Philosophy as Proto-Science
Where philosophy was, there science shall
be.
—Robert Nozick
My aim in this paper is to examine the structural and
dynamic relationships between philosophy and science, particularly the view
that philosophy anticipates and leads to science. My investigation sheds light
on the nature of both philosophy and science.
Greek Origins of Occidental Philosophy as a Case
Study
When seeking an explanation for the nature of
philosophy, a good starting point is to inquire as to its origins. As we know,
Occidental philosophy originated in Ancient Greece as an alternative to the mythological
and religious answers that were then commonly given to relevant but unapproachable
questions. Instead of accepting the usual explanations of the foundations and
origins of reality based on the anthropomorphic projections of mythology, early
Greek philosophers decided that the world could also be explained
speculatively. They thus appealed to impersonal (or nearly impersonal) principles,
for example, water (Thales), air (Anaximenes), fire (Heraclitus), infinity
(Anaximander) and being (Parmenides), or life forces like love and hate or
strife (Empedocles).[1]
Questions that could help us to understand the nature of philosophy are in this
case: What was the reason for this change in explanatory approach? What was the
nature of this change?
A good explanation for the shift from
mythological to philosophical thought has been proposed by historians of
philosophy. According to W. K. C. Guthrie,[2] for example, Greek
thinkers, having borrowed scientific knowledge (astronomical, physical,
geometrical, arithmetical, etc.) from other cultures, were the first to
consider such knowledge in abstraction from their practical
applications, namely, in the form of theoretical generalizations.
We find the best example of this outlook in Euclid’s Elements, with its
axiomatic-deductive method of proving theorems. It was this awareness of the
explanatory power of theoretical generalizations that presumably suggested to
early Greek thinkers the possibility that questions once answered with the
anthropomorphic metaphors of mythology and religion could instead be addressed
in terms of abstract speculative generalizations, that is, in philosophical
terms.
Although persuasive, this last explanation
remains incomplete. True, the Greeks were the first to consider scientific
generalizations apart from their applications. They were the first to axiomatize
geometry, and they were able to make physical generalizations and astronomical
inferences (such as, respectively, Archimedes’ measurement of specific gravity
and Aristarchus’ heliocentric hypothesis). Nevertheless, to explain the rise of
philosophical thought it is not enough to consider the emergence of explicit
generalizations independently of their practical applications, for this is not
a privilege of scientific explanation. Common-sense explanations, for example,
are also based on empirical generalizations, like those expressed by sentences
such as, ‘The sun rises everyday’, ‘Water quenches thirst’, ‘Fire burns’...,
which are not scientific conclusions, but have always been accepted as
obviously true. Moreover, people have certainly always been able to think about
such commonplace generalizations apart from practical concerns.
A more complete explanation for the
emergence of philosophy in ancient Greece seems to me to be the following. When
they succeeded in creating abstract scientific knowledge, Greek thinkers, from
Thales to Aristotle, also achieved an intuitive understanding of the nature of
the generalizations and explanations of science, both of the formal sciences
(geometrical theorems) and the empirical ones (physical and astronomical
laws). While they did not have an explicit philosophy of science from the start
(the first steps in this direction were taken later by Aristotle in his Organon,
mainly in the Posterior Analytics), they certainly did have an idea
of the kind of hypothetical, predictive and explanatory procedures that are in
a broad way shared by the sciences in general – both empirical and formal.
Thus, they already had what we could call an idea of science.
