentially replace “idea” with “trope”. However, I will be free from the main criticism of Berkeley's solution to the problem of predication, which is that it is an imagistic solution and that many concepts do not require the formation of images or only require them secondarily.[6]  Since tropes need not be essentially imagistic, even if they must be somehow derived from sensory experience, my approach will not be open to this accusation.

   In what follows, I want to propose my solution to the problem of how we can say the same of many, inspired by Berkeley’s strategy. Although based on the theory of tropes, this solution does not need to answer the epistemological problem through an ontological solution. It will be an alternative move that dispenses the appeal to universals dealt with in the traditional answer.

 

4. Universalizing Skills

In conformity with the suggested line of thought, I propose we learn to say the same of many by gaining a skill. It is the ability to (i) associate a trope  with its corresponding general term; (ii) use this same trope (or any others that are precisely similar to it) as a model to compare with any trope that we are given to consideration, in order to be able to tell whether or not it has a precise similarity with the tropes used as a model. Once this skill is acquired, we can say the same of many without resorting to universals or classes of tropes as universals. We can call this skill a universalizing ability.

   I want to start with a straightforward example. Suppose Mary has taken a painting course and learned to identify the color ‘land of Sienna’. To this end, she had eye contact with many examples of this color, having learned to associate these examples with the color’s name and remember precisely this model color trope. Later, she takes a trip to Italy. There, she identified many buildings painted with the colors Land of Siena. All she needed to do to name the color of these buildings correctly is to have the memory of a particular trope and be able to identify new tropes precisely similar to it. She developed the ability to recognize the land of Siena trope. She learned to say the same of many regarding this general term. Obviously (to her luck), she does not need to resort to the immense set of land of Siena tropes that are precisely similar be able to use this general term predicatively. Maria’s universalizing ability concerning the land of Siena trope can be specified as the hability to identify any land of Siena trope that is given to her experience as being precisely similar to the model tropes she remembers to have seen as she learned the reference of the general term ‘land of Sienna’. We also say that Mary has learned to use the word ‘land of Siena,’ that she knows its meaning, that she mastered the concept or conceptual rule for the word’s application. Finally, the rule followed by Mary is also a trope, a complex trope that involves her memory of the land of Sienna trope and her identification of new tropes as precisely similar to the first one. 

   Two points are worth mentioning. The first is that memory isn’t a problem. It is like a copy we learn to trust as it works well enough to be considered trustworthy. Its trustworthiness is bestowed through interpersonal comparison between what has been identified and what has been reidentified. Moreover, it is importante to see that memory is an intermediary that is not even a necessary part of the procedure. The second point is that this ability is always, at least in principle, capable of generating an extensional class of tropes—but a class that has no relevance whatsoever in solving our problem of saying the same of many.

   We can highlight these points by resorting to a language game that shows the essence of the universalizing procedure. Imagine that a group of people with a particular mnemonic deficiency are in an exhibition of paintings, and are given a task: to identify the paintings in which the color of Sienna appears. There are 12 numbered paintings. Each person receives a tablet where the name ‘Land of Sienna’ is found next to a circle painted in the same color and twelve squares corresponding to each of the 12 paintings. All they need to do is mark the spaces corresponding to the paintings that feature the color of the land of Sienna. By taking the tables with their painted circles close to each painting, they can mark the spaces corresponding to the paintings in which a color precisely similar to the model is found. By doing this, people carry out a universalizing practice without resorting to long term memorized patterns. Finally, let’s say that the only frames with these color tropes are 2, 3, 8, and 12, and that this shows up as a result in the correctly marked tables. With this, they found, within a very narrow domain, a set of land of Sienna tropes that are precisely similar: the extensional set {2, 3, 8, 12}. It is clear that this set is of no use to us. It has no explanatory force concerning our ability to say the same of many.

   What the people in the example do is that they follow a rule that tells them to compare the color model trope of the tablet with the color tropes found in the paintings in search for precise similarities. The model trope that they see, as much as the model trope we usually actualize in our memory, serves as a criterion for applying the rule. The rule applies when people mark the square on the tablet corresponding to the trope where the land of Sienna trope is found. Since we say this person now has the concept of the land of Sienna, there is nothing more natural than considering this universalizing ability a conceptual rule or concept, which is nothing beyond the trope of a repeatable spatio-temporal procedure.

   Returning to our problem, we can now define the universalizing ability (the “universal” in a harmless sense) as follows:

 

Universalizing ability concerning a general term G by the epistemic agent S (Df.) = S’s ability to, having associated G with a model trope Tm, be able to use it as a criterial rule capable of allowing the identification of any given trope T as being or not being precisely similar to Tm.

 

The universalizing ability is the hability to follow a conceptual rule corresponding to what we ordinarily call a concept. Like everything else, this rule must require a replicable trope that will be found in every application of G, not as something metaphysically abstract in any realist sense. The memorized model trope Tm serves here as a criterion to be satisfied by some given trope T.

 

5. Universalization of complex tropes

So far, we have exemplified our universalizing ability relative to a trope that can be classified as perceptually simple: the color called ‘land of Sienna’. But what about more complex cases, such as the other tropes named by Williams, tropes such as those of triangularities, sneezing, smiles, sadness, a thought, and an act of contrition?

   I believe that anyone who has read the constructive particularist procedures of John Locke would find the achievement of the above described universalizing ability also applicable to complex tropes (1979: Book II). Locke started with imagistic ideas and combined them to form more and more complex and diversified ones. The difference is that here, we do not start with ideas or qualities, as Locke did. We start with simple tropes (that include his ideas and qualities), combining them to form more complex and diverse tropes that may appear to recur to abstract universals in the independence of empirical foundation, since they cannot be easily traced to their origins. But we use their memory as a criterion for identifying precisely similar tropes that are precisely similar to them, and in doing so we are applying the same universalizing skill exemplified above.

   In what follows, I will analyze a few complex tropes to demonstrate that they can be viewed as spatiotemporally localizable particulars without any abstract quality in the realistic (Platonic-Aristotelian) sense. To do so, it is necessary to define or decompose these tropes analytically as far as we can, showing that although they are not as directly and immediately identifiable as in the case of the trope of the land of Sienna, they are composed from tropes that can be found in sense-experience or derived from it. The goal is to make it plausible that the universalizing ability acquired in the cases of more complex tropes does not differ essentially from the intuitive case of a simple trope like ‘land of Sienna’.

   Let’s start with the straightforward case of the complex external trope of sneezing. It can be assumed that our ability to use general terms is acquired interpersonally, through both positive and negative examples (Tugendhat 1976, lecture 11). Thus, we usually learn the concept of sneezing by observing that adults give this name to the act of sneezing, whether it is ours or someone else’s, so that we are praised when we get it right, and we are corrected when we make a mistake. In this way, we acquire the universalizing ability to identify sneezes, which are themselves dispositional tropes. This is also about learning the concept (the tropical rule of conceptual application) based on our memories of sneeze tropes. As this rule is tacitly understood, we do not generally know how to verbalize it. But dictionaries help us, defining sneezing as “an involuntary movement of the airways to expel any foreign substance from the body.” This definition makes explicit what we mean by naming the complex sneeze trope; it works as a criterion for the application of the criterial conceptual rule, as much as the land of Sienna. To have the concept of sneezing is to have a dispositional procedure or rule understood as a dispositional trope that enables us to identify tropes that satisfy the definition. Since this disposition is a trope, it should not be confused with the tropes it is made to identify.

   Let us now look at the relatively simple trope of triangularity, also recalled by Williams. Here, learning is also tacitly done through interpersonal examples. We are presented with equiangular triangles, acute, obtuse, rectangles... until we learn not an abstract triangle typical to all of them (as Berkeley famously accused Locke to have suggested), but to vary the internal angles of a model triangle trope, so that we can form the corresponding images of triangles given in the experience. By doing this, we have already learned a tacit definition of a triangle, which can be explicitly formulated as “A triangle = a three-sided polygon.” Such a definition decomposes the internal tropes of the triangle into those of a three-sided polygon. (We can compare our use of the definition with a machine in with which by varying the input we can get a diferente output, namely, a diferent triangle, which shows that we do not need any abstract idea of a triangle in order to recognize triangles.)