Now, it seems that Greek philosophy arose from the speculative application of
this idea of science to questions that earlier were approached exclusively by
means of religion and mythology, like the question of the ultimate nature of
the world and of our place in it. Equipped with this new notion, early Greek
philosophers attempted to proceed rationally, first by seeking to establish
true generalizations based on certain kinds of data (empirical or
formal), and then by trying to explain certain kinds of facts, whatever their
nature, by applying these generalizations.[3] The first Greek
philosophers pursued this aim by introducing vague principles (like water, air,
infinity, being) or forces (like heat and cold, love and strife). These might
be interpreted as the first attempts to replace explanations relying on the
actions and intentions of divinities with explanations based on the
constitutive elements of the real world and the impersonal laws regulating
their transformations, often hovering midway between the two kinds of
explanation.[4] It was by no means
accidental that Thales, the first philosopher of the Occidental tradition, was
also a natural scientist and a competent astronomer who once predicted a solar
eclipse.[5]
Philosophy as Conjectural Inquiry Lacking Consensual
Foundations
If we accept it as given that Occidental philosophy
developed through the speculative application of the idea of science to
questions inherited from mythology and religion, how can we then distinguish
the activities of philosophers from those of scientists? Despite some
suggestions to the contrary, there seem to be considerable differences between
them.[6] The answer to this
question brings us to what I regard as a central insight into the nature of
philosophy. Even if philosophical methods generally resemble the practices of
scientific inquiry, there is a fundamental difference between them, namely,
that philosophical explanations remain merely conjectural and, to
this extent, speculative.[7]
But what do the words ‘conjectural’ and
‘speculative’ mean when we say that philosophical investigation remains
conjectural or speculative? One answer is that an investigation is conjectural
if it produces only hypothetical results, and that this is the
case when there is no possibility of consensual agreement about the truth of
these results. Indeed, while it is rather easy to reach consensual
agreement on results in the sciences, this kind of consensus is impossible in
the murky waters of philosophical inquiry. Consider the difference: The Greek
scientist Archimedes explained how levers work by precisely formulating the law
of the lever, and his explanation could be empirically verified and agreed on
by everyone. In contrast, the pre-Socratic philosopher Empedocles proposed to
explain the creation and destruction of things in the world through the action
of the forces of love (eros) and strife (neíkos) on the four
elements (water, air, earth and fire), which was nothing more than vague,
obscure speculation. He developed this theory in a mode and domain of inquiry
where thinkers were unable to find a viable path to consensual agreement.
The conjectural character of philosophical
thought – as the result of a lack of consensual agreement on fundamental
matters – reveals itself to be a necessary property able to explain its
typically argumentative and aporetic character. For when thinking
cannot be other than conjectural, there is no alternative except to embark on
hypothetical reasoning: We begin by accepting certain non-consensual
assumptions and then apply our best knowledge and skills in order to find all
their implications. Then we (usually other philosophers do this) change the
assumptions and proceed in a similar way. We subsequently try to critically
compare the different results and the procedures that lead to them, in a
process that can be endlessly repeated. In this way, philosophers are always
beginning: they are always pondering new ideas in ways that usually generate
aporetic argumentative discussion.
The conjectural character of philosophical
inquiry also suggests an explanation for the lack of progress in philosophy:
since philosophers cannot achieve agreement on the truth of their ideas,
inter-theoretical comparisons must remain inconclusive. Thus, to give an
example, scientists would generally agree that Einstein’s relativistic
mechanics is superior to Newtonian mechanics, since the explanatory power of
the former is greater – this is a matter of scientific conclusions. On the
other hand, philosophers have remained divided on alternative explanations of
many important issues. Consider, for example, the disputes over the problem of
universals, the mind-body problem, the free-will problem…).
Still, why can’t we achieve consensual
agreement on the results of the philosophical endeavour? The answer is that
consensual agreement about the results of an investigation is only possible
when there is sufficient agreement about the main presuppositions underlying
the investigation. Previous agreement on these matters is always absent
from philosophical inquiry. Philosophy lacks:
(i) agreement about the adequacy of its
data, general principles and even problems (philosophical ‘data’ and
principles are uncertain, and there are philosophical questions, we suspect, which
are pseudo-problems resulting from linguistic-conceptual confusion);
And it also lacks:
(ii) agreement on the adequacy of its
methodological procedures for evaluating the truth of answers proposed for
philosophical questions (an argument or a set of arguments can appear
conclusive to one philosopher, but unpersuasive to another).
In opposition to this, conditions (i) and (ii)
are always sufficiently satisfied in the case of scientific research.
Scientific problems and procedures are relatively uncontroversial, and the
correct solutions, when finally found, can be publicly verified, if not with
certainty, with a high degree of probability. Indeed, where fundamental
preconditions like these cannot be satisfied, there is no way to achieve
consensual agreement concerning the truth (or probable truth) of the
conclusions, which means that we cannot escape the aporetic discussions typical
of philosophy.
Philosophy as Proto-Science
The foregoing discussion suggests that by
investigating the similarities and contrasts between philosophy and science, we
will be better able to explain some central features of philosophical inquiry.
Moreover, they invite us to ask if our present philosophical inquiries will
someday be absorbed into science when they achieve a degree of maturity that
allows practitioners to reach consensual conclusions. In other words: Could
philosophy be seen as a conjectural inquiry anticipating science – a proto-science?
Could all philosophical inquiry be seen in this way?
We are not in the position to assert this.
But an affirmative answer to this question is suggested by the historical fact
that most of the sciences grew out of philosophical inquiry. Consider a few
examples from several different scientific fields:
A. According to Karl Popper, the now accepted
astronomical understanding that the Earth is a large, round body moving in
empty space, impelled by inertial and gravitational forces, was already
anticipated by Anaximander (610-546/5 BC). This Greek philosopher proposed that
the Earth was a stationary cylinder, not held in place by anything else, but
floating unsupported in space because it is equally distant from everything in
the universe, and it is impossible for it to move simultaneously in opposite
directions.[8]
B. The scientific investigation of subatomic
particles by contemporary physics has its forerunner in the speculative
hypothesis of the atomistic philosophers, from Democritus to Epicurus, that
visible things are formed by the aggregation of extended invisible (because
extremely small) but physically indivisible particles.
C. Biological theories of evolution seem to
be dimly anticipated by Anaximander’s insight that since man is helpless as a
child he would have perished in primeval times if he were not descended from
creatures very much like wild animals…
D. The Platonic theory of the tripartite soul
has its modern counterpart in Freud’s structural theory of mind, which divides
the mind into the I (ich), the it (es) and the over-I
(über-ich) (commonly referred to as ego, id and super-ego).
It is true that psychoanalysis strongly resembles philosophy, insofar as its
practitioners are still unable to reach consensual agreement on many issues,
but it had in Freud’s hands a relatively controlled method used as a form of
investigation.
E. Wittgenstein’s therapeutic conception of
language as a nebula of language games working as unities of meaning
anticipated the much more systematic (and narrower) theories of speech acts of
J. L. Austin and J. R. Searle, which nowadays belongs more to linguistics than
to philosophy.
These are only a few examples, and the developmental
process is continuing. Many believe, for example, that once we really
understand how the brain works, many of the riddles of our present philosophy
of mind will yield to consensual (and in this sense scientific) solutions. All
these facts lead us to ask whether science might not someday replace the
remaining central philosophical fields, such as epistemology, metaphysics and
ethics.
Nevertheless, there are philosophers who
resist the notion of philosophy as proto-science. Echoing Wittgenstein, Anthony
Kenny holds that philosophy, unlike science, deals with knowledge as a whole,
since it aims to organize the already known, providing an overview of
our knowledge. This kind of comprehensiveness, he argues, is absent in
the particular sciences. Consequently, at least central areas of philosophy
such as metaphysics, epistemology, the theory of meaning and ethics will
forever remain philosophical.[9]
Nonetheless, some overview and some degree
of comprehensiveness can also be achieved by scientific inquiry. Why could a
wider overview not be scientific? I suspect that the main reason for the
resistance lies less in the nature of things than in outdated positions on the
nature of science that are still uncritically accepted by many philosophers. Indeed,
these opinions, which have their roots in the philosophy of natural science
developed by the positivists – and also in the main reactions against them –,
are often too restrictive to assure that our central
philosophical interests will receive their deserved place in some future
scientific inquiry. If applied, they would be impoverishing, destroying
philosophy in its kern.
Consider, for example, Popper’s conception
of science as an inquiry that aims to construct theories that can resist
falsification by decisive experiments.[10] This view is too
restrictive, for it seems to exclude the theory of biological evolution from
science, since the former is not decisively falsifiable: How would we conceive
of an experiment capable of falsifying a hypothesis about an evolutionary
process that occurred in the distant past? Given this problem, how could we
ever apply a standard as restrictive as falsifiability (which arguably may be
applicable to physics) to the central subject areas of philosophical inquiry,
such as epistemology, metaphysics and ethics, other than in a crassly reductive
or even eliminative way?
Indeed, if we accept such a view of
science, our attempt to conceive of philosophy as proto-science would have to
end here. The reason for this pessimistic conclusion is that when our view of
the nature of science is inspired by the investigation of a well-established
particular science like physics, we are led almost perforce to reductive
generalizations about the character of still unknown areas of science. What we
are looking for is a concept of science so general and inclusive that any new investigation
deserving the name of science that might chance to emerge could satisfy it, for
it is credible to imagine that this would be precisely the concept of science
that could be properly contrasted with that of philosophy.