   Now, consider Williams’ internal trope of sadness: all we need to universalize is to be able to identify instances of sorrow that are precisely similar to tropes of sadness that we have already learned to identify by different means in other people and ourselves. Moreover, we use these memorized tropes as models for identifying further cases of sorrow. Dictionaries characterize this trope as “a feeling of despondency, melancholy, unhappiness, and hopelessness.”

   Let us now examine the mixed and complex trope of the act of contrition mentioned by Williams. As I was informed, it is a Christian prayer that asks for repentance for sins and mercy from God. All we need to universalize are examples of acts of contrition in memory, or, in my case, explicit information about this trope, which allows us to imagine it and identify precisely similar cases.

   I now want to consider two examples that Williams did not mention of countable tropes. They differ from the previous ones since they are concerned with the essence of concrete particulars. A first example is that of an artifact name: the trope of chair (from ‘to be a chair’). This is a complex external trope. We all know what a chair is, but we have difficulties defining it since we have learned the conceptual rule for the identification of chairs in a tacit or implicit way. However, we can give the following reasonable definition of a chair:

 

Chair trope (Df.): a non-vehicular seat with a backrest made for one person to sit at a time.

 

It would not be a chair but a simple bench if it had no backrest. It cannot be found in vehicles such as cars, planes, or trains because, in that case, they will be called seats. They must be made so that only one person can sit on them each time; otherwise, they would be sofas. Even if a chair were teletransported to a planet where people were very slim, and several of them could sit in the same chair, it would not turn into a sofa, since as an artifact it was made for only one person to sit on at a time. A chair that has not been made as an artifact, say, a chair carved into the rock, is only a metaphorical chair, no less than a toy chair.

   We cannot directly perceive a chair trope. It is not written on a chair that it should be a bench with a backrest, that it is made for one person to sit at a time, or that it may have been the work of a carpenter. But we can build all this conjoining perceptible tropes in space and time.

   That is why it took a good number of experiences of positive and negative examples so that we could gradually tacitly learn the complex trope, linguistically expressed in the definition of a chair. Afterward, keeping in mind the external, complex, and articulated trope that we associate with the word chair, we can identify precisely similar tropes of “chair”, such as those that exist when we encounter table chairs, wheelchairs, beach chairs, electric chairs, thrones... Of course, the dispositional conceptual rule used to identify chair tropes cannot be reduced to something we can have a mental image of. Neither tropes nor the tropical procedures of universalization force us to a purely imagistic conception of reality, once the relations among images established by the conceptual rule expressed above cannot be reduced to images alone.

   Someone may now ask a challenging question: How can I distinguish the trope of “chairness” from the concrete particular that is a specific chair? After all, this trope is a combination of spatiotemporally locatable tropes present, and where a chair is found, one will also find a complex trope of this chair. The answer lies in the spatio-temporal location of the object, which will always be distinctive. However, insofar as we can identify a particular chair apart from its spatiotemporal location, the answer is that a concrete particular is constituted by many other tropes besides those that definitionally constitute it. These accidental tropes do not define it, but help us identify the concrete particular. For example, the chair I’m sitting on now has soft upholstery. It is made of plastic and wood, faded yellow and old, and was bought in a second-hand furniture store. These are not elements of the trope of the chair I sit in, but of this concrete particular. Hence, the concrete particular must be a conjunction of present tropes that extrapolate its definitional trope. This answer can also be applied to other countable names of “essences” like the one in the following example.