The Right Contrasting View of Science
To arrive at this more balanced view of science, I
propose that we should not adopt a model settled on by some already
established science, but rather should rely on scientifically informed common
sense. We must begin with questions such as: What does the scientific community
as a whole understand as ‘science’? How would scientists recognize any new
theory or field of investigation as belonging to science? When considering
these questions, the obvious answer that occurred to me was that science should
be systematically contrasted with philosophy in the sense that science is not
conjectural: It achieves consensual agreement on its results because it has
already achieved consensual agreement concerning basic issues such as data,
general principles and methodological procedures.
Searching in the literature, I found that
such a balanced view of science was already suggested by John Ziman, who
understood science in general as ‘consensualizable public knowledge’, that is,
as any kind of knowledge susceptible to consensual agreement about its truths.[11] According to this
perspective, science is essentially constituted by generalizations that are –
or at least are able to be – consensually accepted as true by the members of a
scientific community.[12]
Ziman’s notion of science is in complete
accord with the picture most informed laymen and scientists have of science.
When we talk about the progress of science, we are thinking of the acquisition
of new knowledge that the community of specialists can or could evaluate with
certainty and precision. This view of science is also sufficiently general and
flexible to include everything we usually accept as belonging to the
sciences, both the empirical and the formal. Moreover, placing the concept of
consensual agreement at the centre of attention, this view of science seems to
provide the ideal contrast between philosophy and science, since, as we have
seen, the first is an inquiry identifiable by a lack of possible
consensual agreement concerning its results. Accordingly, even if philosophy,
as Kenny thought, should be a comprehensive inquiry aiming to achieve an
overview, it could also be proto-scientific, insofar as we cannot rule out in
advance the possibility that over time philosophical theories could become a
sort of consensualizable and comprehensive public knowledge.
However, isn’t the definition of science as
‘consensualizable public knowledge’ too inclusive? It might seem
to be, because there are ideological circumstances in which ‘consensus’ is
imposed from above, excluding the possibility of critical evaluation. Notorious
examples of this are the roles played by political ideologies in defining
legitimate science in Nazi Germany (excluding non-Aryan science) and the Soviet
Union (excluding non-Marxist biology) and the religious ideology of the
Catholic Church that established Geocentrism (and condemned Galileu as
heretical). Yet, in accord with the above characterization, such ideological
impositions do seem to pertain to science, since a scientific community
of ideas has consensually accepted them. Thus, as presented, the proposed
characterization of science seems incapable of distinguishing science from an
ideological by-product.
Nonetheless, we can regard this difficulty
as only apparent, if we distinguish between authentic and inauthentic
consensus, specifying what we understand as a community of ideas that is able
to produce science in a way that excludes inauthentic consensus. Keeping the
contrast with philosophy in mind, I suggest we call a community able to warrant
authentic consensus a critical community of ideas, understanding it as a
community that satisfies some constitutive conditions
approximating those specified by Jürgen Habermas for what he calls an ideal
speech situation (ideale Sprachsituation).[13] This means that we must
define a critical community of ideas as something that satisfies constitutive
conditions warranting the claim to authentic consensus. Without trying to be
either systematic or exhaustive, I propose that we can generally characterize
the main constitutive conditions for a critical community of
ideas as requiring:
(a) Commitment to seeking
truth: The members of the community should seek to find truth
throughout the entire process of inquiry and evaluation of ideas.
(b) Freedom of discussion:
There must be an equal opportunity for free critical discussion among the
members of the community of ideas; they should not be subject to any
intellectual constraints, except those of the best arguments.
(c) Full access to
information: All members of the community must have full access to
information and equal chances for the evaluation and exchange of ideas.
(d) Shared competence:
All members must have suitable training in order to be able to make
adequate evaluations regarding their fields of research.
Indeed, Nazi Germany’s Aryan science and the Soviet
Union’s Marxist biology only prevailed because their scientific communities did
not satisfy such conditions. A truly scientific consensus can only be produced
by sufficiently satisfying constitutive conditions like these, which make
possible free and rational evaluations of the results of scientific
investigation. When we evaluate reports of a new scientific discovery, we
always assume at least that the scientific community has satisfied the
conditions of commitment to seeking truth, free discussion, full access to
information, and shared competence, if not in full, at least to a sufficient
degree.
Another important objection that critics
could make against such a consensus-based view of science is that it would be
too dependent on social consensus, compromising its objectivity. It seems at
first glance that science can be whatever the critical community of ideas
decides to call science, arbitrarily disregarding objective criteria. However,
this is not how science is defined in practice. For the critical community of
ideas aims at achieving a consensus about truth, and as a
matter of fact it is unable to achieve this aim in arbitrary ways like
consulting crystal balls and similar superstitious practices. It is simply a
matter of fact that a critical community of ideas must fulfil the appropriate
objectivity conditions for a chosen epistemic domain if its aim is to achieve
consensus about truth. In other words: Experience has shown that no community
of ideas ever achieves an authentic consensus about truth unless it
first meets some appropriate conditions for objective evaluative consensus.
Indeed, without attempting to be either systematic or exhaustive, we can show
that this is the case by making a list of conditions that must be sufficiently
satisfied by any critical community of ideas able to reach an objective
consensus about how to achieve truth. These conditions are what we could call conditions
of scientific objectivity. Indeed, in order to achieve objective consensus
there must at least be previous agreement about:
(i) what should be counted
as the (empirical or formal) basic data and/or general
principles of the epistemic domain to which certain scientific theories
should be applied;
(ii) what can be accepted as
adequately formulated questions to be asked concerning the epistemic
domain (theories must answer meaningful questions);
(iii) what can be accepted
as an adequately constructed theory in the epistemic domain
(i.e., adequate in its internal, as well as in its external coherence
within a wider conceptual framework);
(iv) what can be accepted as
the procedures of truth-evaluation in a theory’s
epistemic domain (which should involve some kind of correspondence
between a theory and the facts the theory is meant to explain, together with the
accepted forms of verification procedures for finding this
correspondence, etc.).
Such conditions of scientific objectivity are
different to each scientific field. But they must be satisfied in order to
assure the factual truth of scientific work, and they coincide in many ways
with the kinds of things that philosophers of science often investigate in
depth with regard to their preferred scientific field. The difference is that
these philosophers have too often considered only such conditions and their
particularized ramifications, abstracting the social role of the critical
community of ideas. On the contrary, we regard the satisfaction of such
conditions only as an indispensable prerequisite for the successful scientific functioning
of a critical community of ideas. As already noted, even if these conditions
are not met a priori, the need for their satisfaction in order to
achieve consensus on truth is an inescapable matter of fact, learned through
experience by any community of ideas effectively committed to the achievement
of truth.
With the aid of these notions, we can
improve Ziman’s general characterization of science as ‘consensualizable public
knowledge’. Here is our understanding of science:
SCIENCE = a body of non-trivial
generalizations reached by the members of a critical community of ideas (the
community of scientists), these generalizations (sometimes seen as scientific
laws) being (or being able to be) consensually held as true by this community.
This is a better understanding of science. It is
better in the sense that it is unbiased, according sufficiently with the view
of science that everyone, from scientists to the educated public, generally
holds. And it is also better, because it cannot be seen as reductionist or
positivist: Any discipline that well-informed, objective evaluators deem a
science should be compatible with this characterization, for the first
requirement of the scientific enterprise is the possibility of agreement on the
truth-searching conditions of non-trivial generalizations shared by the members
of a critical community of scientists.
Right View of Philosophy Contrasted with Science
The above-outlined consensualist-but-objectivist view
of science enables us to establish the appropriate relation between science and
philosophy. We can oppose the consensualizable public inquiry of science with
the non-consensualizable conjectural inquiry of philosophy. In order to achieve
this, we can characterize philosophy as follows:
PHILOSOPHY = a conjectural body of
non-trivial generalizations arrived at by the members of a critical community
of ideas (the community of philosophers), without this community being able to
reach any consensual agreement on the truth of these generalizations.
In accord with this characterization, we can regard
any conjectural inquiry in any domain of thought where it is impossible to
achieve a consensual body of truths to be of a philosophical nature. Its
philosophical nature results from its failure to satisfy the truth-searching
conditions that can make consensual agreement in the critical community of
ideas possible. In short: philosophy lacks (i) agreement about its basic data
and/or principles, (ii) agreement about the right questions to pose, (iii)
agreement about the right form of its theories, and (iv) agreement about the
right procedures for its truth-evaluation.
Indeed, in those difficult domains where
science, understood as ‘consensualizable public knowledge’, clearly remains
impossible, only the conjectural inquiry of philosophy is available. In this
way, we can explain why philosophy, in conformity with the etymology of the
word, is the love (philo) of knowledge or wisdom (sophia)
and not the attainment of knowledge (scientia). In the words of Bertrand
Russell: ‘Science is what we know; philosophy is what we don’t know’… ‘Science
is what we can prove to be true; philosophy is what we can’t prove to be
false’.[14] Indeed, when philosophy
achieves consensual truth, it ceases to be philosophy and becomes science. Even
the meta-philosophical understanding I am outlining in this paper could be
accepted as belonging to science, if the critical community of ideas were able
to achieve authentic consensus on its truth.[15]
Another point that we should note is that
the practice of philosophy always presupposes a critical community of ideas,
even if in some cases (like those of Vico, Peirce and Nietzsche) in a
counterfactual sense. A well-known criticism of medieval philosophy is that by
accepting Christian dogmatism as above criticism, it fell short of satisfying
this condition.