   Let us consider, finally, a much-talked-about trope of the countable concept of natural species: that of the human being, traditionally defined by the Greeks as a rational animal but characterized today in dictionaries as “a bipedal primate endowed with reason, culture, and advanced language.” Of course, this characterization of the complex trope cannot be directly perceived in our immediate sensory experience of other human beings. However, it was also learned tacitly through many positive and negative examples, even if we are unable to articulate the explicit dictionary definition. Indeed, I have already seen many of these bipedal primates and learned to recognize myself in the mirror as one of them. I know they can have a certain degree of reason, culture, and advanced language. It was through this public learning arising from extraordinarily complex spatio-temporal articulations of simple imagistic perceptual tropes that I gradually learned what human beings are and that I became able to use my knowledge of the complex trope associated with the general term ‘human being’ as a rule to recognize, at least aspectually, precisely similar trope articulations in the cases of the most diverse beings recognizable as humans. I do not need to form images of this trope, since, as a whole, it is unimaginable. However, with the conceptual rule, I can produce associated images and their combinations. We would say that the conceptual rule expressed by the word ‘man’ is a trope allowing us to associate the memory of an extraordinarily complex articulation of tropes with any precisely similar articulation of tropes we can find in the external world.

 

4. Conclusion

By the given arguments added to the Analyse of some few examples, I hope to have shown that constructing our predicative capacity as an hability of following a linguistic rule enabling us to identify complex tropes in the empirical world through their implicitly known definitions or characterizations abstracted as model-tropes is in principle feasible and, from the viewpoint of trope theory, a more promising endeavor than Williams resource of classes or sums of tropes as reifying “ersatz-universals”.

 

 

References:

Abelard, Peter. From the “glosses on Porphyry” in his logica ‘ingredientbus’. Cf. Valdetônio Pereira de Alencar, “Problemas com o nominalismo de classe”, in Griot, v. 13, 2016, p. 375.

Aristotle (1984): De Interpretatione. The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation. Book I, Ed. Jonathan Barnes, Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Armstrong, D. M. (1989): Universals. Boulder: Westview Press.

Armstrong, D. M. (1978): Universals and Scientific Realism. vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Berkeley, George (1973 (1710)): The Principles of Human Knowledge. In Philosophical Works Including the Works on Vision ed. by M. R, Ayers, London: Everyman.

Campbell, Keith (1990): Abstract Particulars. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

Campbell, Keith (1981): “The Metaphysic of Abstract Particulars,” in P French, T. E. Uehling and H. Wettstein (eds.), Midwest Studies in Philosophy 6 (1): 477-488.

Hume, David (1978 (1740)): A Treatise of Human Nature. Edited by L. A. Selby-Bigge, Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Kung, Guido (1967): Ontology and the Logistic Analysis of Language Dordrecht: Reidel.

Lewis, D. K. (1986): On the Plurality of the Words. Oxford: Blackwell.

Locke, John (1979): An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Ed. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press).

Maurin, Anna-Sofia (2007): Infinite Regress: Virtue or Vice? In Hommage a Vlodek (Lund University).

Ockham, Wilhelm. Philosophical Writings: A Selection (Hacket Publishing 1990),

Plato (1961): The Republic. In The Collected Dialogues of Plato. Edited by Edith Hamilton and Huntington Cairns. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Tugendhat, Ernst (1976). Vorlesungen zur Einführung in die sprachanalytische Philosophie. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp Verlag.

Williams, D. C. (1953a) “On the Elements of Being I.” Review of Metaphysics, 7(1) 3-18,

Williams, D. C. (1953b) “On the Elements of Being II.” Review of Metaphysics 7(1) 171-92.

 

 



[1] Keith Campbell (1990: 151-155) has called them quasi-tropes, but conceding the given account it does not seem that these forces need be less than tropes.

[2] There was also for Plato the point of justifying the unchangeability of the objects of knowledge. However, this is not properly the problem of universals, but a further reason for his doctrine.

[3] Note that the formulation I propose of “how can we say the same of many?” is not precisely the same as Plato’s question of “how can we say the same over many?”, which already hints at the existence of universals and is loaded with interpretative problems.

[4] It is true that Plato’s problem was also that of finding a stable object of knowledge, which cannot be found in the changeable sensible world. But this problem can be set apart of our present discussion.

[5] See Metaphysics 1034a 5-9. However, Aristotle also argues, inconsistently, that forms cannot be universal. Metaphysics, sec. 13 of book Z.

[6] In this broad sense, ‘imagistic’ means not only what can be seen, but also what can be heard or tasted, with which the English empiricists surely would agree.