Finally, one could object that as a
typically ‘higher-order’ form of investigation, by its very nature
philosophical inquiry is not subject to objective verification and,
consequently, to the kind of objectively grounded consensus achieved by
science. Our response is that this argument may well be overly pessimistic. The
main reason to think so is that support for much theoretical work is not just
directly empirical – through observational verification – but also inter-theoretical.
We can often find this kind of support in the sciences. Take as an example the
Darwinian theory of evolution. Darwin and his contemporaries developed their
ideas without recourse to genetics, since Mendel’s work was unknown to early
evolutionary theorists. Nevertheless, the subsequent rediscovery of genetic
theory by the scientific community provided extremely important
inter-theoretical support for evolutionary theory. Something similar can also
occur within ‘higher-order’ philosophical inquiry.
It was once figuratively suggested that the
problems of philosophy are so intertwined that any one problem can only be
solved when all the other problems have already been solved (Wittgenstein). Far
from being pessimistic, this thesis points to inter-theoretical support.
Insofar as related fields of knowledge move toward science, this provides new
inter-theoretical support for philosophical insights, paving the way for
consensual scientific knowledge.
Proto-scientific versus analytic-conceptual
views
Once we accept these proposals, we see that the
supposedly essential differences in subject matter or even in methods between
philosophy and science are illusory. Take, for example, the still widely believed
conception according to which philosophy is a non-empirical, higher-order
activity of conceptual analysis (its method) intended to make
explicit the structure of our most central concepts and the relations between
them (its subject matter). This view or something alike arose due to the
prominence of the philosophy of language in the first half of the Twentieth
Century.[16] In the second half of
the Twentieth Century, however, the philosophy of language lost its status as
the most productive philosophical field to the philosophy of mind, which
consists largely of empirical speculation.
Moreover, the fact that a given form of
philosophical inquiry has a linguistic-conceptual character does not mean it
cannot develop into a science. This is exemplified by J. L. Austin’s theory of
illocutionary forces. As he himself foresaw, today this theory belongs, in the
form of the theory of speech acts, more to the scientific field of linguistic
than to philosophy. The reason for this is that it has achieved enough
consensual agreement to lose its more plastic role in the uncertain domain of
conjectural thought. Hence, there seems to be no contradiction between
understanding philosophy as proto-science and understanding it as conceptual
analysis, since the latter can be regarded as belonging to the former.[17]
Finally, we can offer a meta-philosophical
refutation of the thesis that the proper object of philosophy is
of a conceptual nature. As W. V. Quine rightly noted, philosophers often need a
particular resource that he called a semantic ascent.[18] A semantic ascent could
also be called a semantic meta-language (a semantic meta-language
is different from a syntactic meta-language: whereas the latter has as
its objects signs and their relationships, the former also has as its objects
meanings, and with them, indirectly, the world as we mean it; in Rudolf
Carnap’s simplified example, instead of saying, ‘Five is not a thing but a
number’, the philosopher prefers to say, ‘“Five” is not a thing-word, but a
number-word’.) However, the call for semantic ascent need not be confusing, for
this is nothing more than a propaedeutic resource, aiming at the
achievement of the kind of conceptual rigor usually demanded by philosophical
arguments. Even if philosophers like Carnap have seen here a proof that the
object of philosophy should be purely linguistic-conceptual, this cannot be
true, as Quine realized, because every sentence of the empirical sciences can
also be meta-linguistically represented in this way. As he noted:
“There are wombats in Tasmania” might be
paraphrased as ‘‘Wombats’ is true to some creatures of Tasmania’, if there were
any point in it; but it does happen that semantic accent is more useful in
philosophical connections.[19]
The upshot of this argument is that philosophy does
not have concepts (e.g., meaning, knowledge, consciousness, substance...) as
its proper subject matter, any more than does science (e.g., genes, molecules
or superstrings), except for reasons of semantic ascent. We can regard the task
of both a theoretical physicist and a philosopher of mind, for example, as not
only to analyse and combine concepts, but also to work toward solving empirical
questions, the latter in much more speculative ways. Hence, all that we can
intend by saying that philosophy is conceptual analysis is to refer to certain
methodological resources, not to an indispensable approach, and still less to
its proper subject matter.
To the question of whether all
philosophy might be an anticipation of science, assuming the wide concept of
science that we have proposed, the only answer is that we have no strong
reason to think otherwise. Moreover, it makes sense to accept this as at least
a normative assumption, since it gives us a ground to progress toward truth.[20]
More Complete Framework
While I have limited myself here to the relationship
between philosophy and science, I think that this is only one aspect of a more
complete framework that places philosophy within a wider perspective. In my
book on the nature of philosophy, I explored to some extent this wider
perspective, conceiving philosophy in general as a derivative cultural
activity.[21] Opera, for example, is
an artistic activity combining plot, poetry and music. In this regard,
philosophy has some similarity to opera. It seems to be a kind of amalgam of
motivations, materials and procedures borrowed from three fundamental cultural
activities: art, religion, and science. These cultural
activities can be represented as forming the corners of a triangle, inside of
which the various philosophical activities find their places. The scientific
corner of the triangle is responsible for the solid, practical, reality-bounded
and truth-oriented aspects of philosophy. The mystical-religious corner is
responsible for the speculative-transcendental, verbally inexpressible element,
usually grounding the comprehensiveness of philosophy, the traditional breadth
of the philosophical quest in its inquiry about the world as a whole and man’s
place in it. The aesthetic-artistic corner, finally, is responsible for the
metaphorical dimension that to different degrees is always unavoidably present
in philosophical discourse. We can use this scheme to classify the various
forms of philosophy. We can locate them in different positions inside the
triangle. At its centre, we can locate philosophies that in a balanced manner
have scientific (truth-oriented), religious (transcendental) and aesthetic
(metaphorical) dimensions. Examples are Plato’s Republic, Descartes’ Meditations,
and Wittgenstein’s Tractatus. However, there are forms of philosophy
located near the scientific corner of the triangle, like Carnap’s Logical
Grammar of Language, Quine’s Word and Object and Austin’s How to
Do Things with Words. There are works near the mystic-religious corner,
like John Scotus’ On the Divisions of Nature and Meister Eckhart’s
treatises. Moreover, there are those near the aesthetic corner, works by
poet-philosophers, like Nietzsche’s Zarathustra and (almost crossing the
border) Novalis’ Hymns to the Night. And there are also works near to
some side of the triangle, like Heidegger’s writings, which can be placed near
the aesthetic-religious side...
We can also use the triangular diagram to classify
entire cultural traditions linking philosophy with a corner of the triangle.
These are the cases of the scientifically-oriented English tradition, the
mystically-oriented German tradition and the belletristically-oriented French
tradition.
Finally, the relationship between the
components is not stable: it is possible to perceive in the sub-domains a wide,
gradual movement from the aesthetic-mystical side of the triangle to the
scientific corner, as an inevitable consequence of the continuous and now
accelerating advancement of science.
[1] Similar principles have continually been proposed over
the entire history of philosophy: Plato’s ideas, Aristotle’s substance,
Plotinus’ Uno, Aquinas’ God, Kant’s noumena, Fichte’s I,
Hegel’s Absolute, Schopenhauer’s Will, Heidegger’s Being
and Wittgenstein’s unsayable, played a similar foundational role.
[2] See Guthrie, W. K. C., A History of Greek
Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1962), vol. 1, pp. 36 f.
[3] A similar procedure is even used by philosophy understood
as conceptual analysis: philosophers usually consider certain data, such
as those found in examples, paradigmatic cases, thought-experiments, etc., in
an effort to find conceptual generalizations adequate to explain a broad set of
conceptual applications.
[4] This phenomenon was already identified by Auguste
Comte, when he considered what he understood as the transition from
mythological to metaphysical thought. For a discussion, see Claudio Costa, The
Philosophical Inquiry: Towards a Global Account (Lanham, MD: University
Press of America, 2002), chap. 4.
[5] According to Hegel, Oriental philosophy never
distinguished itself enough from religion; the reason could be that they also
never had in sight a sufficiently clear model of science and systematic
scientific procedures.
[6] For a proposal to the contrary, see W. V. Quine, ‘A
Letter to Mr. Osterman’, in C. J. Bontempo & S. J. Odell (eds.), The Owl
of Minerva (New York: Free Press, 1975). Quine suggests that the boundaries
between philosophy and science are arbitrary, like those between different
jurisdictions demarcated on a map. If this were true, agreement about whether
new ideas belong more to philosophy or to science would have to be settled by
establishing conventions. But this is not what actually happens in practice.
Usually such agreements arise naturally and immediately.
[7] In some passages, Ludwig Wittgenstein defended the
thesis that philosophy is not constituted by argumentative theoretical
conjectures, but is rather a therapeutic activity of describing how language
really works able to dissolve them as pseudo-problems. See Wittgenstein, Philosophische
Untersuchungen (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1983), sec. 109. However, as many
critics have remarked, neither Wittgenstein nor his followers have come even
remotely close to achieving this aim; for the obscurity and elusiveness of
Wittgenstein’s arguments do not transform them into descriptions. See A. J.
Ayer, Wittgenstein (New York: Pelican Books, 1985), p. 137.
[8] K. R. Popper, ‘Back to the Pre-Socratics’, in his Conjectures
and Refutations (London: Routledge, 1962), p. 138.
[9] Anthony Kenny, Aquinas on Mind, (London:
Routledge, 1993), p. 9.
[10] See K. R. Popper, Conjectures and Refutations,
pp. 339-340.
[11] This is the general thesis on the nature of science
defended by J. M. Ziman in Public Knowledge: An Essay Concerning the Social
Dimension of Science (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1968), chap. 2.
See also H. L. Longino, The Fate of Knowledge (Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press, 2002).
[12] I add the words ‘are able to
be’ because there are many scientific hypotheses that we still do not know how
to prove or disprove, although we have good reasons to believe that we will
eventually be able to test them. Maybe the best known example of this is
superstring theory in physics.
[13] See Jürgen Habermas,
‘Wahrheitstheorien’, in Vorstudien und Ergänzungen zur Theorie des
Kommunikativen Handelns (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1984), pp. 174 f.
[14] Quotes taken from Allan Wood’s postscript to Bertrand
Russell’s My Philosophical Development (London: Routledge, 2004).
[15] One could also object that the proposed
characterization is overly inclusive: There are some theories, e.g., Freudian
psychoanalysis and Marxian dialectical materialism, which are not considered to
be typically philosophical, even though they lack consensual agreement about
their results. I think that the problem here is in part just one of
nomenclature, for Freudianism and Marxism are in fact quite philosophical.
[16] The persistence of this view is underlined by the
essays of Robert Brandom, Barry Stroud, Allen Wood and Karl-Otto Apel,
published by C. P. Ragland & S. Reidt in What is Philosophy? (New
Haven: Yale University Press, 2001). For standard presentations of similar
views, see Michael Dummett, ‘Can Analytical Philosophy be Systematic and Ought
it to Be?’ in his Truth and Other Enigmas (London: Duckworth,
1978), and Ernst Tugendhat ‘Überlegungen über die Methode der Philosophie aus
Analytischer Sicht’, in Philosophische Aufsätze (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp,
1992).
[17] Also J. L. Austin saw no contradiction between
philosophy as proto-science and philosophical analysis, since, on the one hand,
he championed philosophy as conceptual analysis and, on the other hand, he was
an energetic defender of the here-developed view. See the often-quoted passage
in ‘A Plea for Excuses’, in his Philosophical Papers (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1961), p. 232.
[18] W. V. Quine, Word and Object (Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press, 1960), p. 270 f. See also Claudio Costa, The Philosophical
Inquiry, pp. 15 f.
[19] W. V. Quine, Word and Object, pp. 271-272.
[20] There are many other problems that cannot be dealt
with here. For example, how would we locate certain non-central domains, like
those of the philosophy of existence, philosophy of life, or the critique of
culture – which have changeable subjects – in our scheme? (Probably in ways
similar to those in which the historical sciences can be seen as
consensualizable). Another point is that the development of science can itself
create a room for new and previously unforeseen philosophical fields. Consider,
for example, the philosophy of computational science.
[21] Claudio Costa, The Philosophical
Inquiry: Towards a Global Account, chaps. 4-6.
Ótimo texto. Só achei o contraste de cores um tanto cansativo à leitura. Vi algumas indicações de fundo cinza [especificamente RGB(240,240,240)] e texto preto, mas deve haver sugestões mais bem fundamentadas.
ResponderExcluirMais uma vez, parabéns pelo texto. Gostei muito da visão de filosofia como antecipação da ciência como normativa.